A Commentary on the Mystical Philosophy
of
St. John of the
Cross
By
Geoffrey K. Mondello
© Copyright 2000 - 2003
by Geoffrey K. Mondello. All rights reserved.
“In finem nostrae cognitionis Deum
tamquam ignotum cognoscimus” *
St. Thomas Aquinas
Dedication: to Mary, Mother of God
Mysticism is a phenomenon fraught
with nuances, both linguistic and metaphysical. The Metaphysics,
consequently, as a philosophic work, presumes to address issues of a
nature less than congenial to the universe of ordinary discourse. Philosophy, to
be sure, demands a rigorous language, a syntax, if you will, that is subtly
antagonistic to the fluid and sometimes extremely volatile concepts intrinsic to
the phenomenon of the mystical experience.
The austere language that philosophy arrogates to itself is sometimes too
rigid a probe to uncover, reveal, the subtle and often delicate complexities
that inevitably arise in a careful examination of mysticism; hence a
sometimes involuted terminology will be encountered in our fragile attempt to
render
linguistic
what merely verges on becoming intelligible. I have, to the best
of my ability, limited this proliferation of abstruse language applied to an
already abstruse subject. I have attempted to keep neologisms to a minimal, but
have not blenched from employing them when my own linguistic resources are
exhausted. Notwithstanding the difficulties inevitably encountered in language,
I have endeavored in this work not simply to clarify what is obscure, but to
address what is unique and compelling in this type of experience, an experience
that has challenged philosophy for something more than a paranthetical account,
an account, more often than not, much too eager to either dismiss this
phenomenon, or to relegate it to psychology through its own failure to provide
it with an adequate epistemological framework. Philosophy, in a word, has not
yet coherently responded to this challenge. I am not satisfied that I have done
so to the extent required, and many readers will no doubt concur with my
assessment. Nevertheless it is a beginning of sorts, and if it provokes more questions than it answers it will at
least have served to rehabilitate the philosophical arrogance that has been too
ready to dismiss what it finds uncongenial. Hence
the impetus of this work.
WHAT THIS BOOK IS, AND WHAT IT IS
NOT
Although this book is
subtitled a “Commentary on the Mystical Philosophy of St. John of the
Cross” it will become immediately evident to the reader that, both in scope and
purpose, it is a commentary structured around some very specific epistemological
issues. In particular, it is concerned with exploring the possibility of
articulating a coherent theory of knowledge that is implicit, or perhaps
better yet, latent, in the writings of St. John. I say latent because the
theory itself is really rather an aside to the very practical issues raised by
St. John in the writing of his several treatises on mystical experience. Anyone
who has read St. John will undoubtedly agree that his approach to the subject is
more programmatic than analytical, at least in any contemporary sense. As such,
the aperture, if you will, of our focus must go beyond the hard and fast
boundaries that might otherwise define our expectations of a commentary dealing
strictly with the theological complexities that inevitably arise upon a close
reading of St. John of the Cross.
In
one sense, of course, the works of St. John are a commentary unto themselves,
and while this may simplify matters in one respect, it considerably complicates
them in another. The verse by verse interpretation which St. John himself offers
is, obviously, the first and most apparent level, a level where St. John
provides us with an often detailed explication of the meaning behind his
extremely subtle poetic utterances. This meaning, both in scope and intention,
is purely theological. Our own purposes within this book, however, are not: they
are, by and large, epistemological. And this is where the issue becomes a
bit more complex.
A commentary of the type
proposed, it seemed to me, must take this first level of meaning fundamentally
rooted in theology, to the next and less apparent level of meaning
radicated in epistemology; in other words, one that specifically emerges
from an epistemological criticism of the first level. In this sense it is a
striving for what might be called hyper-textual meaning, a meaning always latent
within, but often suppressed by, the complexities of the text itself. At the
same time it is also a striving for contextual coherence. In any critical
encounter between mysticism and epistemology, it is the demand for coherence,
and not credence, which inevitably predominates. The often attenuated and
sometimes conflicting principles that have largely become part and parcel of
mystical theology remain no more than mere speculations until coherence is
demonstrated to obtain not merely between the principles themselves within their
own legitimate province (theology), but more importantly, between these
principles and the canons of reason to which epistemology presumes to hold them
accountable. Questions likely to emerge from such an encounter are of the
following sort: “Do the implications of St. John’s often abstruse statements
actually hold up under epistemological criticism?” “Does a fully explicated
meaning which accords with accepted theological principles, also accord
with accepted epistemological principles?” In a word, do the theological
principles have adequate epistemological credentials?
For
this reason, and others, I thought it best to entitle this work a commentary
dealing with St. John’s mystical “philosophy”, and not his “theology” as
such, for a much broader range of issues, especially epistemological issues, are
clearly necessary to the scope of this type of endeavor, issues which a purely
theological analysis would otherwise, and legitimately, exclude. The reason I
have done so will, I think, become apparent early on. I have essentially
attempted to bring three related issues into focus within the present work: the
phenomenon that we have come to understand as the “mystical experience”, the
metaphysics ostensibly underlying it, and the consonance, if any, obtaining
between the two when viewed under the objective lens of epistemology. The real
question of the work, then, can be summarized simply as this: “Is the
mystical experience epistemologically coherent?” There are, of course,
inevitably a subset of questions latent within this: “Are the conclusions drawn
from St. John’s arguments consistent with the premises implied?” “Do the
premises and conclusions themselves coherently accord with the metaphysics?” In
short, is the mystical experience described by St. John of the Cross at the very
least epistemologically credible?
But
why St. John of the Cross? Why not Eckhardt, Gerson, or Tauler? Even the
briefest historical survey of the great Western Christian Mystics offers,
especially in the way of speculative mysticism, a wide variety of other and
perhaps better known candidates. The reason that I have chosen St. John is
simply this: the works of St. John of the Cross, particularly the Ascent of
Mount Carmel and The Dark Night of the Soul, stand, I think, as the
culmination of the Western tradition of mysticism. Every other representative of
this tradition is either in some way defective or deficient in articulating what
has come to be accepted as orthodox doctrine in mystical theology.
It is, in retrospect, no small token to the depth and scope of his writings that
St. John was declared the first “Doctor of Mystical Theology” within the Roman
Catholic Church. Much of this remains to be discussed later.
As a
final note in the way of explaining what this book is, or at least
endeavors to be, I think it necessary to say something briefly about the term
“mysticism” itself. It has always appeared to me somewhat regrettable that the
term “mysticism” is used to define what would really be more accurately
described as “contemplative theology”. With the term “mystical” we are likely to
conjure up a good deal that is either unrelated, or deeply inimical to the
contemplative theology that comes to us in the writings of the great Christian
mystics. Mystical theology, in one of its typical paradoxes, is essentially a
rational enterprise despite the fact that the mystical experience itself
is not. While basically a practical undertaking, in presuming to set forth
reasons for this practical task, it is at least implicitly a rational
justification as well. And it is precisely this rational aspect of the mystical
experience that is the focus of this book.
On the other hand, it is
equally important to the reader to understand what this book is not. This
book is not a compendium. While it carefully attempts to chronologically
accompany the text where possible, it does not blench from a departure where an
examination of concurrent issues is warranted. Some will undoubtedly find this
vexing. And while it adverts to the Mystical Tradition in general, a tradition
out of which the thought of St. John very clearly emerges, it does not presume
to exhaustively treat of the many notable figures who have contributed to this
long-standing tradition. Deidre Carabine’s “The Unknown God: Negative
Theology in the Platonic Tradition: Plato to Eriugena”
1, I suggest, would be much more suitable to this purpose.
The goal of this book is unabashedly epistemological. Neither do I presume the
reader to be intimately acquainted with Thomism as such, from which many of the
metaphysical doctrines articulated by St. John unquestionably derive. For the
sake of clarity, and the convenience of the reader, I have endeavored to
reiterate them when necessary, providing pertinent documentation should the
reader wish to explore the issue further. As dearly as I wish this work to be
all things to all people, I have settled for the more modest goal of providing
epistemological perspective on the sometimes fluid, sometimes volatile, but
always paradoxical issues that mysticism perpetually engenders.
* (In Boetium de Trinitate, q. 1, a.
2, ad 1um)
1 Peeters Press,
Louvain (W.B. Eerdmans) 1995
Preface to the Philosophy of St. John of
the Cross
The Search for Coherence
If there is one unifying feature that appears to bind the
great diversity of philosophic thought as it has occurred throughout history, it
may well be found in the search for coherence. While the passionate and
resolute pursuit of truth is certainly more exalted, it has for some time
suffered rather badly, and for good reason has been denigrated as the pure
impulse behind every philosophical system. The dispassionate search for
coherence, on the other hand, has been, and is likely to remain, fundamental to
all good philosophy. It is no less the driving force behind the great
Platonic Dialogues, or Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, than
Kant’s abstruse Critique of Pure Reason or Hegel’s involuted
Logic. On every philosophical frontier we essentially encounter
problematics that demand explanation because they confront us as facts.
What is more, these intractable, often vexing elements of experience do not
always readily lend themselves to understanding, or if they do, it is sometimes
upon terms not entirely of our own making. Such occurrences invite inquiry,
challenge us to coherently respond to them, and even in the face of indifference
resolutely refuse to be turned aside. They defy us, and therefore
challenge us. By their persistent recurrence, they effectively demand of
us accountability; demand, in fact, to be coherently incorporated
into that philosophic purview toward which all inquiry inexorably moves as
toward a universal comprehending every fact.
However elusive this
pursuit may be, the impulse which motivates us to exact from experience
the epistemological tribute which coherence demands, remains the same always and
everywhere: the pursuit of understanding. To leave unexplained --- or
worse yet --- to ignore any recurrent element in experience simply
because it proves either inconvenient or recalcitrant, is not merely bad
philosophy; it is contradictory to the philosophic impulse itself, an impulse
which not merely derives from, but thrives within, the fertile matrix of
inquiry.
If this indeed is so, it
is particularly apropos of a study of arguably the single greatest --- certainly
the most voluble and articulate --- figure in the Western tradition of
mysticism, St. John of the Cross (1542-1591). Mystical experience, despite its
many cultural and often conflicting interpretations, remains undeniably a fact
of experience. This alone is sufficient warrant for examination. Its
credentials lie in the repeated, which is to say, the historical
experiences of men and women, and philosophy essentially demands no more of the
subject of its review.
It is, however, equally
clear that such an investigation suffers a regrettably persistent, if popular
handicap: the general consensus seems to be, prior to any real critical
reflection on the matter, that in and of itself mysticism is something entirely
and irredeemably irrational, and inasmuch as it is beyond reason it is
beyond the legitimate scope of rational inquiry altogether. Indeed, apart from
the possibility of what appear to be otherwise solipsistic utterances meaningful
only among the mystics themselves, it really has nothing to recommend itself to
the type of inquiry to which other and decidedly less refractory experiences
legitimately lend themselves. This is to be much mistaken. It is precisely this
fundamental and pervasive misconception about mysticism that remains, I
think, the chief obstacle
to a study of mystical philosophy in its own right, the credibility of which, as
a consequence, has suffered unnecessarily.
But there is more to the
problem we confront at the outset than simply this. Semantics has played no
small part in contributing to the confusion that surrounds the very term itself.
As William James astutely observed:
“The words
“mysticism” and “mystical” are often used as terms of mere reproach, to throw at
any opinion which we regard as vague and vast and sentimental, and without a
base in either facts or logic. For some writers a “mystic” is any person who
believes in thought-transference, or spirit return. Employed in this way the
word has little value.”1
As a consequence, the
term “mysticism” has come to acquire a kind of pseudo-metaphysical connotation,
or perhaps better yet, an esoteric pathos of the most reprehensible sort
--- evoking, as it does, a type of vaguee intellectual empathy to which nothing
in any sense coherent and meaningful corresponds. This essential
misunderstanding of mysticism, however, is quickly dispelled upon a close
examination of the works of St. John of the Cross: immediately we confront
facticity and discern logic; facticity and logic so compelling, in fact, that a
philosophy of mysticism may well offer a unique contribution to
epistemology itself. To wit, In Part II of our commentary we shall
examine, among other things, the possibility of a type of experience in which
the redoubtable Problem of Induction --- first introduced by the
18th century Scottish philosopher David Hume --- and a thorn in the
side of philosophy ever since --- fails to obtain. This of itself would be no
small recompense for our efforts given the magnitude of this problem to which
philosophy, in one form or another, has attempted to respond since the
publication of Hume’s Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding in 1740. In
short, we find reason in the mystical philosophy of St. John of the Cross,
coherence and logic. Indeed, we find that, externally considered, the mystical
experience is a profoundly rational experience --- and it is this
discovery, sweeping aside many long-borne misconceptions about mysticism which,
if justification at all is required, suffices to justify an epistemology of
mysticism.
To be sure, there are
central elements in the mystical experience essentially inaccessible to reason.
St. Thomas Aquinas perhaps summed it up best in the terse statement, “In
finem nostrae cognitionis Deum tamquam ignotum cognoscimus.” 2
It is this
unknowing, this first and most fundamental principle of the metaphysics
of mysticism which, in our examination, we shall find to assume profoundly
rational dimensions in the mystical philosophy of St. John of the
Cross.
Geoffrey K.
Mondello
1 Varieties of Religious Experience, Lect.
16
2 In the end, we know God as unknown
Foreword
In this short commentary on the two principle works of St.
John of the Cross --- the Ascent of Mount Carmel and the Dark Night of
the Soul --- we will, as I stated earlier, be primarily concerned with
examining the possibilities of developing a coherent mystical epistemology, that
is to say, a theory of knowledge relative to the mystical experience in
which the rational elements of this unique experience will become explicit to
us, and so enable us to usher at least some very crucial aspects of this
phenomenon into the arena of rational discourse. Certainly, this will not make
mystics of us. Indeed, this understanding itself is by no means propadeutic to
the mystical experience, as we shall later see; that is to say, an understanding
of the metaphysical principles underlying the mystical experience is not
requisite in the way that, say, an understanding of the relation between
rational numbers is presupposed in the exercise of pure mathematics. The mystic,
unlike the mathematician, may in fact dispense with such an understanding
altogether.
This type of
understanding, however, is requisite to the inquiring mind, which is to
say, to those of us standing, as it were, outside, peering in through the
sometimes-obfuscated lens of rational inquiry. We can, however, only achieve
this through carefully examining the various and sometimes involuted arguments
which St. John articulates in the development of what must be understood as his
mystical philosophy; a philosophy which only gradually, even reluctantly,
emerges from the text. Our inquiry, then, essentially boils down to an
examination of certain rational features of the mystical experience which lend
themselves to the possibility of being so organized as to constitute something
systematic enough to be incorporated into what we have come to understand as
epistemology. And this, of course, presumes order, sense, meaning and logic. One
surprising consequence of our analysis, in short, will be the disclosure of the
mystical experience not as antipodal to reason (as some have supposed), but as
profoundly consonant with it. However, this reason we seek in St. John’s
account is, we hasten to add, and for reasons that we shall later explain,
implicit only; from the outset it often requires patient analysis, but
the results will be no less, --- in fact, all the more--- compelling for the
effort.
Given the broad and
inevitable complexity of the issues involved, it appeared to me that the best
way to proceed in this type of examination would be through an analysis of the
central moments in the movement to mystical union as they logically occur
in the two texts. Where there is logical or chronological order to begin with,
it seemed to me best to construct an analysis parallel to the already existing
continuum. Not only should this help us in a comparative analysis of the text,
but it serves to constrain us to the text as well --- while at the same time
allowing us the necessary latitude to extrapolate from it in an attempt to
construct an epistemological analysis of our own. In doing so we will find
ourselves moving from an examination of those factors external to the mystical
experience and generally spoken of in terms of predisposition, to those
elements more or less explicitly involved in the actual mystical experience
itself and in turn generally spoken of in terms of union. Our purpose,
then, is to examine the normative, as well as the descriptive elements in St.
John’s account. To do this, it is vital for us to provide the often-isolated
elements which occur in the text with a coherent epistemological framework. This
in turn requires us to draw out the logical implications of his statements,
examine their premises, however suppressed, elicit their conclusions, however
latent, and in the end attempt to demonstrate the coherence, if any, which
obtains between them.
A certain antagonism with
the text is inevitable. These are fertile but not necessarily congenial grounds
for purely philosophical inquiry. There are, for example, certain tacit
assumptions, both theological and philosophical in nature, to which St. John
often adverts; assumptions, more often than not, in the form of suppressed
theses which, if we are at all to succeed in our examination, must be
lifted from the text as so many copulas to the intelligibility or our
account. We must endeavor, then, to show not merely that certain
experiences or consequences follow any given moment in the account, but
why they follow logically (that is to say, deductively, or necessarily)
from the given moments. As we examine St. John’s arguments in greater detail, we
come to realize that it is not so much an antagonism that we contend with in the
account as it is a recalcitrance encountered within the text itself: that
certain later statements and arguments essentially derive from earlier
statements and arguments is not always clear in the writings of St. John. It
remains for us to attempt to render these connections explicit, to endeavor to
demonstrate their logical coherence, and to organize them into something
systematic if we hope to succeed in articulating an epistemology of mysticism
--- at least St. John’s mysticism. The uultimate aim of this commentary, in the
end, is to give philosophic form to St. John’s arguments, in effect to develop a
coherent philosophy of mysticism, especially in light of the
epistemological dimensions suggested within it.
St. John’s works can be
divided into three logical moments: Predisposition, Transition,
and Union. Part I of the Commentary, which I have entitled the
Presuppositions is principally concerned with the moment of
predisposition, that is to say, with the merely mechanical features of
mysticism which the latter two moments presuppose. It forms the foundation upon
which the mystical momentum builds and in virtue of which much of the subsequent
mystical experience is explainable. Its principal feature, we will find, is the
apophatic way, better known as the Via Negativa (the Way of Negation, or
the Negative Way) in all its mechanical aspects upon which the entire
metaphysical infrastructure of mysticism depends. Detailed discussion of this
central feature in mystical philosophy is dealt with in Part II of this
commentary where it will be examined in detail.
Working from the various
principles elicited from St. John’s foundational work, the Ascent of Mount
Carmel, Part II, entitled the Metaphysics, is an attempt to
relate the evolving mystical experiences to these principles (the via
negativa, notions of participation, proximity, proportion, contrariety,
etc.) in order to demonstrate the latter to be, in fact, the logical
consequences of the former. It is an attempt to show that, given certain
statements concerning the function of these principles, other statements about
certain unique types of experience (essentially states-of-being) not just
follow, but necessarily, that is to say, deductively, follow. But
at the same time we must also come to terms with the limitations inherent in the
kind of books St. John was writing; books addressing issues vital to a
distinct group of readers (issues that we shall discuss later in Part II
). As a result, deductive relations which do in fact obtain between the
various elements in his philosophy are often obscure to the casual reader.
Suffice it to say at this point that St. John did not understand himself to be
writing an enchiridion on mystical theology replete with deductive schematics to
be later analyzed by, and subsequently vex, systematic theologians. Deductive
relations do in fact exist, but because of this literary limitation, they must
be elicited through careful reading if we are to arrive at that philosophic
coherence we strive for in the works of St. John; a coherence that, in fact, is
always latent, even in his most abstruse writings.
In the way of
explanation, I should like to point out that I have omitted treatment of St.
John’s last two works --- the Spiritual Canticle and the Living Flame
of Love --- not as an oversight, but simply because, for our own purposes,
the pertinent material found in these two treatises derives from, and are
largely more elaborate iterations of, the first two principal works in which
all the elements in his philosophy are contained in much greater detail.
As a final note, an addendum in the form of a prolepsis follows the commentary
proper. Within it, various objections posed by skepticism, psychology, and
orthodoxy, are briefly considered and answered in light of our examination.
This, in turn, is followed by a brief biographical sketch, and an overview of
the mystical tradition culminating in the thought of St.
John.
The abbreviations used in
this commentary are as follows:
AMC : Ascent of Mount Carmel
DNS : Dark Night of the Soul
SC : Spiritual Canticle
LFL : Living Flame of Love
ST : Summa Theologica (St. Thomas
Aquinas)
Documentary references
are based upon the translation of St. John’s works by E. Allison Peers:
Ascent of Mount Carmel, Dark Night of the Soul, Living Flame of
Love, and Spiritual Canticle, Image Books, Doubleday & Co.,
Garden City, NY, 1958, 1959, 1961, and 1962.
Scriptural references
are, unless noted otherwise, taken from The Jerusalem Bible, Doubleday
& Co., Garden City, New York, Copyright 1966
An Introduction to the Philosophy of St.
John of the Cross
The Epistemological Paradox: the Knower, Unknowing, and the
Unknown
Any study of St. John’s mystical philosophy must first
come to terms with the nature of mystical theology itself; what its object is,
what its limits are: in short, what particular universe of discourse we are
addressing in our attempt to understand the mystical experience described by St.
John of the Cross. A good definition, it appears to me, must be broad enough to
subsume the many interpretations we encounter outside any specific tradition.
The advantages of this are at once obvious, for such an approach, broadly
chronological in its purview, provides us with a much needed sense of historical
continuity inasmuch as many of the doctrines found in the writings of St. John
have very clear historical antecedents that are not, in fact, rooted in
Christianity at all. Some precede it. Indeed, some are deeply inimical to it. On
the other hand, it is equally clear that our definition must be sufficiently
specific to the tradition to which St. John so clearly belongs and in light of
which alone his mystical doctrine becomes coherent. One extremely useful
definition, a definition embracing what is both specific and general, would
construe mystical theology as essentially the consummate theology. Why
consummate? Because it is the cognitive apex of an otherwise largely
speculative theological enterprise. Mystical theology, in short, is concerned
with the direct intuition –
-- experience, if you
will --- of God 1; the immediate and unmodified apprehension of the
Absolute through what has come to be understood as ‘unio mystica’, or
mystical union.
Perhaps the clearest,
certainly the most concise, definition offered is, I think, summarized in the
words of the great fourteenth century theologian and mystic, Jean
Gerson:
“Theologia
mystica est experimentalis cognitio habita de Deo per amoris unitivi complexum”
2
Natural Theology, by
contrast, concerns itself exclusively with the knowledge of God arrived at
through natural, or discursive reason: that is to say, in Natural Theology an
understanding of God is abstractly achieved through a rational process much in
the way that a logical argument is constructed through a sorites. St. Anselm’s
famous ‘Ontological Argument’ is a fine example of this type of
theological reasoning. The God it broaches upon, however, remains as abstract as
the syllogistic reasoning that deduced him, and, practically speaking, few
people undergo conversion experiences as a result of this line of reasoning,
however impeccable.
Dogmatic Theology, on the
other hand, takes a somewhat different tack: it is primarily concerned with the
knowledge of God obtained through divine revelation principally embodied in
Sacred Scripture, and has come to assume a rather monolithic architectonic
through a long-standing and erudite tradition of Patristic exegesis. The force
of reason and the appeal to authority (Scriptural, patristic, and philosophical)
which typically characterizes dogmatic theology is a powerful combination, a
combination so effective, in fact, that it is arguably the single most vital
element in any individual’s --- including the mystic’s --- orthodox religious
formation. It is, in a sense, the springboard off which the mystic leaps into
less certain waters. St. Thomas Aquinas is an eminent example of
both disciplines,
artfully incorporating elements of the Natural and the Dogmatic into that
remarkable synthesis culminating in his Summa Theologica, considered by
many to be the greatest theological treatise ever
written.
Reason as Propadeutic:
the Ex Hypothesi
Mystical theology
approaches God quite differently. Its path lies neither through the narrow
corridors of reason, nor through the rigid architectonics of dogmatic exegesis.
It either leaps off at the point where the scholar is left stammering, or may
prescind altogether from the cumbersome intellectual impedimenta that becomes
effectively superfluous in the ecstatic momentum that impels the soul to union
with God. This, of course, is to disparage neither reason nor dogma. Each in
measure is an indispensable tributary to the depth of that inexorable movement
toward God, as we shall later see. It remains, nevertheless, that even a scholar
of the caliber of St. Thomas Aquinas had subsequently come to view all that he
had written, and this was considerable to say the least, as “so much straw” in
light of the direct experience of God which he briefly encountered
in a moment of ecstatic union. So overwhelming, so all embracing, so utterly
definitive was this experience that St. Thomas immediately ceased
writing.
Shall we then toss aside
the Summa? It is clear that St. John did not. Neither, in fact, did
Tauler, Suso, or Eckhardt. And for good reason: Mystical Theology, properly
understood, neither compromises nor invalidates its Rational and Dogmatic
counterparts. Rather, it surpasses them in the way that the act of
seeing surpasses the most definitive description of sight. The
description itself remains true; it is entirely accurate inasmuch as words
signify, and in signifying attempt to communicate, what is essentially an
experience. But the disproportion between the experience itself
and any description subsequent to it remains nearly irreconcilable. To one who
is color-deficient (to carry the analogy a little further) and who has never
seen the color purple, the most precise and detailed description of this
absolutely unique chromatic phenomenon called purple, even when coupled with
appeals to extrapolate from colors with which one is familiar, yields at
best only a vague conception, and in the end brings that person no closer to the
experience of the color itself. In short, we must come to terms with
limitations inherent in language, especially descriptive language; limitations
that are radicated in shared experiences outside of which the power of
language reaches a cognitive terminus. No more can meaningfully be said. And
this is precisely the plight of the mystic, and, therefore, that of mystical
theology itself.
But let us take this a
little further. While each of the several branches of theology take God as their
cognitive object, something of a sense of theological fragmentation inevitably
occurs. Somehow a universal and unitary comprehension of God is not so much
lost, as never quite achieved. If a synthesis is obtained, however comprehensive
and integrated, it only leaves us in the vestibule of the Divine, and the
antechamber is yet obscure and unoccupied. Each discipline within theology, in
other words, is possessed of quite definite and intrinsic limitations in
addressing the Absolute; insuperable limitations, we shall find, that derive
from a metaphysical finitude inextricably bound up with nature as
subsuming under itself everything created in opposition to the Uncreated
Absolute. Each approach to God is irremediably limited; hence the extent of the
possibility of its cognition of God is determined a priori. In other
words, the knowledge of God we acquire through Natural Theology is mediated, and
therefore limited, by reason. It addresses the inexhaustible Absolute
strictly as the object of rational inquiry. On the other hand, the knowledge
acquired through Dogmatic Theology, while not prescinding from reason, is
nevertheless itself equally mediated, and therefore limited, by
revelation, pertaining to the infinite God only insofar as he has
revealed some aspect of his infinite being in finite human history. Our
acquaintance, our cognition of God through reason and revelation, then, is
necessarily incomplete. The contributions of traditional theological disciplines
are not, for that reason, understood to be irrelevant. To the contrary, St. John
was well schooled in scholasticism at the University of Salamanca and relies a
great deal on Dogmatic Theology as a propadeutic to the mystical journey. As a
journey of faith, it is Dogmatic Theology which enables us to the reach the
vestibule safely; it is the compass whose unchanging ordinals, divinely
illumined, give us bearing in the dark night of the soul. Constituting, as it
does, an index of truth in the form of dogmatic certainties, it provides
essential definition in the face of gathering obscurity, and so disabuses us of
error, which St. John sees as constituting one of the principal
impediments to the soul in its journey to union with God.
This is not to say, as we
suggested earlier, that the mystic must first thoroughly acquaint himself with
Dogmatic Theology if he hopes to arrive at union with God. God of his own
predilection brings whom he wills to this exalted state, and makes no inquiries
into the mystic’s theological credentials. However, the likelihood of
achieving this state, given the many obstacles likely to be encountered on the
journey, will in some measure be commensurable with the mystic’s certain
grounding in fundamental dogmatic issues. One’s prospect of attaining to
ecstatic union with the One, Most Holy, and Uncreated Absolute is considerably
diminished if ones conception of God is grossly and fundamentally divergent from
the Divine reality toward which one aspires. It is not unlike one attempting to
find the solution to some complex algorithm by sorting out the entrails of owls.
Some measure of correspondence is presumed between the objective and the means,
and it is Dogmatic Theology which ensures this, not by delimiting the
inexhaustible Absolute, but in defining certain irrefragable aspects of it.
Unfortunately, or fortunately, the egalitarianism so dear to the human heart is
shattered as much on the frontiers of heaven as it is on the formulas of
mathematics. However dearly we would that two and two equal five, we strive for
it in vain, or hold to a fiction, but never quite achieve true mathematics. This
would appear to be no less true of the quest for God. However dearly we would
that God conform his being to our wishes, our sensitivities, our inclinations,
even our mistaken beliefs, the invincible reality will continue to elude us
until we are prepared to settle upon terms not entirely of our own making and
more in accord with the reality we pursue. Dogmatic Theology simply makes some
of these terms clear.
A good deal more,
however, must be said about reason. To begin with, inasmuch as reason
mediates our approach to God, in so doing, it simultaneously
modifies our perception of the Absolute; our apprehension of God is not,
without stringent qualification, entirely veridical. Certainly it is not a
perception of God in the plenitude of his being. Rather, it is a perception
modified by, in being accommodated to, reason and revelation. God is essentially
construed as a being upon whom rational categories are imposed, and who in
himself, defined as infinite, transcends these intrinsically limiting and
modifying categories. The nature of God, in other words, infinitely exceeds the
narrow architectonics of reason, and while it is clearly arguable that the
intelligibility of God requires at least a minimal availability to reason, it is
no less clear that the divine essence is incapable of being exhausted by reason
alone, for the rational availability of God is only, merely, one dimension of
God’s infinite being. And this is really to say that we understand by God
something more than the merely rational.
Transcendence through Immanence?
What emerges from all
this is perhaps the most interesting question of all: is there in fact, beside
reason, perhaps even above reason, some alternative mode of cognition which must
be admitted into our epistemological account? One which, while not abrogating
reason, somehow surpasses reason, much in the way that, to advert to our
earlier analogy, seeing infinitely exceeds the description of
sight --- while in no way invalidating the description
itself?
At the same time it is
important to recognize that the deliverances of reason, however limited,
nevertheless remain authentic. What reason predicates of God is not abolished in
mystical experiences; such experiences, rather, are found to corroborate them.
It is vitally important for us to understand this, for it means that those of us
who stand outside this unique experience nevertheless have an understanding of
God that is not in the end merely one of so many superlative fictions. In some
albeit limited way our conception of God actually corresponds to the reality of
the Absolute. Were this not so, the Christian understanding of salvific history
would otherwise be emptied of meaning and our relationship to God would not so
much be a matter of disproportion as one of utter incommensurability. In
other words, if God cannot be known, in some sense meaningfully understood,
then, practically speaking, he simply does not exist for us; no more so than we
may hold anything to exist in any meaningful way about which we know
nothing.
Nevertheless, it is
precisely this genuine perceptual capacity within the mystic which undergoes a
profound transformation in ecstatic union; a transformation in which the
encounter with God is more accurately described as an intuition, that is,
an immediate experience, one unconditioned by reason and sensibility ---
and if unconditioned, then totally unmodified. It is, for the mystic, a
supernatural apprehension of God as he is in
himself.
This claim, perhaps the
most controversial, certainly the most central aspect of mystical experience,
inevitably invites contradiction, and for good reason. Since Immanuel Kant, the
notion of a perception of anything in itself (an sich) --- the
noumenal insight into unmodified being --- has become epistemologically
problematic. According to this line of reasoning, the presumably pristine data
presented us in any possible encounter is modified in the very act of perceiving
it: our perception, in other words, invests data with logical and aesthetic
qualities that do not inhere in the data themselves, but which are present as a
condition to the very possibility of their being perceived at all. And
these qualities themselves are present as a result of our own epistemological
activity which first conditions data in order to accommodate it. We can,
therefore, never know anything in and of itself. We are acquainted merely
with the phenomenal appearance, but never the noumenal substance, the unmodified
reality forever concealed beneath a phenomenal framework of our own
epistemological making.3
Reason and sensibility,
then, having largely defined the terms (and subsequently the limits) of any
epistemological analysis since Kant, must in some way be cogently accounted for
in mystical theology as well. At the same time, by its very nature mystical
theology cannot be arbitrarily constrained to the scope limiting other types of
epistemological pursuits since its objective is understood at the outset to
transcend the phenomena legitimate to them. This, however, is latitude, not
license; a latitude which must nevertheless hold to terms mutually recognized in
any competent epistemological endeavor whatever. The problem is that the terms
themselves become much more fluid precisely at the point where epistemology and
mystical theology converge. Consequently, there is perpetual tension in this
convergence, a tension fraught with misunderstanding. What is vitally needed
from the outset, then, is a clarification of terms. And what I am suggesting is
that much of the confusion surrounding mysticism itself results from the fact
that mystical theology has, at this point, essentially redefined the
terms.
It is equally important
to understand that it has done so not by abolishing these terms, but by
prescinding from them. Mystical theology does not contradict the terms which
largely define other types of epistemological pursuits. It recognizes that they
are, in fact, entirely valid within their own legitimate province. But while it
does not contradict these terms, it is nevertheless ineluctably
constrained to negate them. And this is quite another matter altogether.
Recognizing that an epistemological analysis defined solely in terms of reason
and sensibility is inherently inadequate to its own unique enterprise,
mystical theology has not abrogated the terms --- it has simply redefined
them. And this is really the critical point of our departure. In
redefining the terms it redefines the epistemological enterprise itself which is
no longer understood so much as attaining to knowledge as attaining to
being. Its objective is not the acquisition of an end, but a
participating in it. Participation, in a word, becomes not simply
an alternative to knowledge --- it altogether supersedes it. At best, “knowing”,
to the mystic, is penultimate to “being”. In a larger sense, within the concept
of participation the implicit distinction between the “knower” and the “known”,
a distinction otherwise constituting one of the most fundamental epistemological
premises 4, becomes effectively superfluous. In the state of ecstatic
union, the “knower” and the “known” are ultimately understood, in a carefully
qualified sense, to in fact be one.
So crucial is the concept
of participation, in fact, that it is fundamental to understanding the very
possibility itself of the type of absolutely unconditioned and therefore
veridical perception which the mystics claim to possess in ecstatic union. The
epistemological margin between subject and object, the knower and the known,
which gradually evanesces until it is totally transcended in the moment of the
mystic’s apotheosis in God, only becomes coherent through an understanding of a
metaphysics radicated in the notion of participation.
The Doctrine of Original Sin as an Epistemological
Tangent
But we are getting ahead
of ourselves. At this point it is probably best to address some of the other
fundamental issues that inevitably influence our understanding of mysticism
before venturing further into our account. One such issue concerns the doctrine
of Original Sin. According to this doctrine, mankind in its first state of
innocence (moral impeccability) enjoyed familiarity with God. This innocence,
however, is held to have been lost, together with the intuitive apprehension of
God which attended it, through an act of Original Sin. The consequences of this
breach not only profoundly altered and vitiated our relationship with God, but
our very cognition of the Divinity is held to have been subsequently impaired as
well. From this perspective the task of mystical theology, at least implicitly,
must be understood as restorative: somehow man must once again be
reconciled to that state
of innocence in which his relationship to God is once again consonant and,
consequently, his apprehension of God immediate.
The return, so to speak,
to this original state can only be achieved, or perhaps better yet, approximated
by the mystic through what is essentially a purgative process in which the
mystic strives to center consciousness entirely and exclusively upon God. This
process, we will later see, basically consists in the categorical negation of
all that is not God, both externally according to the senses, and
internally according to the spirit. Mystical theology therefore employs a
negative epistemology, proceeding through what is known as the via
negativa (or the negative way) to arrive at a veridical cognition of
God.
At the same time, we
observe in the mystic an epistemological striving for centricity: as a result of
our fallen state, our relationship to God has become, as it were, eccentric.
That is to say, God is no longer central to ordinary consciousness, but rather
exists on its periphery as only one of a multiplicity of notions competing to
varying degrees for primacy in consciousness, and often entertained
simultaneously --- if indeed God occupies a place in consciousness at all. As
long as a plurality of necessarily discrete, and often competing notions
alternately occupy consciousness, just so long is man’s relationship to God
eccentric. And it is precisely this type of epistemological diffusion which, for
St. John, engenders what he calls “contrariety” to God in the soul. It is
essentially a diffusion among incommensurable categories. If the soul, then, is
to reestablish itself in its original state of consonance with God, it must in
some way succeed in negating this plurality.
Let us attempt to sort
this out for a moment. Assuming the intentionality of consciousness, that is to
say, that consciousness itself presupposes as a condition of consciousness, an
object or notion of which it is conscious --- the soul in having but
one item of consciousness is exclusively united with this object as the
sole condition of its epistemological activity. We do not “know”
in vacuo: the act of knowing, however vigorously abstracted and
reduced, presupposes something being concurrently known, even if only the
knower himself. Indeed, we understand the state of not knowing anything at all
as unconsciousness. Consciousness, then, is not some dogmatically
independent noesis apart from the data through which it is actualized. In this
rigorously exclusive state of focused awareness, consciousness is contingent
upon its solitary object --- it is, in fact, united with this object as a
consciousness this object. And it is one hand, and the activity of God on
the other. Given this dialectic, the soul appears to be --- despite the fall ---
yet latently disposed to that authentic cognition of God which marked the
ordinary awareness of man prior to his fall from the state of original justice.
So we find that the very possibility of mystical experience presupposes the soul
to be at least implicitly disposed to a veridical cognition of God. When
actualized, when rendered explicit in the mystical experience, this cognition
is, as it were, a dimension of the state of innocence re-achieved. This does
not, however, mean that man is therefore rendered impeccable, as the Illuminists
believed: while epistemological consonance may be reestablished precisely this
type of epistemological centricity toward which the via negativa moves.
The via negativa, then, must be viewed not simply as inseparable from,
but as intrinsic to the epistemological predisposition to mystical union,
for it ultimately enables an epistemological union of the soul as the
possibility, and God as the condition of any subsequent state of
consciousness.
In the state of mystical
union, however, we may be surprised to find that cognitive agency is not
ascribable to the contemplative himself except insofar as he is engaged in the
purely negative, if you will, the purgative process of eradicating within
himself all that is not God preparatory to receiving the divine infusion. In the
mystical experience of St. John, the notion of agency is directly ascribable to
God only: the contemplative merely disposes himself to receive this infusion
which God alone initiates and consummates, both according to his will, and that
degree to which the soul has succeeded in eliminating within itself all the
epistemological debris which effectively obstructs the clear and immediate
vision of God. Mystical experience, then, is seen to consist in a dialectic
between the passivity of the soul on the in mystical union, the contemplative is
not for that reason abstracted from the penalty of original sin and therefore
incapable of subsequently sinning. His nature, radicated in genealogy and
inherited from Adam, remains intact --- despite God’s predilection --- and the
invitation to union is apt to be viewed by the mystic not as a violation of
nature, but as extraordinary testimony to the ability of God to work
supernaturally in the soul.
The Problem with Language: the Limitations of the
Intelligible
One of the most
challenging issue to be addressed, and fundamental no less to the philosophy
than the theology of mysticism, concerns the role of language in the mystical
experience. It is a linguistic tradition --- and problematic --- the antecedents
of which, at least for our purposes, go as far back as the Neoplatonists in the
third century, and, arguably, earlier, to St. Paul himself. Within the tradition
from which St. John writes, the works of Dionysius the Pseudo-Areopagite,
particularly his treatise entitled De Divinis Nominibus (Concerning the
Divine Names), are an eminent example of the difficulties language encounters in
addressing the Absolute. This problem becomes critical in the often attenuated
discourses of the mystic, so let us look at this issue a little more closely.
For the contemplative, words characteristically fail to adequately
express or convey his experience of the Absolute, and any linguistic description
drawing its categories from experience is found to be inadequate to, and
radically distinct from, that unique experience of God in mystical union.
So entirely dissimilar is this experience to all others, that the mystic
typically finds it difficult to establish any commensurability at all.
At best, God may only be
spoken of analogically. But even this becomes problematic in St. John’s
exposition, for any analogy at all presupposes at least some common
categories between the analogized. To wit, in the first book of the Ascent of
Mount Carmel, St. John outlines a cosmological relationship characterized by
opposition between the created order and God. Each is possessed of
ontological categories radically dissimilar in nature. How then, we must ask, is
the role of analogy, which figures as largely in St. John’s poetry as in his
philosophy, possible? For the answer, I think, we must look to the nature of St.
John’s two principal analogies: the relationship of the Lover to the beloved,
and that of the Bridegroom to the bride. Quite obviously, it is the notion of
love that is fundamental to and essentially characterizes each
relationship. And it is precisely this notion that, for St. John, becomes the
common denominator between the contemplative and the Absolute. The analogy, we
will find, is adequate precisely because commensurability is possible through
man’s basic ontological status as the image of God. And this image of God
in man is, for St. John, love, for God Himself is love.5
And yet the very nature
of love itself is incapable of being adequately expressed. Words, however well
chosen, and descriptions, however articulate and exhaustive, are found in the
end to be profoundly impoverished. The essence remains ineffable, to be
experienced immediately, intuitively. And so the analogy itself breaks
down linguistically: our experience of God can only be analogized to our
experience of love --- and our experience of love is essentially recalcitrant to
language. The experience of God in mystical union, like the experience of love
between the bride and the bridegroom, remains intuitive and essentially
unavailable to language. The experiences are comparable because they share
common intuitions, and while certain subjective states attendant upon, and, as
it were, accidental to, such experiences may in fact be vaguely described, the
intuitive affinity itself evidently derives from some source in itself
spontaneous, ever-immediate, and self-creating.
This serves to underscore
yet another dimension of the persistent problem with language. Descriptive
language purports to convey to us, or to signify, some aspect of reality
typically not immediately available to us; it serves, then, to mediate or
to approximate the reality. But it is only able to do so by presupposing
an entire spectrum of shared experience necessary to
intelligibility in any particular universe of discourse. In this sense, language
may be viewed as an expedient in lieu of direct experience. And yet we have
found that the nature of the mystical experience is essentially intuitive,
immediate, direct. It is, in short, an experience --- and any language
endeavoring to describe this experience necessarily presupposes this
experience as a condition to the intelligibility of the account it would render.
Let us suppose an individual with a rare sensory dysfunction who has never
experienced the sensation “hot”. No matter what linguistic categories we invoke,
from the cup of hot tea to the arcana of thermodynamics, our attempts to
communicate this sensation to that individual will be in vain until he has
shared that experience with us, and only in light of that experience will
the word “hot”, and all that attends our understanding of it, become
intelligible, meaningful, to him. In other words, our admission into any
meaningful universe of discourse presumes shared experiences upon which
it is grounded. Apart from this essential condition, any description of mystical
experience, however detailed and definitive, is necessarily emptied of
intelligibility. Mystical union, then, or infused contemplation as it is often
called, remains to be experienced, and when spoken of is only done so
analogically. Coupled with the problem of absolute incommensurability
deriving from any attempt to relate the finite to the Infinite, the created
conditional to the Uncreated Absolute, the mystic who would attempt to relate
his experience faces a redoubtable challenge indeed.
Perhaps in some small way
we have already succeeded in understanding some of the very fundamental issues
involved in the Western tradition of mysticism. It by now be reasonably clear,
for example, that the relatively esoteric nature of mysticism, coupled with the
mystic’s insistence upon the ineffability of the experience itself, derives from
two closely related factors: the relatively small number of shared experiences
upon which this tradition rests, and, of course, the limitations inherent in
language itself. Experience,we find, inevitably outstrips language --- it is the
antecedent which language presupposes as a condition to the intelligibility of
language at all. An alternative, then, must be sought beyond purely descriptive
language. And while language clearly cannot be abandoned in any attempt to at
least approximate meaning in the mystic’s account, it can, nevertheless be
modified, articulated, inflected, to form a linguistic tangent on the Absolute
--- and this, I think, is what St. John strives to achieve in his poetry. It
seems to me very significant that St. John treats of the mystical experience in
poetic form, and then proceeds to comment on each line and stanza with an often
involuted exposition on its theological or philosophic import. It appears to be
of the very essence of poetry that the words of themselves are merely vehicles,
often to non-verbalizable meanings. The meanings arise, hover as it were,
enigmatically above the hard and fast signification of the words and often defy
our most persistent efforts to impose some determinate form upon them. That one
line of St. John’s verse may be followed by ten paragraphs of closely reasoned,
discursive analysis merely brings to relief the fact that poetic form contains
within itself a near infinitude of meaning which transcends the finite words. In
short, the enigmatically communicative form of poetry demonstrates itself to be
the only proximate means of communicating the mystical experience ---
while at once underscoring the inadequacy of words to describe
it.
Why indeed, we must ask,
given these extraordinary obstacles, does St. John, or any mystic, for that
matter, endeavor to write of these experiences at all? The answer, I think ---
at least for St. John --- is that while this experience is extraordinary and
seldom encountered, it is not for a lack of predilection on the part of God.
Indeed, St. John insists that ecstatic union in this life is merely the prelude
to that everlasting and ecstatic union with God that is inaugurated in heaven as
the culmination of our life on earth --- and that it is God who ceaselessly
calls us to this union. And while many, called to perfection, turn aside like
the rich young man of the Gospels, either through an arrogance as ancient as the
angels, or simply through a lack of perspicacity, there will always be generous
souls quick to answer, and it is to these that St. John addresses his works.
What remains obscure in the text will become at once luminously clear in the
experience.
1 Although we
shall eventually find that the notion of experience itself is inadequate
to our understanding of the mystical experience.
2
Mystical
theology is knowledge of God by experience arrived at through the embrace of
unifying love. ( De Mystica Theologia Speculativa ).
3
cf. Critique of
Pure Reason (Immanuel Kant), Transcendental Doctrine of Elements, I, A20/B34 -
A46/B73
4
This,
incidentally, is no less true of Solipsism, or the epistemological theory which
holds that we know only ourselves and modifications of that self. Every
modification eventually constitutes a known datum contributing to, but no
longer concurrent with, the personal continuity (identity) that remains (as the
present knower) throughout these modifications.
5
1. Jn.
4.
The Mystical Tradition and St. John of
the Cross
Confluence, Divergence, and Coherence
From the outset, as it must be clear by now, it will not be
our purpose, nor does it lie within the scope of this book to seek
parallels between the doctrine of St. John of the Cross and the many mystics
which preceded him within the tradition to which he very clearly belongs. It is,
rather, my express wish to examine the philosophy of St. John upon its own
terms, in and of itself, without cluttering the text or confusing an
already difficult issue with a plethora of distracting references and historical
asides that, while providing a broader overview, inevitably vex us by pulling us
away from the focus required to grasp this profound work. Historical perspective
is very valuable; indeed, indispensable to an understanding of mysticism at
large, and while clear parallels do in fact exist between the doctrine of St.
John and the doctrines of earlier mystics, the reader who would have both ---
the breadth of historical perspective and the intensity of focused examination
--- must inevitably decide upon oone or the other. I have opted for the
latter. But I also recognize the necessity of some perspective from the former.
As E. Allison Peers had correctly pointed out, in the works of St. John we find
ourselves at the confluence of a great mystical tradition to which many prior
writers had contributed --- each uniquely, but only in part --- to the
culmination of that unified and disciplined whole systematically, and for the
first time coherently, articulated in the thought of one writer: St. John of the
Cross.
But St. John is no mere
synthesizer. His unique and profound contribution, not merely to the literature,
but to the theology of mysticism, is unparalleled, and unrivaled by any of his
predecessors, many of whom unquestionably contributed to the development of his
thought. But one would not, for that reason, hold the creative genius of, say,
Heisenberg, to be diminished simply because prior physicists had made separate
and distinct contributions which the creative genius of Heisenberg --- grasping
in toto what each had only succeeded in articulating in part --- molded
into a successful physics no less original for these prior contributions, than
it was creative in articulating the whole. Our notion of creativity as such
quite often and unconsciously appears to derive its paradigm from God
understood as having literally created ex nihilo. But in man, in any man,
creativity is not something that suddenly emerges quite spontaneously and in
isolation. There are always antecedents from which creative genius springs,
distilling something pure from the brackish tributaries upon which it draws.
Within the Christian tradition this was certainly so of St. Thomas Aquinas. It
is no less true of St. John of the Cross.
Mystical theology, we
might say, appropriately begins, as it ends --- in a paradox. The most direct,
and certainly the most widely accepted interpretation of the development of the
tradition of Western Christian Mysticism traces its origins back to Plotinus in
the third century 1 But where Plato had endeavored to preserve
the fluid dialogical nature of what was essentially philosophic inquiry,
the Neoplatonists in general, and particularly Proclus in his tremendously
influential Elements of Theology, strove toward a rigorously
architectonic form, a form through which they sought to elaborate not so much a
synoptic philosophy, but a coherent and essentially reactionary doctrine.
This doctrine, only casually derived from Platonism, emerged from what
essentially began as dialogues between Plotinus and Ammonius Saccas --- a
long-standing oral tradition to which Plotinus himself adhered until he was
fifty and had begun making notes of his lectures. It was these notes which his
pupil Porphyry subsequently edited and organized into the Enneads
2
--- and the reason this was done at all is the whole point of the paradox to
which we had adverted at the beginning.
The Bursting Chrysalis: Antagonism, Assimilation and
Articulation
While Plotinus himself
makes no reference whatever to Christianity, confining his criticisms
specifically to Gnosticism, it nevertheless remains that the mystical doctrine
of Plotinus that had been subsequently developed by Porphyry and Iamblichus
3 --- and especially as it had been systematically
articulated by Proclus --- cannot be understood apart from, because in
fact it was in large measure a calculated response to, the burgeoning
threat of the still nascent Christianity. Not only was Christianity winning
converts to the cause, but more importantly, it was simultaneously encroaching
upon the state religion --- and with it, making decided inroads against what the
Neoplatonists saw as the last vestiges of classical culture. Neoplatonism was,
in this very clear sense, a reactionary philosophy --- it was articulated in
response to, and essentially to compete with, the new religion of Christianity
which was sweeping the Empire, and along with it, the Hellenic tradition that
had become a part of the unraveling fabric of post-classical society. And this
is to say that even the systematic origin of the phenomenon of mysticism has its
historical roots in antithesis.
It is important to
understand in this connection that early Christianity, imbued as it was with the
anticipation of the imminent parousia, or Second Coming of Christ, had more
urgent, and certainly more practical objectives in light of its impending
redemption, and, consequently, little interest in speculation. With the passage
of time, this sense of imminence, of impendence, while not entirely lost,
inevitably receded before the more immediate demands thrust upon it by an
antagonistic culture. The early Christian community soon came to the realization
that it had to cogently evaluate its own doctrines in the very terms of its
antagonists; to coherently interpret their deepest convictions in light of the
increasingly critical and hostile position of the Neoplatonists. While it is
true that the Neoplatonists could claim an historical continuity with classical
antiquity through the fusion of Platonic and Aristotelian philosophical
concepts, it is also true that Neoplatonism had effectively exceeded the
legitimate bounds of classical philosophy. In fact, Neoplatonism had radically
redefined philosophy by no longer understanding its objective to lay
simply in the attainment of truth, but by transforming truth into religious
insight through a specifically epistemological enterprise in which philosophic
knowledge culminated in the knowledge of God, or better yet, in God as the
culmination of philosophical knowledge. Through this transformation it
successfully, if superficially, combined the official gods of the Empire
reinterpreted through Plotinus, with the prestige that classical philosophy
enjoyed at large. It was, after all, a doctrine clearly more congenial to,
because it more closely accorded with, the prevailing Hellenistic tradition
through its unique interpretation of Plato, and had, moreover, the distinct
advantage of preserving important and popular elements of pagan religion. The
official polytheism of the state, now reinterpreted in pseudo-Platonic terms ---
however tentative --- in turn lent philosophical legitimacy to Neoplatonism, a
legitimacy it would not have otherwise enjoyed apart from the prevailing
cultural affinity for Plato.
Neoplatonism, then,
effectively forced Christianity out of the slumber of its own critical naiveté.
In a larger sense, the conflict which had long existed between Rome and Galilee
had now emerged from the narrow and patently futile gauntlet of the Roman arena,
where even blood had failed to attenuate the conflict, into the decisive arena
of the mind. Faith would wither under the light of unrelenting reason --- and
reason would succeed where duress not only had miserably failed, but had served
to fuel the fervor of this growing, unreasoned, and recalcitrant sect. Another
approach was clearly necessary to preserve what was left of the respectability
of Hellenism in a declining empire, and Plotinus found in Platonism the most
effective instrument to this end. This is not to say that the essentially
reactionary impulse of Plotinus was exercised, or even conceived, in the
interests of the state, at least in a way that we would understand in
contemporary terms; still less that he did not have a genuine philosophical
commitment to, if coupled with a defective understanding of, the tradition of
Platonism --- but the fact remains that the doctrine itself unquestionably
evolved as a response to both cultural and contemporary
considerations.
Inevitably, however, even
this perspective is too myopic. Very clearly, systematic mysticism cannot be
discussed apart from Plotinus, Porphyry, and especially Proclus --- who first
made the distinction between the via affirmativa and the via
negativa in the epistemological approach to God --- and whose synthesis of
Neoplatonic concepts through Aristotelian logic was to prove so influential in
later Scholastic thought. But the mystical enterprise must be understood within
a much larger historical context. The bankrupt philosophies of the classical
era, Eclecticism, Epicureanism, Skepticism and Stoicism, all of which had
promised --- and failed --- to deliver happiness, resulted in a general
disillusion with philosophy as a viable means of rescuing post-classical society
from its impending dissolution. And while it is true that Neoplatonism attempted
to provide that alternative by vying with Christianity, it is no less true that
the mystical impulse itself clearly predated the advent of Neoplatonism as the
first systematic formulation of the basic mystical thesis; an impulse which cuts
across all traditions and cultures and has been universal in every age. It is
fundamentally a human response that is as ancient as the Divine invitation
echoed in the cool of the evening in the garden of the first paradise:
“Vocavitque Dominus Deus Adam, et dixit ei: ‘Ubi es?’
“
4 The Divine solicitation to union with
God, then, is as ancient as the creation of the heart of man. The human
susceptibility to God cannot be confined to a culture, a tradition, a doctrine,
or even any one religion. This is no invitation to indifferentism; it is merely
a realization, a recognition, that this susceptibility is rooted in the ontology
of the soul itself, and is therefore universal to all men, in all ages, in every
culture. It is obviously another case altogether how each culture has
interpreted this invitation and responded to it. For the Christian mystic,
however, this invitation takes the decisive and definitive form of God Incarnate
in the Person of Jesus Christ, a point to which we alluded earlier, and for
which reason we needn’t reexamine now.
The concatenation of
persons and ideas which had culminated in the lucid exposition of St. John is
more or less clearly defined along an historical continuum that is nevertheless
worth exploring, for the thought of St. John cannot be exscinded from the
tradition out of which alone it coherently arises. We had already briefly
adverted to Plotinus, Porphyry, and Proclus as the systematic progenitors of the
mystical doctrine that had come to be subsequently elaborated within Christian
metaphysics. There are many intermediary figures, to be sure: Iamblichus, the
Syrian pupil of Porphyry; Marinus, the disciple of Proclus; and commentators
like John Philoponus who subsequently converted to Christianity, among a host of
other less significant figures after whom Neoplatonism, as a viable philosophy
in its own right, had effectively come to a conclusion, having been supplanted
by the decidedly more cogent and closely reasoned Christian interpretation.
Christian thought, in the end, did not abolish Neoplatonism, as Neoplatonism had
been intended to abolish Christianity, but rather reinterpreted it, and in the
process had not so much adopted, as assimilated significant features of
Neoplatonism, and incorporated them, with some residual tension, within the
philosophic body of Christian doctrine.
The Neoplatonic emphasis
on the dialectic approach to God is a good illustration. For the Neoplatonist
there are essentially three dialectical moments culminating in the knowledge of
God. These may broadly be summarized as the predicative, in which we affirm
something about God; the dispredicative, in which, paradoxically, we deny what
we have affirmed, at least in a univocal sense; and finally the
superlative, in which we reaffirm what we had denied, but in an equivocal
sense; this latter finally achieving the most adequate approximation not simply
linguistically available, but epistemologically possible. An example will prove
helpful. For the Neoplatonist, the only ascriptions proper to God are the
One and the Good. The most fundamental concept of being, however, is not
predicated of God except equivocally, or analogically: it is not predicated of
the One or the Good --- because it is absolutely transcendent --- in the way
that it is predicated of other things in the universe of experience. So much had
at least been suggested by Plato in his Republic and Symposium,
although with a good deal of vacillation and, we might add, with sufficient
enough ambiguity, if not ambivalence, to provide stable enough a platform for
Plotinus to make his leap to super-reality where Aristotle through that same
ambiguity stepped down to the world of experience. The fact remains, however,
that every instantiation of being in the world of ordinary events is, without
exception, determinate, limited, and therefore finite. In other words, each is
possessed of being in a way that is not just different from, but radically
dissimilar to, the completely transcendent Being of God. We cannot, as a
consequence, univocally ascribe being to God --- who is without limitation,
determination, and finitude --- in the way that we ascribe being to a man or,
for that matter, to a tree. In this sense, then, God is not being; at
least not being ordinarily understood. To arrive at an adequate understanding of
the nature of God, then, we must effectively dispredicate him of being in the
way that being is understood of everything else apart from God. God, as a
result, must essentially be understood neither as being, nor as not-being. His
being is, in the terminology of the Neoplatonists, above
being.
A good deal more, of
course, is involved in this dialectic which is extrapolated to every other
possible predicate of God with essentially the same result: the thesis, having
been established, is at once abrogated through its antithesis, and the erstwhile
contradiction is sublated into a synthesis reconciling this apparent opposition.
The synthesis itself, however, is at best only tentative, resting as it does
upon a precarious balance between the univocal and the equivocal use of language
--- and the problems this inevitably creeates for language, together with the
paradoxes it subsequently engenders, are by now obvious and have become
intrinsic to mystical discourse ever since. In other words, what has become
conceptually synthetized through language does not translate into an
ontological opposition that in the end is understood as apparent only.
The ontological opposition remains unmitigated and intact. What has been
conceptually reconciled are merely the terms of opposition applied to the
Absolute --- an opposition which, in any event, is entirely extraneous to the
One in virtue of its utter transcendence --- a synthesis which the Neoplatonist
tentatively achieves through the use of the superlative. And this, of course, is
simply another way of saying that the Absolute is only susceptible of being
addressed analogically.
As we may well
anticipate, such an analysis --- at least relative to the paramount concept of
being --- was fraught with problems upon its own terms, and, as it stood, was
not entirely amenable to thinkers struggling to articulate a Christian
philosophy within an otherwise useful Neoplatonic framework. Systematically
sound, the metaphysical architecture around which Plotinus constructed his
doctrine stood largely in need of rehabilitation only --- specifically along the
lines of its cosmological and ontological interpretations. And it is precisely
on this point, in one of the first crucial breaks with unchristened
Neoplatonism, that the 4th century Marius Victorinus, considered by
some to be the first Christian Neoplatonist in the Western tradition, took
exception. Significantly, Victorinus held being or esse to be, if
not the most appropriate, at least the most accurate name for God in one of the
earliest, if only inchoate, formulations of Christian philosophical thought. A
tension, then --- one never entirely resolved --- ineluctably emerges from the
Christianizing of Neoplatonism; a tension, we can see, essentially
resulting from the
incorporation of significant features of Neoplatonism, both metaphysically and
cosmologically, together with the repudiation of one of its most basic tenets
concerning the fundamental concept of being.
In other words, while
much of the metaphysical infrastructure of Neoplatonism remained intact
despite its adaptation to specifically Christian concepts; ontologically,
the abstract, superessential being of, say, Proclus, is clearly not
identical, nor can it be equated, with the personal Being of the
Christian Neoplatonists. Although the One identified by Plotinus is indeed, and
almost parenthetically described as “the paternal divinity,” 5 the god of Plotinus, Porphyry, and Proclus is, in a manner
of speaking, not the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. To begin with, it is not
a personal being to whom, for example, prayers are addressed; a being understood
as intimately involved in the lives and the affairs of men. For the
Neoplatonist, there is no predilection for man in the abstract being of the
Absolute. The whole point, however, is that not just the Being, but the
personal Being of God, is unquestionably the most fundamental
tenet of Christianity; in fact, it is unquestionably the first principle of any
specifically Christian metaphysics.
As a consequence, the
categorical transcendence of the Absolute of Plotinus --- a transcendence so
complete that it does not so much as admit of the predication of “being” to a
proper conception of the Absolute except by way of pure analogy --- becomes an
immediate point of contention in the adaptation of Neoplatonism to Christianity.
This, paradoxically, but no less obviously, is not to say that the Christian
philosopher does not attribute transcendence to God; he merely interprets this
transcendence, not in less categorical, but in less stringently ontological
terms; terms which, in the end, find their most coherent definition in a
metaphysics involving the notion of participation.
The Areopagitica
Certainly in terms of the
influence exercised by any one Neoplatonist, the most central figure, and
unquestionably the most instrumental in this transformative assimilation is
Dionysius the Pseudo-Areopagite, or as he is often simply called, the
Pseudo-Dionysius, the fifth century Christian philosopher (probably a disciple
of Proclus) whose actual identity remains unknown, although largely conjectured
upon. He is generally believed to have been an ecclesiastic of some sort whose
pseudonymous authorship of this body of writings that has come to be known as
the Areopagitica, is ostensibly attributed to one of the judges of the
Areopagus, or the supreme tribunal in Athens, before which St. Paul had stood to
defend his evangel, and subsequent to whose eloquent defense, converted to
Christianity 6.
We now know this not to be the case, and the reasons put forth for this
pseudonymity are many and varied, but few of them seriously suggest anything
more than the type of pious literary imposture that appears to have been
commonly practiced at the time. In any event, the authorship of these works is
largely beside the point considering the systematic coherence achieved in which
Neoplatonic concepts were successfully synthesized with accepted Christian
doctrine. These treatises, which were to have an impact well into the middle
ages and beyond, and which in toto constitute the Areopagitica, are four: De
Divinis Nominibus (a paradigm of the via affirmativa), Caelestis
Hierarchia, Ecclesiastica Hierarchia, and Theologia Mystica
(an even more celebrated paradigm of the via negativa)
7 The latter, though extremely brief --- having only five
chapters --- distills elements essentially derived from the other three
treatises which then form the basic principles to mystical union with God.
Anyone who has read anything of the medieval mystics will be immediately
acquainted with much of the imagery and many of the analogies, to say nothing of
the method, in this work. And while we do not intend to go into a detailed
analysis of the Christianized Neoplatonism of the Pseudo-Dionysius, it is
sufficient for this brief summary to note that the Areopagitica is the locus
classicus not only of the linguistics of mysticism, together with the
inchoate development of a distinctive mystical epistemology, but of the via
negativa, or the negative way, the concept perhaps most central to the later
metaphysical thought of the medieval mystics in particular, and Christian
mysticism in general.
It is very clear from the
outset that the author of the Areopagitica was profoundly influenced by Proclus,
the last and arguably the most systematic thinker of the Neoplatonic school, who
was deeply antagonistic to Christianity. Despite this marked influence, however,
the synthesis which the Pseudo-Dionysius had effected between Neoplatonism and
Christianity was so successful that the Areopagitica very early on were invoked
as competent documents on both sides of the Monophysite controversies in the
6th century, and in the dispute over Monothelism in the
7th. Within the latter part of that same century we find St. John
Damascene, the last of the Greek Fathers, appealing to the Pseudo-Areopagite in
discussing the limitations of language in addressing the Absolute, particularly
in his references to the essential incomprehensibility of God.
8 Widespread as his influence had been, however, it was St.
Maximus Confessor, the 7th century theologian who, by successfully
integrating dogmatics into the Pseudo-Dionysian schema through his lucid
commentaries on all four treatises, had provided the necessary theological
glosses to obvious ambiguities in the texts, bringing the works of the
Pseudo-Dionysius into closer alignment with orthodox doctrine and thus
effectively preparing them for, and greatly contributing toward, their general
recognition in the later Middle Ages.
Ironically, the profound
influence that the Pseudo-Dionysius was to exercise upon the later development
of medieval mystical thought was nearly lost to the West together with the
knowledge of classical Greek that had all but vanished in the four hundred years
preceding the Carolingian reforms and the subsequent revival of letters,
culture, and learning. Greek at this time, indeed, the pursuit of learning in
general, appears to have been preserved exclusively in the monasteries of
Ireland, which alone had been spared the barbarian incursions that had ravaged
the Continent and extended as far as Britain. Fortunately, however, they had
failed to press farther west, and at the behest of Charles the Bald, it was the
Irish philosopher and theologian, Johannes Scotus Erigena, one of a handful of
theologians in the West who had acquired facility in classical Greek, who was
largely responsible for bringing the Areopagitica 9 (together with St. Maximus Confessor’s Ambigua) into
the mainstream of medieval theological thought through his translation in 858 of
the works from their original Greek into Latin. At the same time, he
incorporated significant features of these works into his own speculative
theology that itself had become prominent in his most celebrated, if
controversial work, De Divisione Naturae 10, otherwise known as the Periphyseon, which was
widely read by mystical theologians in the 13th century and exerted
considerable influence upon such later figures as Johann Eckhart. With the
isolated exception of Johannes Scotus Erigena, however, a significant hiatus
occurred in the development of mystical-theological thought between the
9th and the 11th centuries that coincided with the greater
gap in continuity that had occurred within philosophy itself apart from a few
notable exceptions such as Boethius in the early 6th century ---
considered by some the last of the Romans --- whose De Consolatione
Philosophiae (a philosophical and not an explicitly Christian work per se)
bears the unmistakable stamp of Proclus, and possibly St. Isadore of Seville in
the 7th century, more properly an encyclopedist in his attempt to
compile a sort of summa of universal knowledge, parts of which, incidentally,
preserved important fragments of classical learning that would otherwise have
been lost altogether.
Revival, Reason and Revelation: the Middle Ages and the
Mystical Tradition
Not until the revival of
letters and learning in general under the auspices of Charlemagne (principally
through Alcuin, the great architect of the Carolingian renaissance) will we find
the literature of mysticism reintroduced through the reintroduction of classical
learning itself. This, as we have seen, was the impetus that brought the
Pseudo-Dionysius to Johannes Scotus Erigena in the first place. While the
assimilative process, as we may expect, was gradual, so effective was the reform
in education and learning that had been brought about largely through the
efforts of Alcuin that the educational system it produced survived the collapse
of the Carolingian Empire, which had effectively ended with the death of Charles
the Fat in 888. However, the wealth of classical learning it had succeeded in
acquiring was preserved in the Cathedral schools and monasteries through which
it subsequently became available to the mystics who would later flourish in the
12th century
It would seem to appear
that these two distinct repositories of classical literature were largely
responsible for the two equally distinct approaches to mysticism that we find
emerging in the 12th century. While clearly not separate traditions,
the divergent interpretations found their clearest expressions respectively in
the Cistercian monasteries, most notably at Clairvaux and Signy, under the
auspices of St. Bernard --- widely regarded as the first medieval mystic --- and
at the Abbey School of St. Victor in Paris founded in 1108 by William of
Champeaux, but which really came to renown under the leadership of Hugh of St.
Victor, one of the foremost theologians of the 12th century and one
of the principal architects of scholasticism. In many respects it was St.
Bernard, however, who, in his “homilies on the Canticle”, and elsewhere, put the
indelible stamp of Christianity upon the Neoplatonic mysticism of the
Pseudo-Areopagite by contending that grace, and not simply the
abstracting process of contemplation, was essential, indeed, indispensable to
the knowledge of God that culminates in mystical union; a union, moreover,
achieved not through the intellect, but through the will; not through reason,
but essentially through love, and for whom the very possibility of union at all
presumed the imago Dei in the soul.
William of St. Thierry, a
close friend and colleague of St. Bernard, provided perhaps the clearest
expression of the Cistercian emphasis upon the role of the will in the
realization of union:
“When the object of thought is God, and the
will reaches the stage at which it becomes love, the Holy Spirit at once infuses
Himself by way of love [ such that ] the understanding of the one thinking
becomes the contemplation of the one loving” 11
In this respect it would
appear that St. John of the Cross is much closer to St. Bernard and William of
St. Thierry than to Hugh of St. Victor to whom he is in other respects
nevertheless indebted. While not prescinding from the necessity of revelation,
and always within the bounds of orthodoxy, Hugh of St. Victor nevertheless
strongly emphasizes the role of reason in attaining to the knowledge of
God. His contribution to the literature of mysticism, principally in the form of
his five mystical works, De Arca Noe Morali et Mystica; De Vanitate
Mundi; De Arrha Animae; and De Contemplatione et eius speciebus
was significant and the Neoplatonic influence upon his thought
unquestionable as we see in his Commentariorum in Hierarchiam Caelestem
Sancte Dionysii Areopagitae secundum interpretationem Joannnis Scoti libri
x. The emphasis upon reason, which characterized the Victorines in general,
is particularly evident in the mystical works Beniamin maior and
Beniamin minor by Richard of St. Victor for whom contemplation formed the
terminus of a progression of knowledge to the point of pure reason beyond which
--- and only with divine assistance --- the soul attains to union. In an
interesting aside nevertheless apropos of St. John, Richard invokes a
particularly useful analogy in the way of underscoring the importance of dogma
and Scripture to the mystical experience by seeing in the Mount of the
Transfiguration a prototype of certain “visions” accompanying this experience,
and claiming that such essentially peripheral phenomena, if they are in fact
genuinely divine in origin, must be corroborated by Moses and Elijah, who for
Richard symbolize the Church and Sacred Scripture. If they accord with neither,
they are to be rejected. Certainly the tradition that culminates in the thought
of St. John owes a considerable debt to the Victorine School in further
elaborating the Christian synthesis that derived its impulse from the
Pseudo-Areopagite. The extent to which St. John of the Cross was influenced by
this important school of thought is, I think, most clearly evidenced in his use
of the allegorical interpretation of Scripture, certainly not in the Victorine
emphasis upon reason. It would also seem probable that St. John’s metaphysics of
participation through love owes at least an historical debt to Richard of St.
Victor in whose De Trinitate God is emphasized as love itself, as the
Evangelist John had beautifully summarized, and not merely as a perfectly loving
being.
This tradition continues
to be developed in the writings of the13th century Franciscan mystic Giovanni
Fidanza, better known as St. Bonaventure, a contemporary and close friend of St.
Thomas Aquinas, whose Itinerarium mentis in Deum, or Journey of the Mind
to God, and De Triplici Via, or the Three-fold Way --- essentially a
compendium of the mystical theology of the Victorine School --- were widely read
by such diverse later 14th century mystics as Blessed Henry Suso and
Jean Gerson. It is really in the 14th century, however, that we come
the flowering of mysticism, and more specifically, to the apex of speculative
mysticism. The various earlier systems, both rational and affective --- that is
to say, emphasizing either reason or the will respectively --- converge at that
academic crossroads where the increasingly abstract, dry, and often contentious
schools encountered a popular yearning for depth and renewal in the most basic
spiritual aspirations of which the academics had seemingly lost sight in the
pursuit of matters abstruse and trivial by comparison. Here we find such
familiar and notable figures as Eckhart, Ruysbroeck, Suso, Tauler, and Gerson,
all of whom, directly or indirectly, to some extent influenced St. John of the
Cross. Within the limited scope of this book we cannot possibly attempt to
detail the individual contribution to the thought of St. John of each of these
figures who were, at least chronologically, his most immediate predecessors; it
is nevertheless clear, however, that the most direct sources to which St. John
had access were in any event themselves indebted to the contributions of
previous figures within the same tradition. And while we may safely advert to
the earliest systematic formulations of this doctrine in the Neoplatonists in
general and the Pseudo-Dionysius in particular, and see every subsequent
development essentially in light of this basic metaphysical doctrine, we cannot,
and quite obviously, for that reason prescind from those unique contributions
that were instrumental in articulating this early and largely inchoate doctrine
in a way that progressively succeeded in making it consistent with both
Christianity and reason.
To a large degree, each
figure in the mystical tradition owes a greater debt to the influence of another
and preceding figure in a way that is more clearly recognized than his debt to
the rest. But we must equally recognize that every mystic is essentially
eclectic in drawing upon the distinct universe of ideas that constitute the
tradition out of which his own thought emerges, sometimes subscribing to certain
aspects of one doctrine while largely rejecting the rest, as in the case of
Blessed Henri Suso’s rehabilitation of some of the faulty doctrines of Johann
Eckhart. In a sense, to say that St. John owes his most immediate debt to
Ruysbroeck, as some maintain, even if true in a purely chronological or
immediate sense, is to fail to see in Ruysbroeck the myriad other mystics,
indeed, the entire mystical continuum to which the doctrine of Ruysbroeck or any
other mystic is indebted. Every mystic, then, incorporates something of the
thought of not merely one particular mystic preceding him, but of the entire
tradition implicitly comprehended within the doctrine of that mystical figure to
whom he himself is most immediately indebted. And distinct elements within this
tradition extend back well beyond the Pseudo-Areopagite himself; in fact, at
least as far back as the 3rd century AD, some two hundred years prior
to the appearance of the Areopagitica. And the whole point is this: whether or
not say, Maximus Confessor in the 9th century had read St.
Athanasius’s Life of Antony written around 357 AD or the Spiritual
Homilies of the 5th century Pseudo-Macarius, and whether or not
Maximus’s Ambigua itself was the subject of study of say, Johann Tauler,
may be impossible to ascertain. What is certain, however, is that an entire
tradition consisting of a wide variety of writings by a great many different
writers is brought to bear on the doctrines that later became articulated in the
speculative systems of the great 14th and 15th century
mystics.
Any brief survey, for
example, must certainly include Origen, the 3rd century scholar and
Church Father who stands not only as one of the most creative minds in the
history of the Church, but as one of its earliest mystical teachers. Indeed, not
only was Origen a contemporary of Plotinus, but he studied under the very same
Ammonius Saccas from whom Plotinus derived his own mystical doctrine. In Origen,
among other things, we find one of the earliest examples of the systematic use
of allegory in the interpretation of Scripture 12, a literary device exercised no less by St. John of the
Cross than it was by the Victorines some four centuries before him. Among the
mystical doctrines to be found in his Commentary on the Song of Songs is
a conception of union framed around the notion of the imago Dei and his
writings clearly adumbrate the celebrated three-fold way of purgation,
illumination, and union,13 which had subsequently come to typify the mystical path to
God. But there are other aspects of mysticism to be considered as well. The
4th century St. Antony, for example, is widely acknowledged as having
contributed indispensable elements to the development of the ascetic aspects of
Western mysticism, which find their clearest expression in the form of what are
basically the ascetical prescriptions mandated by the via negativa. The
conception of a rehabilitation of man’s nature to its original state of
consonance with God, which had been forfeited as a result of the Fall, is
equally addressed by St. Anthony, and in the context of a conception of union
with God. His skeptical regard of supernatural phenomena and his admonitions
concerning them (to be reiterated by Maximus later, and St. Bernard later
still), his stress on the necessity of withdrawal from the world, together with
his counsels concerning impediments likely to be encountered as a result of
diabolical interference, are very familiar to us by now from a much later
historical context.
More influential still
upon the thought of the medieval mystics was the 4th century Desert
Father St. Gregory of Nyssa to whom the mysticism of St. John is, directly or
indirectly, indebted. In contradistinction to earlier (and some later) mystics,
but very much like the Pseudo-Dionysius (whose writings were unquestionably
influenced by St. Gregory of Nyssa) ecstatic union is to be attained through
darkness, not light. Not surprisingly, in his Life of Moses (as St. John
will much later describe it in his Ascent of Mount Carmel) we find that
the journey to “… the knowledge of God … is a steep mountain difficult to ascend
…”, and in this ascent itself, moreover, the imago Dei figures largely in
the mystical experience that follows. The Incarnation is, for St. Gregory, as it
is for St. John, and for Maximus Confessor before either of them, absolutely
essential to the very possibility itself of mystical union. The necessity of
abstraction from sensibility, and the imperative of faith as the only proximate
means to this union --- this is no less the currency of the mysticism of St.
Gregory than it is of St. John of the Cross.
In the writings of these
early Fathers, particularly Origen and St. Gregory, we also find some of the
earliest references to Divine love inflicting a wound whose pain is
longing for union; a sentiment echoed only less eloquently but no less
passionately by St. Bernard than by St. John of the Cross. Like St. Antony
before him, and St. John after him, St. Gregory understood mystical union as
essentially culminating in the restoration of the imago Dei obscured by
sin. But our striving after parallels for their own sake, should we care to
pursue them further, may well continue indefinitely, and in the end be quite
pointless; the recognition of such antecedents itself suffices to our present
purpose. For what I am suggesting in all this is merely what I had attempted to
state with a good deal more brevity earlier: All the coherent, but fragmented
elements of an entire historical tradition, dating at least as far back as the
3rd century, come into brilliant focus in the thought of St. John of
the Cross some thirteen hundred years later. Perhaps, in closing, an analogy of
our own will be useful. This tradition comes to us more or less like the
fragments of a mirror shattered at the dawn of time, each piece of which, in
some diminished form, in and of itself reflects something authentic of the one
same sun whose light is brought to bear upon it --- but these scattered pieces
are finally brought into proper orientation, aligned, reintegrated, and
seamlessly conjoined only through a creative insight so flawless in perspective
that the whole is for the first time reflected as unfragmented in all its parts,
revealing a brilliance far greater in its unity than the sum of each distinct
light reflecting in only the totality of its parts. Where each previous
mystic, through the indomitable prompting of Unspeakable Love, had succeeded
merely in hurling a star into the darkness, St. John, peering into that same
night, grasped the divine dialectic of darkness and light --- and with the
finger of God traced the constellation that revealed, in the closing words of
Dante’s Paradiso, “the love that moves the sun and every
star.”
1 or literally,
‘sets of nine’ essays divided rather arbitrarily by Porphyry in his penchant for
numerology into six groups.
2 Apart from the
Enneads, Porphyry himself had written several influential treatises, the most
notable being his Sentences, essentially an exposition of the philosophy
of Plotinus, and the Isagoge (or introduction to Aristotle’s categories)
which figured largely in later medieval thought especially in the controversy
over universals in the 11th and 12th
centuries.
3 His principal
works, broadly organized as the Summary of Pythagorean Doctrines, while
less celebrated than those of Porphyry, were more speculative still, and
contributed significantly to the modification of the basic metaphysical tenets
of Neoplatonism, elements of which Proclus would subsequently take up in his
final systematic synthesis.
4 “… the Lord
God called to the man, and said to him, “Where are you?” Gen. 3.9
(Vulgate)
5 Ennead
5.1
6 Acts
17.34
7 Not including
ten letters, apart from these treatises, attributed to the Pseudo-Dionysius as
well. These were addressed severally to ecclesiastics of ranks ranging from the
monk, Caius, to the Bishop of Titus, and one ostensibly to the Apostle John
himself.
8
De Fide
Orthodoxa
I.12
9 The text of
which, in the original Greek, had been archived by Pope Paul I in the Abbey of
St. Denis just north of Paris in 757 where it had remained unread for the better
part of a hundred years.
10
A boldly
speculative but unsuccessful attempt to synthesize the emanationisn, pantheism,
and mysticism of the Neoplatonic schema with the empirical elements of
Aristotle, Christian theism, and the doctrine on creation.
11 Golden
Epistle, 249-250
12
Philocalia, chapters
1-15
13 intimated
earlier still by St. Clement of Alexandria in his Stromateis in the
3rd century.
(Continued below)
PART 1
ASCENT of MOUNT
CARMEL
Beyond
Innocence
One of the fundamental principles of mystical theology,
briefly touched upon in our introduction, is that the relation between the
contemplative and God is marked by profound incommensurability in every
category. Ontologically, this incommensurability derives from the relationship
between two radically distinct natures: God, on the one hand, considered
ontologically, is uncreated, infinite, eternal, immutable, autonomous, and
self-sufficient. The ontological attributes of man, on the other hand, are
diametrically opposite. While procreative, his nature itself remains created. He
is finite in knowledge and power. His being exists, is enacted, radicated
within, the distinct and limited physical locus circumscribed by his body. He is
temporal, having historical antecedents in time: a beginning before which he was
not, and an end toward which he ineluctably moves. He is mutable, inconstant,
changing, evolving, maturing --- not only physically, but intellectually and
spiritually. He is altogether heteronymous. Subject to circumstances, forces,
and occurrences quite often beyond his control --- despite the most
assiduous application of his will --- he lacks complete self-determination.
Finally, he is utterly contingent. His being, in every way, relies, depends,
upon, requires, re sources beyond itself. Ultimately, the ontic reality of man
is understood to be conditioned by the divine existence itself: his being,
metaphysically considered, is ultimately dependent upon the being of God. The
divine existence, however, is absolutely unconditioned, being completely
sufficient unto itself.
Furthermore, this
incommensurability between God and man in the realm of the ontological, is
compounded by moral alienation in the universe of ethics. Prior to Adamic sin,
or the fall, the gulf between God and man is held to have been mediated by grace
which, according to Christian doctrine, is understood to be the created
participation in the life of God --- a life which, significantly, consisted in
familiar commune with God. By some primordial act of sin, however, man
fell from this state of grace; his communion with God was sundered and his
nature, once consonant and harmonious with God, became corrupt, divided,
disordered. He is yet possessed of an immortal soul in essential
communication with God inasmuch as God continues to communicate being to
the soul, but as a result of the fall and his subsequent alienation from God,
his cognition of this fundamental source of his being --- in a very real sense,
his vision of God --- has become inadequate and obscure. He is
essentially communicated with, but noetically excommunicated from, God. In the
state of innocence, the noetic apprehension of God is held to have been
connatural to man --- but this is no longer the case. In his fallen state, man
is deprived of this simple, immediate apprehension of God in which his
original felicity consisted.
Thus divided, man, once
empirically acquainted with the eternal --- and now in isolation from it --- is
a being whose cognitive acquaintance is now limited to one dimension only, the
temporal: and this really is the beginning of the mystical problematic, for it
is precisely temporal categories that are incompatible with the eternal, and
incommensurable with the infinite. It is the task of the contemplative, then, to
somehow reintegrate these bifurcated dimensions, in fact, to pass beyond them by
gathering the temporal into the eternal, and in so doing strive to attain
that epistemological integrity which existed in the state of innocence ---
indeed, to go beyond innocence by achieving not simply communion with God, as
Adam enjoyed prior to the fall --- but union with God. To do so, the
mystic must first abstract himself from that manifold of temporal categories
which are metaphysically irreconcilable with the two basic ontological
attributes of the Absolute: infinity and eternity. His quest for union with God
must be negatively achieved through a series of purgations which
will first attenuate, and then effectively abolish his metaphysical contrariety
to God.
It is within this context
that we first discern the first epistemological principle of the via
negativa: in order to achieve that union with God which constitutes the
soul’s consummate perfection, it is necessary to undergo two distinct negative
processes, or purgations, corresponding to what St. John calls the
sensuous and spiritual parts of the soul. 1 The purgation of each part, moreover, is to proceed
according to the three faculties of the soul --- will, understanding, and
memory --- each in relation to its sensuous and spiritual parts. In a
sense, St. John states his methodology early on and rather clearly in the
Ascent and we are tempted to extrapolate prematurely if not hastily in
light of it. This would be to err seriously. And perhaps we ourselves have begun
too abruptly, for it is not only the method, but also the means with which we
must first come to terms if we are to avoid confusion at the outset. It is
extremely important for us to understand that the movement to mystical union is
a cooperative enterprise throughout. The soul responds to, and passively
cooperates with, that initiative which rests with God alone 2.
Perhaps we can render
this in other terms nevertheless compatible with the thought of St. John; terms
that may more clearly establish the dialectical relationship that exists between
the soul of the contemplative and God. The activity of the soul of which
St. John speaks in his opening discourse in the Ascent, while not of
itself capable of inaugurating the union sought after, may nevertheless be
regarded as predispositional to that union which God alone effects, and
to which the soul is entirely passive. In an epistemological context, this state
of negativity that the soul strives to achieve may be viewed as the
condition of the
possibility of a direct intuition of God. Understood in this sense, the
dialectic between the soul and God becomes somewhat clearer. As the mere
condition of the possibility of the direct apprehension of God, this negation at
once presupposes passivity on the part of the soul, and activity on the part of
God --- an activity capable of actualizing this possibility through what St.
John terms the divine infusion.
This, however, must be
achieved systematically, or perhaps better yet, methodologically, and in keeping
with the empirical foundations of knowledge articulated by his Scholastic
predecessors, St. John begins this redoubtable task on the purely human level of
sensibility. The first step, then, that we encounter in the Ascent of Mount
Carmel (or the step toward the epistemological predisposition to mystical
union) is the negativity of sense. And this, St. John maintains, consists
in depriving the soul of distinct conceptions according to the
understanding, alien desires and affections according to the will,
and various images and representations according to the memory.
3 In other words, it calls for a centripetal movement toward
the axis of the soul’s being --- a rigorous integrating and coordinating of the
faculties in the intensely focused love of God alone, as the first prerequisite
to infused contemplation. And so we find St. John stating in Book I of
the Ascent that:
“…the soul [ in this state of negation ]
is, as it were, in the darkness of night, which is naught else than an emptiness
within itself of all things.” 4
The emptiness of which he
speaks in fact constitutes the state of sheer passive receptivity; a receptivity
toward which the soul is constrained to move preparatory to its union with God.
In this night of sense the pleasures and desires of the soul preeminently
involving the will are not so much systematically abolished, as
rigorously suspended, so that the soul contains nothing appropriated through the
will, in the way of created nature that would engender contrariety with the
Uncreated God. The precise metaphysical nature of this opposition between the
created order and God, which figures so largely in the philosophy of St. John,
remains to be addressed in greater detail later; for the moment, let us examine
some of the more salient implications involved in what we have considered so
far.
The Problem of Union vs. Identity
We have already touched
upon several notions that are indispensable to a clear understanding of
mysticism, and our discussion up to this point has briefly focused upon
predisposition, passivity, activity, and receptivity as central in the movement
toward mystical union. But even at this early point in our account a closer
examination of these central features brings us into an arena of considerably
greater complexity than any clarity it has afforded us thus far. Ineluctably,
even a preliminary analysis brings us, in fact, face to face with perhaps the
single greatest problem confronted in mystical phenomenologies in general, and
St. John’s works in particular, and this is the problem of union versus
identity. It is an unavoidable problem that becomes at times critical in
some later passages that we will examine in which St. John appears to equate
personal annihilation 5 with the virtual assimilation of the soul into the identity
of God 6 To St. John’s credit, however, it is equally important to
note that in other passages he is quite careful in keeping the two natures
distinct.7
What then is this
problem? And no less importantly, what is the provenance of this confusion? In
effect, the problem has always been latent in the account, for that attitude
which is conducive, or better yet, predispositional, to union, consists
precisely in the absolute passivity which follows the sensuous night of
the soul. In every faculty, according to St. John, the soul is rendered empty,
unoccupied. It is the sheer possibility of conscious actualization, but
is not of itself in any epistemological sense actual --- for its ordinary
consciousness, we have seen, consisted in precisely those elements which had
been systematically purged through the via negativa. In this state of
epistemological suspension --- completely void relative to nature broadly
understood as the sum of all possible natural conditions of conscious
actualization --- the soul is then receptive only to God as outside
nature, and who, as such, alone is capable of actualizing this mere
possibility through the divine infusion. Consciousness is thus contingent
upon God, is actualized by God, and is a consciousness of
God. In other words, it is an apotheosized state of consciousness, a
unitary and exclusive awareness of God. However, it is crucial for us to
remember that prior to this infusion, the soul of itself possessed nothing but
the possibility of conscious actualization, and that subsequent to union
its sole epistemological datum --- that in virtue of which alone it has been
actualized --- is God. And this is to say that only insofar as God communicates
himself the soul --- is the soul actual, in any consciously noetic sense. And
this, rather succinctly, is the problem of identity. It appears to be not so
much a union of distinct natures, as an identity resulting from the
apotheosizing of the one through its noetic assimilation into the
other.
But we also mentioned
that St. John was careful in keeping the two natures distinct, for he quite
clearly states that:
“In thus allowing God to work in it, the
soul is at once illumined and transformed in God, and God communicates to it His
supernatural Being, in such wise that it appears to be God Himself, and has all
that God has. And this union comes to pass when God grants the soul this
supernatural favor, that all the things of God and the soul are one in
participant transformation; and the soul seems to be God rather than a soul, and
is indeed God by participation; although it is true that its natural being,
though thus transformed, is as distinct from the Being of God as it was before”
8
What, then, in St. John’s
account may be invoked as the distinguishing feature between the notion of
union on the one hand, and that of identity on the other --- when
the two quite often appear to be conflated? Until we arrive at a concept that
will enable us to discriminate between the two, we can penetrate no further into
St. John’s mystical account, or, for that matter, effectively differentiate it
from other competing accounts entirely outside the Christian tradition. This
crucial concept --- the sine qua non to the very intelligibility of
Christian Mysticism --- is to be found in the notion of participation; a
notion that, while not prescinding entirely from a conception of
identity, more clearly implies the idea of union. Perhaps it can
better be explained this way: we understand by that which participates,
something clearly distinct from that in which it participates. That is to
say, while the notion of participation clearly implies unity between the
participant and that in which it participates, we at once understand that it is
a unity into which disparate elements enter. In a similar manner, we understand
by the notion of union, a conjunction of two in which the individual
natures entering into the union are preserved, rather than abolished; we should
otherwise find it very difficult to understand the sense in which we speak of it
as a union, rather than as a unity. Unlike identity which implies the reduction
of a merely apparent plurality to an ultimate unity, the notion of
participation is understood to involve the preservation of two authentically
distinct elements entering into --- while not simultaneously being abolished by
--- a union.
We should, moreover, find
it largely problematic, and entirely incompatible with the doctrines that St.
John later develops to view the type of infused contemplation that St. John
describes as resulting in an identity, rather than a union. It is, I think,
extremely important to the integrity of St. John’s thought to emphasize this
point, so let us take our previous discussion just a little further. The two
elements entering into identity, we had said, are in fact seen to be one. We do
not speak of one participating in the other, for there is no other,
strictly speaking: the merely-apparent two are in fact identical, understood to
be one and the same. We discover nothing of the sense of subordination or
contingency implied in the idea of identity, for the very simple reason that the
one is the other. The distinction, in other words, is essentially
spurious. Most often it is rendered in purely temporal, although sometimes
spatial, terms: it is, in fact, the one thing understood at different points in
time or space, or both.
Something quite different
emerges, however in our understanding of union through participation; something
which clearly suggests the contingent character of the participant relative to
that in which it is understood to participate. The latter, it becomes clear, is
presupposed as the condition of the possibility of a participant. Simply
put, what participates already presupposes that in which it is participating.
And this, needless to say, very clearly accords with St. John’s
understanding of the soul’s relationship to God subsequent to the state of
negation; a primarily noetic, but also an ontological relationship
in which the soul is contingent upon, presupposes, that divine initiative in
which alone it is actualized. While it is undeniably an apotheosized state of
consciousness, it is nevertheless a consciousness contingent upon, subordinate
to, and metaphysically distinct from, the divine agency through which alone it
becomes actualized. So vital is an understanding of this crucial distinction to
an understanding of St. John’s works at large, that unless we now grasp it
fully, any further attempt at understanding his sometimes involuted expositories
will be either entirely remiss or completely in vain. The notion of
participation is, as it were, the first premise in a mystico-logical sorites
upon which the coherency of the epistemology of mysticism rests. Once we have
succeeded in understanding this, we can begin to address the role that the
faculties play in the movement toward mystical
union.
1 AMC
1.1.1-2
2
AMC 1.1.5;
2.5.4
3 AMC 1.4.1-5;
1.9.6; 2.6.1-6
4 AMC
1.3.2
5 AMC
2.7.1
6 AMC
2.5.4
7 AMC 2.5.6-7 +
2.21.1 Also cf. ST I 3 Q.2 art.1
8 AMC 2.5.7 also
cf. STQ.3 art.4
(Continued below)
I
The Notion of the
WILL in the Philosophy of St. John of the Cross
We had briefly mentioned that in the state of negation the
soul is emptied of all desires and pleasures according to the will
1 and that in such a state the soul contains nothing in the
way of created nature which is contrary to God. But a good deal more needs to be
said about the metaphysical nature of this contrariety before we can go further.
Let us take, for example, the contrariety which St. John perceives to exist
between the finite and the infinite. First of all, it is important
to understand that while there appears to be logical polarity between the two,
they are not, in a metaphysical sense, mutually contrary. It is not so
much a matter of contrariety that is eventually seen to exist, as of an
insuperable disproportion in magnitude; a disproportion which so closely
approximates categorical opposition that it qualifies, in a practical sense, as
contrariety. It is magnitude, then, that is the essence of the finite and
the infinite, as duration is the essence of the temporal and the eternal. So
understood, the finite not only can be, but as a matter of course is
accommodated to the infinite without engendering any contradiction whatever.
The infinite divisibility of matter is one example that readily comes to mind in
the way of illustrating something finite incorporating the infinite within
itself while losing nothing of the nature of its own finitude. Everyone,
I think, will agree that we can, at least conceptually, continue dividing matter
ad infinitum. It is simply a matter of applied mathematics. However tedious we
should find this to be, it serves to demonstrate that the infinite so
incorporated really turns out to be pseudo-infinite after all. Starting with a
discrete whole, we are at least conceptually capable of subjecting it to
infinite reduction.
However, we should find
that at any given point in the reductive process (which may continue
indefinitely, that is to say, infinitely), a reversal toward integration will
eventually go no further than the discrete whole from which we started. In other
words, it is only a disintegratively infinite process. It is only infinite, so
to speak, from the top down. And this, obviously, is equally true of time
vis-a-vis eternity. While of itself infinitely reductive, divisible into
days, hours, minutes, seconds, etc., an abrupt reversal of this process will
never bring us beyond the present.
What is the point of this
aside? In each instance we find that the finite, while unable to comprehend the
infinite, is at least metaphysically susceptible to it. We have seen, through
two rather pedestrian examples, that the infinite may, in principle, be
accommodated to the finite without contradiction. But it does so dis-unitively,
by division, reduction, disintegration. It is, paradoxically, a unilateral
infinity coextensive with the finite: it is infinitely retrogressive, but only
finitely progressive. It will always have its terminus in the unity from which
it began. But the fact nevertheless remains that the matrix of the infinite is
at least implicit in the finite. A latent, if limited correspondence
does in fact exist, and it is in virtue of this fact alone that any
correlation between the two becomes possible --- and only on terms which
abrogate the metaphysical nature of neither. It is only when we try to pass
beyond the finite to the infinite that we encounter difficulties. Whereas
the infinite is capable of instantiating itself within the finite by
subsuming the finite under itself while yet remaining infinite, the finite on
the other hand is incapable of extrapolating itself into the infinite, of
passing beyond itself without at once ceasing to be finite. The bearing this has
on our understanding of the metaphysics underlying mystical union should be
fairly evident by now. It is simply this: In mystical union, it is not a matter
of the finite being poured, as it were, into the infinite --- the finite can
never comprehend, fill, be coextensive with, the infinite; rather it is a matter
of the infinite instantiating itself within, as it were, being poured into, the
finite. And this is precisely why it is termed the divine infusion; an
infusion that can only be effected through an approximation of the
infinite through the negation of all that is finite in the soul. That is to say,
the soul, created in imago Dei, is the approximation of the infinite in
its fundamental ontological nature. The infinite, as we had said earlier,
clearly cannot exhaust itself in the finite, but it can fill the finite
--- to the extent that the finite has abbolished every limiting category possible
to its being, leaving only the image, the ontic nucleus of its being --- a being
which, for St. John, together with a great many mystics within the Christian
tradition --- is being an image.
The Via Negativa: Notions of Contrariety and
Co-existence
As we had begun to say in
opening our discussion on the role of the will, in the state of negation
occasioned by the via negativa the soul contains nothing in the way of
created nature which is contrary to God. Inasmuch as God is ontologically
other to created nature, he is essentially contrary to nature as
Not-nature, and inasmuch as nature is ontologically other to God, it is
essentially contrary to God as not-God---and this, fundamentally, is the basis
for the categorical opposition found between the created order and God, a point
upon which St. John is clear in a number of passages:
“All the affections which [ the soul ] has
for creatures are pure darkness in the eyes of God 2 [and] all the being of creation compared
with the infinite being of God, is nothing 3 How great a distance
there is between all that the creatures are in themselves and that which God is
in Himself 4 for there
is the greatest possible distance between these things and that which comes to
pass in this estate which is naught else than transformation in God 5
Thus, he that will love some other thing together with God of a certainty makes
little account of God, for he weighs in the balance against God that which, as
we have said, is at the greatest possible distance from God 6 the
soul, then, must be stripped of all things created
7”
The soul, then, aspiring
to transformation in God through mystical union is only receptive to God insofar
as it has succeeded in negating within itself all that is other to God in the
way of created nature, until at last only that divine speculum remains in
the form of the image of God which mirrors, reflects, only God, and is so
utterly consonant with God as to effectively be in union with him. But even in
stating this, we’ve anticipated a good deal too much, for our most elementary
understanding is as yet far from complete. What are we to say, for example, of
the following principle upon which the argument rests that St. John has just
articulated above, and which is the sine qua non of every instance of the
via negativa:
“Two contraries cannot co-exist in one
person.”
8
Indeed, if one principle
is held to summarize the most basic metaphysical contention of the mystic, of
any mystic, in any tradition, it is this. But a clear understanding of this
principle is particularly critical --- indeed, it is indispensable, to an
understanding not simply of the thought of St. John as a mystic, but of the
entire metaphysics underlying the phenomenon of mysticism itself. How are we to
understand this principle? Is St. John simply, merely, invoking the law of the
excluded middle? And more importantly, precisely how are we to construe this
principle relative to the mystical experience? For the moment it must suffice to
say that the application of this principle to the mystical experience
presupposes the entire mystical thesis that consciousness is unified in
God thorough the direct and intuitive participation in the divine
existence.
As it is formulated by
St. John, the principle itself, that two contraries cannot coexist in one
person, certainly admits of some very pedestrian exceptions. In our ordinary
states of consciousness, for example, we regularly entertain, indeed, cannot
dispense with, a wide variety of opposites in the routine exercise of the
dialectic of reason. St. John, however, is not concerned with ordinary
states of consciousness except insofar as they stand in need of remediation
through the via negativa. This having been achieved (and here St. John is
really anticipating the full development of his doctrine), we must advert to the
mystical thesis itself, which we briefly touched upon above, and which, we
suggested, is concerned with the exclusive and singular occupation of
consciousness with God. And this is quite another thing. Ordinary consciousness
is always diffuse, always engaging a multiplicity. In the state of mystical
awareness, on the other hand, consciousness is actualized by, and unified in,
its singular object, God, --- or lacking that object, exists in a
terrible night in abstraction from everything else. Clearly, then, the
principle, as it stands, is in need of some qualification. Perhaps we can
restate it more consistently in the following way:
The coexistence of two contraries
within unified consciousness is impossible.
At first there appears to
be something subreptive about this. A consciousness, after all, unified
in being rigorously focused --- either upon nothing (the dark night of the soul)
in anticipation of the divine infusion, or upon God (in ecstatic union) --- by
definition would seem to exclude the notion of any coexistence whatever,
contrary or otherwise. Consciousness totally unified in a single apprehension
exclusive of all else, by definition precludes the possibility of
coexistence relative to other apprehensions--- but it does not, by definition,
necessarily entail contrariety. The notion of contrariety, in other words,
appears to be superfluous and the principle could as well be applied to any
state of affairs. But a closer reading of the mystical thesis reveals otherwise.
Since it is God who occupies (or would occupy) consciousness, everything
else that could possibly coexist with God would be other to God
--- it would, in fact, be nature,, and thus involve contrariety with God.
In short, within the limitations of space and time, there is a mutual
ontological tolerance, often a complementarity, in nature among things
created.
This rather congenial
arrangement, however, does not extend to nature vis-à-vis God. As a
sui generis, God is forever opaque to nature. Metaphysically, the being
of God stands diametrically against nature, not in the way of opposition
suggestive of antagonism but in the way of contrariety suggesting
incompatibility. And it is this to which I think St. John alludes when he
adverts to this Principle of Non-Contrariety --- a principle which, in
the logic of mysticism, is not simply equivalent to, but is identical with, the
Principle of the Excluded Middle or the Law of Non-Contradiction within formal
logic. But it is applied logic, a logic rigorously applied not to
concepts but to existential categories through the agency of the via
negativa. A clearly discernible connection, then, is seen to exist between
the principle of non-contrariety (the coexistence of two contraries within
unified consciousness is impossible ), and the mystical thesis (that
consciousness is unified in God thorough the direct and intuitive participation
in the divine existence).
But something more must
be said about this pervasive principle of non-contrariety which figures so
largely in the thought of St. John; a principle which, in the logic of
mysticism, effectively constitutes the antecedent to nearly every subsequent
premise. So far, we have merely succeeded in establishing the relation of this
principle to the mystical thesis, and while this is clearly indispensable to the
task we have put before us, the more important question to be asked, I think, is
simply this: precisely what role does this principle play in the opposition that
we find between God and created nature --- in both articulating the opposition
occasioned by the encounter between God and nature --- and at once bridging that
ontological gulf; translating that opposition into union? Well, to begin with,
the principle of non-contrariety may in fact be seen as the nexus between
the via negativa and the mystical thesis. It is presupposed by both: by
the via negativa as the principle upon which it functions in negating all
contrariety to God --- and by the mystical thesis in rigorously defining
the parameters around which alone the possibility of ecstatic union may occur.
Moreover, it relates the one to the other: the via negativa as the means,
and the mystical thesis as the end. The role, then, of the principle of
non-contrariety is twofold: it functions in the via negativa to mediate
the opposition between God and nature, and it is the conditional upon which the
realization of the mystical thesis rests. That is to say, it acts through the
via negativa to actualize the mystical thesis.
In the Ascent of Mount
Carmel, we first see this principle at work in the relationship that obtains
between what St. John calls the created will, and God --- a relationship that,
in turn, can only be understood in light of the opposition existing between the
created order and the Absolute. And while it is an opposition primarily
radicated in ontology (finite versus infinite, etc.), it inevitably reflects
itself epistemologically in man’s inability to adequately comprehend God. And
the mystic, of course, cannot hope to achieve union with that of which he knows
nothing, or to perfect union with that of which his knowledge is defective. The
mystic must first know God if he wishes to embrace him, and this
knowledge must be relative to what is authentic, and not a mere fiction. The
mystic who would aspire to union with God conceived of as golden calf would
aspire toward a fiction, and all his misdirected efforts would bring him no
closer to union with the calf than to the real God of whom he knows nothing. But
in St. John’s epistemology there is an antecedent to knowledge, an indispensable
faculty presupposed by knowledge and constituted as the
will:
“Two contraries cannot coexist in one
person and darkness, which is affection set upon the creatures, and light, which
is God, are contrary to each other, and have no likeness or accord between one
another” 9
It is through the will
(affection), then, that contrariety is first acquired by the soul; the will as
the affective faculty for appropriating anything within the created order
10. But, we are inclined to ask, is it not the case that we
must first know what we will to possess? For St. John, I think,
the answer must be, emphatically, no. First we must will to know --- and
then will to possess what we have willed to know. And this is to say that the
Thomistic apothegm, “Deum tamquam ignotum cognoscimus”--- “We know God as
unknown”--- essentially constitutes the first epistemological principle in
mystical theology: that we know God paradoxically --- as unknown. To wit, every
category in human experience that we have appealed to in our quest to know God
has left us empty-handed. Each category has either proven itself to be contrary
to, or incommensurable with, the inexhaustible Absolute. Our epistemological
approach to God has been, at its best, merely analogical. It is not that the
mystic’s plight is so abysmal that he has no inkling whatever of God.
Some acquaintance, however inadequate, however primordial clearly must
exist: we do not seek what we utterly do not know. Rather, we seek what we know
in part, or as St. Paul had eloquently put it, what we see “through a glass
darkly.” 11 And it is this impoverished perception, this only dim
acquaintance with the Absolute perceived, experienced, as the Good and the Holy
--- this only marginal acquaintance withh what is invincibly loving --- so
loving, in fact, that it compels our love --- that appears to be the germ
of mysticism. At its most fundamental level, it is the experience of
love, then, that is the impetus to know. And because we
desire what we will to acquire, St. John quite appropriately
speaks of the will in terms of “affection”.
An understanding of the
difference between knowledge and casual acquaintance --- both empirical
and rational --- we must, regrettably, but of necessity, presume at this point
in our account. It is a topic that simply cannot be adequately addressed without
involving us in too lengthy an aside. Knowledge for St. John, we must simply say
for now, constitutes a good deal more than casual acquaintance, and, relative to
God, a good deal less than perfect understanding. The issue of interest to us
here involves not so much the concept of knowledge as that of opposition. The
matrix of contrariety --- not a problematic of itself --- we have said,
is found in ontology. But it is the will which is the locus of
contrariety: the will as the agency through which the soul then appropriates
created things
to itself --- and in so
doing engendering actual, if you will, existential, contrariety in its
attempt to come to union with the Uncreated Absolute. The incompatibility is no
longer merely conceptual --- it becomes actual, concrete in terms of existential
impediments to union. The soul, possessed of God’s contrary in nature through
the appropriation of the will, is incapable of realizing union with God,
inasmuch as two contraries are incapable of being reconciled without abrogating
one. So let us look a little further into the nature of this opposition
itself.
The will, St. John is
clear, must be rendered passive through its subjection to the via
negativa, desiring nothing and finding pleasure in nothing.12 It must remain empty and receptive to God alone,
appropriating nothing to itself which may be antagonistic to union. The reason
for this passivity on the part of the will should be relatively clear by now:
any activity of the will entails that preoccupation of the will which
precludes its being occupied by God. But, we are compelled to ask, does not the
will, in willing nothing, still will? Yes. But willing nothing is quite
different from willing anything --- for literally nothing is appropriated
through the will willing nothing. Nothing in the way of contrariety, and
therefore nothing that constitutes an impediment to union.
Contrariety, then ---
while always metaphysically latent --- is first introduced, acquired, through
the will. How then, we ask, does the soul as the image of God in a
fundamental metaphysical sense (as we shall later see) come to be characterized
by that contrariety which we have found to be otherwise universal throughout
nature. Before we can begin to answer this, however, I think it is extremely
important for us to be clear about what St. John understands by the concept of
nature. For St. John, nature quite simply constitutes all that exists
outside of (and in this sense, other to) the Divine Simplicity --- a
universe created ex nihilo and characterized by multiplicity and finitude
--- that is to say, in a real metaphysiccal sense, entirely distinct from God. On
the one hand, St. John seems to understand by nature simply the material
universe, the universe of experience ordinarily understood, contributing, for
example, data to the understanding, or things appropriable through the will,
susceptible to the senses.13 But in a broader sense, St. John clearly includes in this
understanding of nature, the non-material universe as well, generally spoken of
in terms of spirit 14: angelic and demonic agencies, the human soul. However
understood, the outstanding feature of nature is its categorical contrariety to
God. It is the finite, the temporal, conceived not simply as distinct from the
infinite and the eternal but as metaphysically diametric to
them.
The IMAGO DEI: The Concept of Participation and the Notion of
Mitigated Contrariety
But while all created
natures exhibit contrariety to God, we shall later find that some measure of
commensurability does in fact exist and is seen to obtain between creatures and
God through a metaphysics essentially constructed around the central notion of
participation. And this is to say that the contrariety, the opposition if
you will, found in nature somehow falls short of being absolute --- that there
is, despite real opposition, a latent commensurability to be elicited from
nature in varying degrees according to its participative relation to God ---
some more, some less. And this, we will find, is why the soul, albeit a created
nature, is capable of realizing union with God. Ultimately, through the soul’s
ontological status as the imago Dei, the categories of opposition are
realized to be tentative, superficial aspects of a more fundamental
participative being. But between this unique human nature, itself only
intermediate between the highest hierarchies of being and the lowest
15 --- a familiar medieval schema --- that is to say, above
human nature and below it on this ontological gradient, the entire spectrum of
being ranges from that which exhibits the greatest contrariety to and the least
commensurability with God, to the greatest commensurability and the least
contrariety. All this, however, remains to be examined in greater detail later
on.
Now that we have a
clearer understanding of what St. John means whenever he invokes the concept of
nature --- broad as this articulation may be --- we can return to our original
question: how does the soul, as the image of God, come to acquire
contrariety through nature? Perhaps we can put the question another way. How can
the soul, which is essentially, that is to say, metaphysically,
constituted as the image or reflection of God 16, be contrary to that of which it is constituted an image?
This is a central paradox among the many that abound in the literature of
mysticism. The soul is held to have been created as the image of the Absolute
--- and nevertheless assumes real metaphhysical polarity to God. How does St.
John answer this? As we already have seen, the opposition between God and nature
poses no special problematic in and of itself. The two quite simply are
categorically distinct. It only becomes problematic when the soul aspires not
simply to a vis-à-vis encounter with God, that is to say, toward apposition with
God --- but to union with God. Some connection, therefore, must exist
between the soul as the imago Dei, and nature as instantiating within
itself opposition to God, such that the direct relation of the soul to God
becomes problematic by virtue of nature. A sort of inverse participation must
somehow occur by which the soul comes to share in that character of opposition
to God which is fundamentally a hallmark of nature. We must then look to the
will if we are to understand the provenance of this contrariety, for it
is the will which had been found to be the faculty through which contrariety is
first appropriated by the soul. But how, precisely, is this contrariety
acquired? St. John’s answer ultimately is formulated around what must be
regarded as one of the most important metaphysical principles he invokes
throughout his four treatises relative to union, and which, for our purposes we
will simply call the Principle of Similitude. Quite simply, for St. John,
the will in its love for anything is, by virtue of that love, somehow rendered
similar and equal to its object. This is the reason that the soul is
placed in an attitude of opposition to God through the exercise of the will upon
created objects of nature. The relation of the soul to God at once becomes
problematic because it is a relation essentially characterized by
opposition:
“... the affection and attachment which the
soul has for creatures renders the soul like to these creatures; and the greater
is its affection, the closer is the equality and likeness between them; for love
creates likeness between that which loves and that which is loved he that loves
a creature becomes as low as that creature, and in some ways lower, for love not
only makes the lover equal to the object of his love, but even subjects him to
it love makes equality and similitude” 17
This principle --- in
fact, this passage --- adumbrates a significant feature about what, for St.
John, constitutes man’s essentially reflective ontology, a
topic which shall be the subject of some rather detailed discussion in Part
II of our commentary. Here it is only important to note that man’s nature as
such is closely connected with, and in an important sense, realized in, its
relation to the universe of experience --- even, as we have already seen, in the
presuppositions of consciousness. Ultimately, we shall find that, for St. John,
man is not a being-in-himself, or being autonomously considered, due precisely
to his ontology as image of the Absolute.
The Principle of Similitude: Conformity and
Contrariety
Much, unfortunately, is
left unsaid by St. John about the Principle of Similitude that is so central to
his thought and so crucial to our understanding of his discussion of mysticism.
He does not, for example, extrapolate upon the mechanics of this principle, and
while this is regrettable, it is also clearly understandable given the nature of
the task he took to himself. We must bear in mind that virtually all his major
works were, despite their exegetical format, written not as speculative
treatises concerned with exploring theoretical principles in mystical theology,
but rather, each of these works must be understood as eminently practical
in both intention and scope; they were written more in the way of enchiridions
for contemplatives in general --- and the Reformed Discalced Carmelite Nuns in
particular --- not as a kind of “Summa Mystica Theolgiae” compiled for scholars,
theologians, and philosophers. This in no way denigrates the meticulous,
forceful and incisive reasoning that is evident in every page of his works ---
and for which, in large part, he would later be acclaimed Doctor of the Church
Universal --- rather, it serves only to delimit the scope of his work, which in
turn enables us to understand why many speculative elements implicit within them
are not subject to the otherwise rigorous examination that the more practical
issues are.
Without an understanding
of the metaphysics implied in the Principle of Similitude, however, we will be
unable to arrive at an understanding of the epistemology involved. So what are
we to make of this rather recondite principle? What basis has this principle in
a coherent metaphysics? Indeed, is there one at all? It certainly sounds
very mystical --- in Lovejoy’s pejorative sense --- that “love makes likeness.”
But how? Since St. John does not elaborate upon this in any strictly analytical
sense, we must look for the answer ourselves. And here, I think, our earlier
discussion will prove helpful to us in avoiding an otherwise purely conjectural
analysis, for the answer, I suggest, is at least implicit in metaphysics we have
already briefly addressed. For St. John of the Cross, man’s fundamental
ontological nature, we had found, is essentially reflective,
consisting as it does in the imago Dei. We had further suggested earlier
that consciousness cannot be understood apart from the data essentially
constituting it a consciousness of. Consciousness and data, empirical or
rational, are always understood copulatively. To speak of someone who is
conscious, but is conscious of nothing, is to utter a contradiction.
Consciousness always implies a consciousness of. And this is another way
of saying that consciousness not simply presupposes data of which it can
subsequently become conscious, but that consciousness is actualized
by data. Apart from data, it remains only, merely, the possibility
of consciousness. It has, as it were, no autonomous being, no actuality apart
from the data in virtue of which it becomes actualized. And this is further to
say that consciousness is essentially a reflective faculty, a faculty
that becomes actualized only upon its imaging data in becoming a consciousness
of that data. A union, we might say, is seen to exist between
consciousness and its data in its becoming a consciousness of that data. The
data, St. John’s argument would seem to suggest, become not merely the condition
of our being conscious, but in fact an integral part of our being conscious.
Man’s reflective ontology, then, is clearly evidenced, at least implicitly for
St. John, in the way in which he is constituted epistemologically --- indeed, in
the most fundamental presuppositions of consciousness
itself.
How is this related to
the problem at hand? How does this bring us any closer to understanding how love
makes likeness as St. John asserts? Well, first of all we have established
something fundamental about man’s epistemology in general: that not merely a
nexus, but a union obtains in the actualization of consciousness by data. But if
consciousness is a consciousness of data, our consciousness is
characterized by that data of which it is conscious --- and this is to
say that a likeness occurs or results between the data and our consciousness of
that data. But we had also said earlier that consciousness characteristically
engages a multiplicity. The intentionality of consciousness is typically diffuse
among a manifold, whether this manifold is yielded through sensory experience or
engaged in the manipulation of rational concepts--- wherein no particular aspect
of that manifold assumes a preponderance exclusive of the
rest.
The Preliminary Role of the Will
But here the role of the
will enters. Seizing upon several aspects of that multiplicity it focuses
consciousness on the few to the exclusion of the many. That is to say, the
scope of consciousness is correspondingly diminished as the will
exercises increasing discrimination in its selection of the data which it in
turn submits to consciousness. As the data diminishes, the focus increases.
Consciousness becomes less and less diffuse among fewer and fewer data; data
which are, we will remember, appropriated to consciousness through the
will. This increasingly discriminatory process may conceivably
continue until the will eventually appropriates only one datum to the exclusion
of the rest. This one datum, then, as the sole object of the will, becomes the
sole focus of consciousness --- which reflects the datum as a consciousness
of that datum. It is not at all inappropriate, then, to say that a
likeness is engendered between the two, between data and consciousness of
the data. Consciousness becomes, in effect, the image of the datum. So
understood, St. John’s thesis suddenly begins to seem a good deal more
creditable than we were initially disposed to view it. But we must carry our
explanation one step further in order to synthesize the
whole.
What, we must ask, first
disposes the will to seize upon one aspect of the manifold of experience to the
exclusion of the rest? St. John is quite unequivocal about this, and the answer
lies in his understanding of the nature of love. It is love, which St. John
variously renders in terms of “affection”, “attachment”, and “desire”, which
first moves the will to appropriate the object
desired.18 But just a moment. Did we not say earlier that the soul
must first will to know and then will to possess what we have willed to
know? Yes, but we also said that acquaintance ( which is quite different
from knowledge ) of necessity preceded the movement of the will. St. John
is very clear upon this:
“... although it is true that the soul
cannot help hearing and seeing and smelling and tasting and touching, this is of
no great import ... for we are not here treating of the lack of things, since
this implies no detachment on the part of the soul if it has a desire for them;
but we are treating of the detachment from them of the taste and desire, for it
is this that leaves the soul free and void of them, although it may have them;
for it is not the things of this world that either occupy the soul or cause it
harm, since they enter it not, but rather the will and desire for them, for it
is these that dwell within it.” 19
St. John is no pure
theorist. He does not deal with man as though abstracted from the world of
common experience. The mystic does not prescind from his surroundings. >From
the phenomena that constitute man’s environment --- objects with which man has
either empirical or rational acquaintance --- the will, in virtue of this
acquaintance, and through desire, that is to say, motivated by
desire, appropriates the object to consciousness. We have already seen that a
kind of union is engendered by the application of consciousness to data in
general, as a consciousness of that data. When, however, the purely
noetic apprehension of an object is augmented by the catalyst of desire,
(attachment, affection), the will inaugurates a process of discrimination in
what it tenders to consciousness, and the exclusionary process, the increased
focus to the exclusion of other data, is directly proportional to the intensity
of the desire. The result is consciousness more or less unified in the object
appropriated by the will --- according to the degree of its desire. A
relatively common experience may suffice to illustrate the point: Our experience
of romantic love is typically one characterized by a desire for, a preoccupation
with, someone --- in a real sense an intensified consciousness of someone that
so completely occupies our awareness that we effectively become the
beloved in the sense that the beloved is comprehensively within us, filling our
thoughts, our awareness, our consciousness --- even to the forgetfulness
of ourselves in our preoccupation with the beloved. We identify with the
beloved, see ourselves in the beloved just as surely as we see them within us.
We may, in a sense, be said to participate in the beloved --- precisely
to the measure or degree of our affection or love for them. St. John therefore
argues that any degree of affection that thus unites us with what we love in the
created order makes us, according to the degree of our desire, affection, or
attachment, more or less contrary to God in our assuming the created character
of what we love in nature and have appropriated to ourselves through the
will.
We can now see more
clearly why a relation of opposition is held by St. John to exist prior to the
soul’s subjection to the rigors of the via negativa. The exercise of the
will, motivated by desire, engenders contrariety through the Principle of
Similitude: the soul is rendered equal and similar to the opposite of God in
nature. In light of this, the problematic of participation becomes increasingly
clear:
“... affection for God and affection for
creatures are contraries, there cannot be contained within one will affection
for creatures and affection for God. For what has the creature to do with the
Creator? What has the sensual to do with the spiritual? Visible with invisible?
Temporal with eternal? ... Wherefore ... no form can be introduced unless the
preceding contrary form is first expelled from the subject, which form while
present is an impediment to the other by reason of the contrariety which the two
have between each other.”
.20
Sensuous negation, or
what St. John calls the “night of the senses”, is therefore absolutely necessary
to that union in which the soul becomes one with God --- not, as we shall see,
through identity, but rather, through created participation. 21 Certainly a good deal more is involved in a adequate
understanding of this concept than we are prepared to set forth and discuss at
this point, but unless we have at the very least a basic understanding of what
is directly involved in the notion of participation we will be unable to
understand much of what will follow in our account. In a noteworthy break from
the scholastic tradition to which St. John is otherwise and fundamentally
faithful, he departs from the prevailing theology which saw the intellect
or reason as the image of God in man.
22 Although he never explicitly formulates it as such, it is
extremely clear from his arguments, especially relative to the Principle of
Similitude, that for St. John the image of God in man lies not in his intellect,
but in his love --- even as the Apostle John tells us that “God is love.”
23 And since God created man in his image 24, love, for St. John, is the created participation of
man in God. This is not to say that reason, or the intellect, does not
in some measure reflect, as the scholastics had maintained, the mind of God and
so constitute an aspect of that image in which man was created. As the image of
God, it would seem that certain --- by no means, all --- aspects of the Absolute
are reflected, however imperfectly, in the ontological composition of man. But
only one, love, is capable of effecting a more than epistemological union of
merely the knower to the Known --- a union fundamentally ontological in the
soul’s not merely knowing, but participating in God. And love, for
St. John, is the only principle capable of attaining to this type of union
which, embracing the soul in its entirety, is ecstatic.
A number of further
implications remain to be drawn from St. John’s treatment of the will as the
seat of love and all the affections, especially in its relation to the Mystical
Thesis and the Principle of Similitude. We find, for example, that while the
will, as the seat of love, is an active principle of union relative to
the created order (as we have seen), it is on the other hand a passive
principle of union in its relation to God. And it is rendered passive by
its subjection to the via negativa according to the demands of the
Mystical Thesis: that is to say, if consciousness is to be unified in God, the
will must cease appropriating contrariety to itself through the exercise of the
will --- whose sole activity subsequent to its purgation through the via
negativa is itself rendered entirely negative in willing not to will. The
Principle of Similitude coupled with the Mystical Thesis, therefore, figures
largely in the transition to union and serves to underscore the
cooperative effort necessary to the realization of that union, for
although it is ultimately God alone who both initiates and consummates this
union, the soul nevertheless cooperates toward this “union of likeness”
25, as St. John sometimes calls it, by passing through the
crucible of the via negativa and removing every impediment to union by
eliminating every contrariety to God. Having done so, the soul remains passively
disposed to the divine initiative and through the exclusive love which the it
bears toward God alone --- the love which is the image become explicit --- the
soul, St. John contends, will become equal and similar to God. This rather
startling conclusion, however, remains to be properly explained later in our
examination of the Night of the Spirit.
The Two-Edged WILL: Propadeutic or
Impediment?
The contemplative, then,
in his quest for union must first strive to empty his will relative to the
created order. Exercised only in the love of God, and detached in the way of its
love, desires, and affections from the order of nature, the created will is thus
prepared to become transformed into the will of God 26 both through the absence of contrariety to God in the form
of nature --- that is, through transformation negatively considered ---
and through that similitude and equality generated through its singular love of
God, or transformation positively considered. The created will, assimilated into
the will of God in the state of infused contemplation, is then indistinguishable
from God’s own will, for in and of itself it is totally passive, having become,
as it were, a created expression of the uncreated will of the
Absolute:
“ [ the soul ] must cast away all strange
gods --- namely, all strange affections and attachments it must purify itself of
the remnants which the desires aforementioned have left in the soul in order to
reach the summit of this high mount, it must have changed its garments which God
will change for it, from old to new, by giving it a new love of God in God, the
will being now stripped of all its old desires and human pleasures ... So that
its operation, which before was human, has become divine, which is that is
attained in the state of union ... “ 27
Possessing nothing of
itself in the way of desires and affections, the will remains passive and
totally receptive to the will of God which, as other to the negated in nature
--- a nature no longer appropriated throough the will --- is that alone in which
it is possible for the created will to be subsequently
exercised.
But does this mean, then,
that the soul in ecstasy is incapable of sin? This would appear to be the
logical conclusion if the will is rendered completely passive. Are we to
understand, in other words, that, given no act directly attributable to the
created will, the soul is therefore no longer liable to sin? Is any subsequent
act, then, deserving of approbation? Indeed, is it still free, with all
the moral and deontological considerations that the notion of a free will
entails? In regard to the second question, --- concerning the soul’s liability
to sin --- a careful reading of the text would reveal that St. John’s answer
would most emphatically be, no. And for this reason: the soul in the state of
infused contemplation becomes, as we have said, a created expression of the
uncreated will of God. In its total passivity, every movement of the will is
directly ascribable to God. And since God is incapable of peccancy, the soul so
moved by God --- and, it is important to emphasize, only in the state of
ecstatic union--- is, likewise, incapable of sin. This obviously does not
mean that the mystic who has attained to sporadic union can no longer sin, for
it is also the case that the state of ecstasy in this life is characteristically
brief, and upon his return from ecstasy the contemplative, despite the obvious
predilection of God, nevertheless remains in his created humanity liable to sin
through the penalty that inescapably accrues to mankind at large through the sin
of Adam; a penalty from which none, even the most holy, are held to be exempt.
Only when that state of ecstasy --- which the mystic now only intermittently
realizes --- becomes indefectible before the beatific vision acquired after
death, will the soul no longer be susceptible to sin. Mystical union is, after
all, as St. John repeatedly states, a foretaste of heaven, and not an
indefectible state on earth.
Bi-Dimensionality, Free Will and Impeccancy: The Mystic as
Man
In reply to the remaining
questions --- to wit, is the soul yet free in the state of ecstasy, and are its
acts within that state deserving of approbation --- St. John’s answer must be
yes, and for the following reasons. In acceding to the will of God, which the
soul recognizes as the sovereign good , and that in which the good universally
consists, the soul freely consents to the exercise not only of that will
but of every good in which that will consists. Among these are the good
of the soul, which preeminently lies in its conformity to the will of God. But
the notion of the good as it relates to the created will specifically, cannot
prescind from the notion of freedom, both as a good in itself, and as a
necessary condition of the moral soul. In choosing perfect conformity to the
will of God, then, the soul simultaneously chooses that freedom apart from which
the soul is neither good nor moral. The created will, then, being subsumed into
the divine will, nevertheless remains distinct and free. Furthermore, it is not
so much that the passive will ceases to will, as that it ceases to will what is
contrary to God --- its will is, in its created nature,
both parallel to and identical with, the will of God. That
is to say, it wills not merely that God should move it, but that its will should
freely coincide with the will of God. The volition of the soul, then, remains
intact --- for the created will so exercised in choosing to coincide with the
will of God is in itself a free act of ratification, appropriating as its own
the will of God to which it perfectly corresponds through an act of free will.
And this is simply another way of saying that the created will
participates in the uncreated will of God. And since the appropriation of
the divine will is a free act of the created will, it may indeed be recognized
as meritorious, as is every act ascribable to the free will which wills the
good.
The precise mechanics
involved in this transition are, regrettably, left obscure by St. John --- but
not so obscure that some very clear inferences are not available to us. It is a
basic Christian premise that man as essentially bidimensional. He is
possessed of a body and a soul. He is composed of matter and spirit. By and
large rational, he is also sensuous. As intrinsic a component to his being as
natural, is the supernatural. His existence is enacted in time but consummated
in eternity. Nature, in short, subsuming under itself body, matter, and time,
constitutes only one dimension of bidimensional man. An inverse metaphysical
relation exists between the natural and the supernatural such that the more
attenuated the natural dimension of his being, the more amplified the
supernatural dimension; as the one recedes the other becomes increasingly
manifest. Any categorical negation of this nature, then, would
effectively result in a unilateral suspension of the corresponding natural
dimension of man. And this means that the soul in having been negated to the
natural dimension of its being relative to the will, becomes, with
respect to this particular faculty, necessarily supra-natural; that is to
say, it is reduced exclusively to the remaining supernatural dimension of this
bidimensional faculty in having passed beyond nature. But to pass beyond nature
is also to pass into the other of nature --- which, on the one hand is
spirit. Thus we find that the will, as described by St. John, is transformed
from what he calls the sensuous into the spiritual; this erstwhile suppressed
dimension of man’s spiritual being now gradually emerging into existential
relief. On the other hand, however, the other to nature, considered absolutely,
was seen to be God. Thus in passing beyond nature the will, while yet remaining
distinct from, is equally and simultaneously transformed into, the will of God.
This admittedly requires some sorting out. The first level of negation we had
seen to consist in the negation of nature according to the will in which
the soul ceases to appropriate anything in the created order according to its
desires and affections. We had already briefly touched upon this. The
second level of negation, however, implicitly follows from the first, and
this is the negation of the will according to nature in which the will in
the state of negativity is effectively suspended relative to its natural
function, thus becoming the functional expression of another in its subsequent
activity --- and that agency, St. John is clear, of which the will becomes the
functional expression is God:
“... this Divine union consists in the
soul’s total transformation, according to the will, in the will of God, so that
there may be naught in the soul that is contrary to the will of God, but that in
all and through all, its movement may be that of the will of God
alone.” 28
We can now more clearly
see that in negating the contrary to God in nature, the will becomes
preeminently, if only passively, predisposed to the divine infusion. In being
transformed from the sensuous into the spiritual, the will is rendered more
proximate to God --- and in the state of passivity (presuming, of course,
that divine election that results in the actuality of union) subsequent movement
of the will proceeds from God. As we shall later see, this entire process
ultimately presupposes the transformation of the will into its corresponding
theological virtue in the unified and integrated love of
God.29 In this state of transformation, the created will
consummately participates in the uncreated will of God. This transition,
however, is not accomplished without penalty. Very clearly, a transformation of
this sort entails a privation of man’s being --- which, in its divinely
constituted nature, is a being bidimensional --- and every privation of being,
of that perfection connatural to any being, will, despite its divine provenance,
and its movement to greater perfection still, be experienced as an evil, as
surely the pain of this transition, often described at length by St. John, is
experienced by the mystic. It is, however, a redemptive suffering in a darkness
about to broach upon light. But this is only realized in the very last stages of
mystical union and already presumes the complete integration of the faculties in
the love of God, which we shall examine at length in subsequent
chapters.
1 AMC
1.5.2
2 AMC
1.4.1
3
AMC
1.4.4
4 AMC
1.5.1
5 AMC
1.5.2
6
AMC
1.5.4
7 AMC
2.5.4
8 AMC
1.4.2
9 AMC 1.4.2; cf.
ST Ques. 48 Art.3, also St. Augustine, Enchiridion, 14 (Patrologiae
Latinae, 32, 1347)
10 AMC
1.5.2
11 1 Cor.
13.12
12 AMC
1.5.2
13 cf. AMC
2.8.4-5; 1.4.1-4 etc.
14 cf. AMC
3.4.1-2; 2.12.3-4
15 AMC
2.12.3-4
16 AMC
1.9.1
17 AMC 1.4.3-4;
also cf. 2.18.5; SC 15.4, 21.5, + 23.5. Emphasis added. This, of course, is
essentially a reformulation of the doctrine articulated much earlier by the
Pseudo-Dionysius that “it is of the nature of love to change a man into that
which he loves.”
18 cf. ST Q.20
art.1
19
AMC
1.3.4
20 AMC
1.6.1-2
21 AMC 2.5.4+7;
2.20.5; SC 11.6+7; LFL 2.30
22
cf. ST Q.93
art.2 In this respect, St. John of the Cross is much more in line with St.
Bernard than, say, the great mystical writers of the School of St.
Victor.
23 1 Jn
4.8
24
Gen.
1.27
25
AMC
2.5.3
26
AMC 1.11.2+3;
2.5.3+4
27 AMC
1.5.7
28
AMC 1.11.2+3,
also cf. 2.5.3+4
29 cf.
II
The Role
of UNDERSTANDING in the Philosophy of St. John of the
Cross
The Via Negativa
Book The Second of the Ascent of Mount Carmel is of
particular importance to us in our exploring the possibilities of developing a
coherent mystical epistemology. While, until now, we have tried to avoid some of
the tedium inevitably involved in a commentary of this sort, the demand for
accountability --- within the greater demand for coherence --- will sometimes
require a somewhat detailed analysis of certain features of mystical doctrine.
But this type of patient analysis will, in the long run, serve to illuminate a
sometimes obscure and often abstruse metaphysics, enabling us to answer some
very fundamental objections which we are likely to encounter further on. It is
the fundamentals of St. John’s metaphysics which we seek after here. And these
in turn will lead us on to examine some of the more explicit epistemological
features of St. John’s account.
The profound disparity
between created nature and God which was seen to characterize the relation
between the unnegated will --- the will prior to its subjection to the via
negativa --- and God, is brought to critical relief in St. John’s extensive
treatment of the second faculty of the soul, understanding. This is not
to say that the same imperatives do not apply equally to each faculty, for the
via negativa is a universal feature throughout the various movements
toward mystical union. In St. John’s analysis of the understanding, however, we
have much clearer insight into some of the metaphysical difficulties to be
overcome in a coherent account of mysticism. As the extraordinary object of
ordinary understanding, God is essentially opaque to the natural intellect for
reasons which by now may already be anticipated: God and the created intellect
inform radically different and incommensurable categories --- the nature, if you
will, of the one is antipodal to the other. All, then, which the understanding
can think, all that it is capable of conceiving in its natural capacity, is
categorically, diametrically, opposed to the reality of God as He is in himself
apart from the mediating and modifying categories of
understanding:
“... all that the imagination can imagine
and the understanding can receive and understand in this life is not, nor can it
be, a proximate means of union with God. For if we speak of natural things,
since understanding can understand naught save that which is contained within,
and comes under the category of, forms and imaginings of things that are
received through the senses, the which things, we have said, cannot serve as
means, it can make no use of natural intelligence 1 ... all that can be understood by the
understanding, that can be tasted by the will, and that can be invented by the
imagination is most unlike to God and bears no proportion to Him ... 2
And thus a soul
is greatly impeded from reaching this high estate of union with God, when it
clings to any understanding or feeling or imagination or appearance or will or
manner of its own ... For as we say, the goal which it seeks lies beyond all
this, yea, even beyond the highest thing that can be known or experienced, and
thus a soul must pass beyond everything to unknowing.” 3
Since all that the
faculty of understanding can conceivably think, or through its purely synthetic
activity possibly imagine, is, eo ipso, not God, the soul aspiring to
knowledge of the Absolute must proceed paradoxically --- through a
process of unknowing --- a process, we shall find, that will ultimately
translate the natural faculty of understanding into its corresponding
theological virtue of faith. The epistemological doctrine of unknowing
is, of course, but one of the many iridescent aspects of the via negativa
which finds its clearest expression in Book One of the
Ascent:
“In order to arrive at pleasure in
everything
Desire to have pleasure
in nothing.
In order to arrive at
possessing everything,
Desire to possess
nothing.
In order to arrive at
being everything
Desire to be
nothing.
In order to arrive at
knowing everything,
Desire to know
nothing.
In order to arrive at
that wherein thou hast no pleasure,
Thou must go by a way
wherein thou hast no pleasure.
In order to arrive at
that which thou knowest not
Thou must go by a way
thou knowest not.
In order to arrive at
that which thou possest not,
Thou must go by a way
that thou possesst not.
In order to arrive at
that which thou art not,
Thou must go through
that which thou art not.
When thy mind dwells
upon anything,
Thou art ceasing to cast
thyself upon the All.
For in order to pass
from the all to the All,
Thou hast to deny
thyself wholly in all.
And when thou comest to
possess it wholly,
Thou must possess it
without desiring anything.
For, if thou wilt have
anything in having all,
Thou hast not thy
treasure purely in God.” 4
Despite its largely
negative format, clearly illustrated above, the via negativa nevertheless
remains not only a viable, but indeed the only, “way” of arriving at the
Absolute. And if it is a difficult way for the contemplative to travel, it is no
less a difficult route for the epistemologist to map, for all its signs, every
cue, each marker, is negative. It is not unlike a series of signs that might
say, not “Paris this way”, but rather, “Paris not this way.” That is well
and good, but the traveler will most assuredly at once ask, “Well, then, if not
this way, which way?” To which every sign he subsequently encounters
simply answers, “not this way” .The via negativa is much like this. It
may be seen as a kind of epistemological compass that indicates not where
to go, but where not to go; it is the negative of a map outlining the
mystical terrain that tells you not so much how to get to the Absolute
azimuth, but, rather, how not to get there. In essence, it is a
cartographical paradox. It is clear, then, and most expedient that some other
principle of direction must be invoked. Some principle that will provide us with
a measure of certitude, not necessarily apart from the negative prescripts we
have acquired thus far --- which of themselves are extremely useful to us in
disabusing us of error in finding our way --- but which, while according with
them, is more precise, or perhaps better yet, affirmative in
direction.
A brief glance in
retrospect may prove helpful. In the opening sequences of Book One of the
Ascent, St. John discussed the night of the senses relative to the will.
There we found that the disparity between God and created nature emphasized the
lack of proportion, of commensurability, between God and the soul in its
relation to God through created nature, and in so doing demonstrated the
inherent impossibility of a sensuous apprehension of God. And the conclusion, of
course, was that if God is to be apprehended at all, he must be apprehended
extra-naturally; not through a sensuous manifold accessible to the will
--- nor, as St. John will now arggue, through any conceptualization
available through ordinary understanding. And much as we had found in the case
of the will, a transition is required which will inevitably result in the
positing of a theological correlate in which the function of understanding is
explicitly suppressed through what St. John sees as the epistemological
negativity of faith. Negativity, as we had seen, implies the absence of
contrariety; so in stating that the three theological virtues --- faith, hope,
and love --- render the soul “proximate” to God, St. John is actually saying
that each of these virtues are essentially characterized by negativity --- a
negativity essentially signifying the absence of contrariety to God.
Proximity and non-contrariety, then, are interchangeable terms in
the mystical vocabulary of St. John.
For St. John, faith
explicitly transcends the limitations of sense and understanding, and in so
doing simultaneously transcends the inherent limitations of nature and
reason.
5 The limitations implicit in
nature are, by now, quite obvious: in every respect it is finite. As
such, not only is nature ontologically distinct from God, but in its very
finitude and limitation it can never yield veridical knowledge of God who is
infinite and unlimited. But the limitations of reason are less clear. In our
introduction we suggested that God, and indeed the universe of experience
itself, is not exhaustively considered in its intelligible dimensions alone;
that any given item in experience affords something more in the amplitude of its
being than the merely rational dimensions to be elicited from it. Within reason
itself, however, we discern even more fundamental limitations, and it is these
that are of particular interest to us. For the most part, the mechanics involved
in the limitations of reason are left unaddressed by St. John. Certainly is not
the case that he was unable to articulate these limitations in greater detail,
for St. John was, we had noted earlier, extremely well versed in scholastic
philosophy. Still less warrant do we have to believe that he presumed them known
in the mind of his readers who were, by and large, professed religious, and not
necessarily scholars. In reading St. John, and I shall emphasize this point time
and again, it is essential to bear in mind that he did not understand himself to
be writing a philosophic treatise, still less a systematic organon in
speculative mysticism, but rather an enchiridion for contemplatives, a fact we
had pointed out earlier and will, no doubt, find it necessary to point out
again. One goal, and one goal only, lay incessantly before St. John and
everything else palled in significance before it: union with God. His own, and
that of others. His readers did not need to know the law of the excluded middle
in order to make a practical choice between mutually exclusive moral or
spiritual ends. Less abstruse and far more effective means were available to
them. These mechanics are, however, of interest to us --- indeed, vital to us if
we are to understand the epistemological dimensions of the mystical
experience.
So what can we infer from
St. John’s discussion of the faculty of understanding, especially as it pertains
to reason? It is, first of all, I think, fairly clear from his own exposition,
that reason essentially functions upon, is limited to, and therefore requires a
manifold --- a manifold which is ontologically possible only in the
universe of created nature, 6 for God of himself is one and simple. In requiring a
manifold, reason is limited in three ways: first, and most obviously, by its
limitation to a manifold itself --- that is to say, by its inability to function
apart from a matrix of sheer multiplicity. The second limitation discernible in
reason, concerns its scope. The manifold which reason addresses is comprised of
the universe of finite entities broadly called nature, and both objects and
concepts (the mind no less than matter) finite in nature, can never yield
infinite, that is to say, unlimited information. Simply put, the synthetic and
analytic activities of reason are incapable of eliciting more than is
ontologically available in the finite data of experience. Reason, then, unable
to transcend, is therefore limited to, an inherently exhaustible (finite)
dimension of being. The last, but not the least, limitation of reason lies in
the fact that it is ineluctably temporal --- the discursions of reason are
thoroughly conditioned by time which is presupposed and implicit in all its
functions and activities. Time is the underlying medium through which the
successive movements of discursive reason are enabled, enacted; and it is
time which constrains reason from apprehending the simple simultaneity of
existence. However comprehensive its purview, reason is limited by time to
discrete and successive moments in all its analytic and synthetic
activity.
We have established,
then, that reason requires a manifold which by definition consists of a
plurality --- plurality of necessarily finite entities, each limited and
distinguishable one from another. Without plurality and differentiation, then,
reason could not be discursive, that is, passing from one aspect under rational
consideration to another in the dialectic we understand to be reason ---
it would, in fact, altogether and at once cease to be discursive. Which is to
say that reason in its discursive capabilities would effectively be not so much
abolished, as suspended. And this, in St. John’s account, is precisely what
occurs to reason in relation to God in the mystical experience. It
remains inoperative, suspended, as it were, blindly staring into the Absolute,
simply for the fact that God is One and simple, unchanging and eternal. Not
reason, but the utility of reason, then, is, for St. John, forever abolished in
the transcendence of plurality.
The Notion of “Proximate” Union
In transcending the
limitations of nature and reason, St. John further argues, the soul then enters
the state of what he calls proximate union with God
7 through having negated within itself the other to God in
nature and reason. Considered carefully, this state of proximate union may be
seen to follow for two reasons, although St. John only adverts to one. First of
all, in passing beyond the finite, the soul quite logically --- that is
to say, necessarily --- passes into the not-finite, or the infinite, and,
according to the same logic,
in passing beyond
limitation, the soul passes into the unlimited. And in so doing --- in passing
into the infinite and the unlimited --- the soul enters a state that is
proximate to God inasmuch as God in himself is infinite and unlimited.
This is not to say that the soul itself becomes infinite and unlimited in
this transition --- in a Christian metaphysics it can never become so: it’s
created nature remains unviolated and unchanged despite the transition. What
has changed, however, is the nature of the experience encountered
by the mystic, one now characterized not by the familiar plurality, finitude,
limitation and differentiation that are typical components in the experience of
the created order. The mystic now, for the first time, encounters,
experiences the infinite and the unlimited. Let us look at this more
closely, and for the sake of clarity segregate the following line of reasoning
for a more detailed examination:
We had said that in
passing beyond the finite, the soul necessarily passes into the not-finite. Now
that which is not-finite is either nothing or infinite. It is nothing if
it is not-finite and not-infinite. It is infinite if it is not-finite and
not-nothing. But the soul is not-infinite and not-nothing---which is to say that
the soul is finite. Moreover, that which is not-limited is either nothing or
unlimited. It is nothing if it is not-limited and not-unlimited. It is unlimited
if it is not-limited and not-nothing. But the soul is not-unlimited and
not-nothing --- which is to say the soul is limited. We have, then, the created
soul which is finite and limited. In passing beyond the finite and the limited
in created nature, the soul must encounter either nothing or the infinite. In
either event, it will be the not-finite.
Further elaboration will,
I think, make this rather concise formulation more readily understood. Whatever
is, is either finite or infinite. If it is neither, it is nothing, for
everything that is, or can conceivably be, is either finite or infinite. There
is no conceivable third alternative. Obviously, then, the concept “nothing”
pertains neither to the finite or the infinite. Were nothing infinite
then there would be absolutely nothing, either finite or infinite --- for the
term infinite would be predicated of nothing. Conversely, were we to say that
the infinite is nothing, we would involve ourselves in a hopeless tautology. We
cannot, therefore, coherently speak of nothing as infinite. Our difficulty in
apprehending this stems, I suggest, from our inclination to render the concept
nothing spatially: we tend to conceptualize it not as nothing, but as
empty space, a kind of amorphous negative configuration coterminous
with and indefinitely configured by something, relative
to which it is nothing; we are inclined to see it as the possible place
of something else; in effect, something devoid of something else, when in
fact it remains the absence of everything --- which is another way of saying
nothing. If, on the other hand, what we are considering is infinite, it clearly
is not finite, for we mean by the infinite that which is not finite; nor
can it be nothing, as we have just seen. The soul, on the other hand, is
something, and not nothing, and it very clearly is finite in every aspect, and
not infinite.
Now, if what we have
argued in fact is the case, then a good deal more about the nature of the
contemplative’s experience prior to union becomes somewhat clearer. The
natural or created soul is, as we have seen, finite and limited; and as
we had further seen, no commensurability obtains between the finite and the
infinite, the limited and the unlimited. The natural or created soul, then, has
no epistemological capacity for the infinite as the not-finite that is
not-nothing; it is incapable --- qua created --- of
experiencing the infinite, (except under the species of the
pseudo-infinite in number, etc., which we addressed earlier). But the created
soul does have a capacity for experiencing the infinite as the
not-finite that is not-infinite, that is to say, of experiencing the
infinite as nothing --- and it is this experience which, for the mystic,
constitutes the dark night of the soul: not only is the soul in utterly
unfamiliar metaphysical terrain, but the topography itself has metamorphosed
into utter nothingness. Moreover, even were the
natural soul capable of experiencing or epistemologically
addressing the infinite, the experience of the oneness of the infinite, the
unlimited, the undifferentiated --- is no less effectively the experience of
nothingness. The senses coupled with reason would falter and ultimately fail in
their inability to grasp what cannot, by virtue of infinite magnitude, be
grasped, apprehended, understood. The very mechanisms of reason and sense,
relying upon limitation, finitude, and differentiation as the very tangents to
comprehension --- individuating characteristics now no longer available ---
would default into suspension. Natural faculties no longer suffice, for nature
finds itself at the bourne between created and Uncreated being, at the outermost
margin, the ontological periphery of creation where the gulf between man
and God is sheer infinity, and as such, an ontic chasm, the primeval nothingness
out of which man and the cosmos was created ex nihilo. St. John speaks of
this experience as a terrible one, unparalleled by any other. We might say that
in some small measure it may be likened to the experience of a man who, awaking
from a dream filled with familiar images, finds himself not only in total
darkness, but amidst incomprehensible emptiness, possessing no frame of
reference whatever, nothing to see, nothing to touch, no sound, no smell, no
sense of direction, no orientation. His experience is essentially one of
complete sensory abstraction and total noetic suspension, of absolute
undifferentiation. The extreme consternation, even terror, that such an
experience is likely to provoke may, to some degree, resemble the plight of the
mystic who has entered the antechamber of the Absolute. In this sense, darkness
is a metaphor for infinity; and the awakening, the inauguration of the dark
night of the soul.
Proximity vs.
Union
Up to this point we had
seen that the soul, as a consequence of having transcended the limitations of
nature and reason, occupies a state proximate to God inasmuch as God in himself
is infinite and unlimited. While the soul in this state of proximity possesses
no contrariety to God, this state of itself, St. John is clear, does not suffice
to bring it to union. Rather, it makes the soul merely receptive to the
divine infusion; metaphysically disposed to the possibility of infused
contemplation. At this stage, the soul is brought to the extremity of its being,
to the irreducible, the most fundamental dimension of its ontology --- beyond
which lies only extinction. While it is indefectibly the image of God, at this
point it neither reflects God whom it only anticipates, nor created nature which
it has transcended. It is the possibility of both and the actuality of neither.
In its sheer reflective ontology, it is like the image in a mirror possessing no
actuality in itself apart from being the possibility of the reflection of
something else; a mirror before which no image passes except the infinite toward
which it is poised and which it apprehends as nothing. In this state, in
reflecting nothing, it has no contrariety whatever to God, and inasmuch as it
possesses nothing in the way of contrariety, it is understood as being proximate
to God. So much is clear from our previous discussion.
The ontological
implications of this argument, however, are two-fold and reciprocal: on the
purely metaphysical level, the soul, St. John has argued, upon
transcending the finite and the limited becomes proximate to God. So much is
clear. In this moment of transcendence, however, it appears that something
doxastic emerges, not simply concomitantly, but logically, which is to
say, necessarily, from this metaphysical transition.
St. John, we have seen,
very clearly maintains that the soul achieves proximate union with God
following the negation of nature and reason. He does not state why it
follows, merely that it does in fact follow. A closer examination, however,
suggests that the utility of reason and sense --- relative to objects of created
nature apprehensible through the will and understanding --- have already been
abolished through transcendence, or negation, and appear to be, as a
consequence of this transition, now supplanted by the theological virtue of
faith --- which St. John argues, is also the state of proximate
union with God.
The problem we now
confront, however, is that if we hold faith to be contingent upon this
essentially metaphysical transition --- as the argument might appear to
suggest --- we divest faith of its supernatural character: it loses its
provenance in God and becomes immediately subsumed under nature. It is a
logical, and therefore necessary moment in a concatenation of events
occurring within a clearly defined and purely metaphysical matrix. Faith, so
understood, is not concomitant with transition, but is the
terminus of the transition itself. It is not concurrent with the negation
of nature and reason, it is indistinguishable from it; it is, in fact,
synonymous with it. It becomes, in a word, metaphysically legislated ---
apart from any divine and free dispensation. As an erstwhile theological virtue,
it immediately ceases as both theological and a virtue.
How can this be? The line
of reasoning strikes us as sound, but is nevertheless deeply disconsonant with
the most profound theological principles from which the impetus to ecstatic
union emerges. Compelling as this argument may appear, it is nonetheless
subreptive as we will soon see. It is, however, also extremely instructive, for
it serves to underscore the complexities, as well as the tensions, that have
often subverted many efforts to articulate a coherent mystical doctrine that is
both consistent with the canons of reason and consonant with accepted
theological tenets. The question, no less, still stands. Let us examine it more
closely.
Transition or Translation?
We had stated earlier
that we have observed something of the nature of reciprocity in this
moment of transition, two distinct levels of proximity that, I will now suggest,
converge --- rather than
conflate. The distinction is critical, for it is precisely at this
juncture that much of the confusion and misconception surrounding so many
attempts at explicating the notion of mystical union occurs. The metaphysical
momentum that has culminated at this crucial ontological point subreptively
lends itself to a spurious interpretation of what is a
transition in being as a translation
of being; as a continuum of something metaphysically legislated, and not
as a breach in that continuum through an autonomous leap of faith. Even while
concurrent with it, faith entirely prescinds from this metaphysical momentum as
a leap from the natural to the supernatural, from what is inherent in nature to
what is inherent in faith.
At this point we stand,
as it were, before the ontological chasm to which metaphysics has brought us and
past which it can offer us nothing more legitimate, and we instinctively blench
before what metaphysics legislates as the terminus of being. Metaphysics, we
recognize, cannot make the transition to nothing, it has reached a point in
extremis from which alone the
soul cannot leap off to extinction. But in offering us translation, the
translation of being, instead of its transition, it is offering us something
counterfeit: it is offering us the nothing from which it shrinks, the nothing in
which the translation of being is no more than the termination of
being, the very point beyond which it cannot pass without abandoning the
ontological infrastructure upon which it stands. Only faith can make that leap.
And the supreme irony is that each essentially ratifies the other and both equally culminate in what appears
to be the terminus of being. The Dark Night.
So what, precisely is
occurring here? On the one hand, the state of proximity to God is achieved
through transcendence (of the finite) on a purely metaphysical level. On the
other hand, it is, as we have said, equally attained through the theological
virtue of faith. Something more than mere congruity, or even concomitance,
appears to occur; something deeply implicative of both mutuality and
complementarity. It would appear that either faith corroborates the metaphysics,
or that the metaphysics corroborates faith. The answer, I suggest, is both,
inasmuch as faith implicitly accords with what metaphysics explicity states.
It is not merely of the
nature of faith, but of the essence of faith to assent to the very same
propositions we find emerging from the metaphysics, not, however, as demanded by
metaphysics, but as demanded by faith. In other words, this is not to understand
faith as proceeding from metaphysics, any more than it is to understand
the metaphysics proceeding from faith. At the point of convergence, however, it
is imperative to understand that the deliverances of each are indistinguishable,
for both arrive at the same impenetrable epicenter that is infinite, unlimited,
and absolute. Nor is it simply coincidental that at precisely this point of
convergence we arrive at the opacity of reason.
We are now, I think, in a
position to understand that this reciprocity which we observe does not in any
way abrogate or violate the unique integrity of what is either ontological or
doxastic --- a superficial bifurcation to the mystic at this point--- but
rather, is axiomatic of the traditional concept of nature cooperating with
grace. What we find, in the end, is not the one through the abrogation of the
other, but instead, a mutual corroboration of each at that critical point of
convergence that St. John understands as the state of proximity to the Absolute,
To God.
The Role of Faith and Reason in the Transition to Proximity
and Union
But how do we understand
faith to be an implicit consequence of this transition? To answer this,
let us look for a moment more carefully at the nature of faith. By faith we
generally understand that theological virtue, divinely infused, which is
cognitive in nature, and which expresses itself in the terms of clearly
defined articles of belief --- not knowledge --- independent of any
empirical acquaintance with the object in which belief is invested ---
specifically, God. The cognitive dimension of faith, in other words, is
doxastic rather than
noetic. Faith makes no appeal to reason. The object, or articles of faith
may be entirely consonant with reason. On the other hand, they may
completely transcend, not simply the canons, but the very capabilities of
reason --- and yet do so without abrogating them, since grace either perfects or
exceeds, but never violates nature. While faith is essentially cognitive in
nature relative to these articles of belief, the articles themselves are
supernatural in character. And the legitimate province of reason, we had
argued earlier, lies not in the supernatural, but in the matrix of nature,
specifically created nature experienced in terms of plurality and finitude. The
faculty of reason, then, has only limited access to the articles of faith, and
only inasmuch as these articles, among themselves --- prescinding
entirely from the question of their authenticity, that is to say, considered
formally, and not materially--- demonstrate a coherence that accords with the
canons of logic, of reason. Insofar as logical coherence is discernible among
the relation of ideas that constitute the articles of belief around which the
notion of faith revolves, reason formally ratifies faith, finds the
relation of the ideas of faith to be consistent with reason, although it makes
no pronouncement on the authenticity of the articles themselves. And to this
limited extent, faith is found to be consonant with reason, or perhaps better
yet, reason is found to be consonant with faith.
But faith also
transcends reason, as we had said. In passing from that realm of finitude
and plurality in which alone reason is capable of being discursively exercised,
the only cognitive capacity remaining to the soul --- with no data available to
sense or reason --- pertains to these articles of belief --- in other words,
faith --- which the soul maintains despite empirical evidence to the contrary:
the nothingness which the soul encounters on the brink of infinity. That some
form of cognition remains is indisputable, otherwise we should hold the
soul to be incognitive, which is to say unconscious, and this very clearly is
not the case with the mystic. If anything, what we find is an intensified state
of consciousness. It is, moreover, equally clear from our previous discussion
that this form of cognition cannot be reason. So what alternative remains?
Confronted with that before which reason defaults into suspension, faith
--- independent of reason and uninformedd by the senses --- remains cognitive in
the form of articles of belief which, themselves supernatural in character, were
never dependent upon reason or sense to begin with --- and thus remains fully as
cognitive as it was prior to the transcendence of nature and reason. In this
sense, then, faith is seen to follow the negation of nature and reason. But that
faith transcends nature, as St. John further implies, seems at first a
rather odd notion, and yet it nevertheless follows from and is consistent with
the overall logic of St. John’s account. Faith, we might say, transcends nature
through reason as that plurality of finite entities which the exercise of
discursive reason requires and therefore presumes. In transcending reason, then,
faith has already transcended nature as implicit within
reason.
As we may anticipate, the
imperative of faith will continue to be not only a significant, but a
multifaceted feature of the mystical doctrine which meticulously unfolds before
us in the opening chapters of the Ascent. Nor can we prescind entirely
from all the concomitant issues which faith touches upon if our epistemological
account is to be complete. For example, St. John argues that the soul not only
transcends time, finitude, and reason through its subjection to the via
negativa and the subsequent positing of faith; but through this same faith
the soul equally circumvents diabolical impediments to union as
well.8 While this issue may at first appear to be only incidental
to any strictly epistemological analysis, a closer examination reveals
otherwise, for we find that St. John’s treatment of diabolical deception
effectively serves to underscore a very fundamental epistemological issue
concerning the notion of error --- which is by no means incidental to any
examination of the notion of understanding.
Let us pursue the point.
Through faith, St. John has argued, the soul has passed beyond understanding. So
much at least is immediately clear from St. John’s account. However, as a
consequence of this transition, that is to say, in passing beyond
understanding, the soul has simultaneously, and for two reasons, passed beyond
--- is no longer subject to --- the posssibility of error. And for the
following reasons: first of all, the notion of error exclusively, if obviously,
pertains to the faculty of understanding: it is, fundamentally, a consequence of
misunderstanding, consisting in the intellectual assent to defective
propositions delivered by, or illegitimate conclusions drawn from, discursive
reasoning. But reason has been transcended --- and along with it, the errors to
which defective reasoning is liable. That is to say, the possibility of error as
a consequence of misunderstanding has been abolished as implicit within
the utility of understanding itself which has already been
negated.
Inerrancy and Impedimence
It is important to
further understand that the second reason that faith, for St. John, is not held
to be liable to error rests upon the source itself of the infused
theological virtue of faith, which is God. The articles of belief constituting
the virtue of faith have, for the mystic, no less a guarantor than God who, as
both object and author of the articles of faith, is understood to be not simply
the source of truth, but Truth itself. 9 So much, I think, is immediately clear from a cursory
rendering of St. John’s understanding of faith. But the question nevertheless
remains, why in fact is it so pressing, so vitally important for the mystic to
be free of error? Or more precisely, how is error to be understood as
constituting an impediment to union? The answer for St. John, of course, is
already implicit in an adequate understanding of the Divine nature itself. Aside
from the simple misdirection --- which is of no small consequence to the mystic
--- which liability to error affords, errror is, quite simply, a form of
contrariety to God who is Truth. While the mystic clearly has, in the form of
the infused virtues, the assistance of God who invites the soul to the ecstatic
state of union as a foretaste of the eternal felicity awaiting the faithful in
heaven --- it is also the case that the contemplative confronts an ancient
antagonist who wishes to frustrate, confuse, and deceive the soul in its efforts
to achieve union with God. And this, of course, is the devil who, within the
Christian tradition, is preeminently understood as a liar and the father of
lies.10 St. John argues, however --- and this is the critical issue
--- that diabolical artifice can only bee exercised over the soul through its
attachment to created things.11 In transcending created nature, in having extinguished all
attachment to the created order, the soul is then effectively brought beyond the
pale of diabolical influence --- and is therefore no longer subject to error
instigated by the devil.
If this concern strikes
the contemporary mind as quaint, it is, I suggest, only symptomatic of a more
prevailing contemporary defection from the supernatural at large, and apart from
which not only mysticism, but Christianity itself remains, in its most
fundamental essence, incomprehensible. The two components of every error, then,
either defective reasoning or diabolical malice, cease to be impediments to
union in the soul’s having transcended created nature and reason. Quite
practically, moreover, any journey --- especially the journey of the soul to God
--- whose course and direction, compass and map, are not free of error, will
not, cannot, bring the traveler home. However he would that his bearings were
correct, without truth as the declination to compass and map, the mystical
terrain remains unrecognizable, and the wayfarer remains lost and without hope
of achieving his end.
Truth, Faith, and Dogma: Triad or
Trilogy?
Truth for the mystic,
however, is inseparable from, and inextricably bound up with, faith --- and
faith, in turn, is ultimately informed by dogmatics. The point is worth
pursuing. Despite the negation of sense and understanding, the soul nevertheless
remains cognitive through the infused theological virtue of faith which, at
least from an epistemological point of view, constitutes a cognitive function,
albeit an obscure one. 12 Faith, in other words, is at least implicitly
cognitive of its object --- and it is here that the doctrinal and mystical
elements in St. John’s philosophy converge. As we had noted earlier, the mystic
of necessity adverts to certain clearly defined dogmatic tenets as
propadeutic to his quest for union with God. Reason alone, as we had seen,
defaults into suspension in the face of the Absolute. To a certain limited
extent, reason may retrospectively ratify the dictates of faith --- but never
inform them. When we speak of faith as an infused theological virtue,
however, we certainly do not mean that the articles of faith are supernaturally
articulated in the soul independent of the avenues of nature. On the contrary,
no less an authority than St. Paul tells us that faith originates in the
hearing. 13 But hearing alone, quite obviously, does not necessarily
translate into faith; it does not involve that consent implicit in faith which
not simply understands these articles, but understands them to be
true; holds these articles to communicate factual information about
certain aspects of reality, supernatural in character, which are unavailable to,
and therefore cannot be authenticated by, sense and reason. This ability to
posit what reason cannot corroborate, what sense cannot confirm, comes from God.
In this sense it is understood as being divinely infused.
This a rather roundabout
way of saying that the mystic’s faith, if it is to be inerrant, must coincide
precisely with the articles of faith tendered him by dogmatic theology which
affirms certain things about God through the indefeasible guarantee of God’s
self revelation in Sacred Scripture in general, and in the person of
Jesus Christ in particular. These, together with that deposit of faith which the
Church understands as Sacred Tradition, form for the mystic the repository of,
while by no means exhaustive, nevertheless inviolable truth; they effectively
define his objective, provide him with the compass, the map, and the lay of the
metaphysical terrain, and detail the perils to which he will be exposed in the
dark night of the soul --- all indispensable elements to the soul’s journey to
that Absolute which is Truth and admits of no error. These dogmatic canons, in
fact, logically precede faith in determining the object of faith. And
while faith as such is ultimately abolished in the moment of ecstatic union when
what has only been implicit in faith yields to the actuality of the Absolute, it
nevertheless is indispensable not merely toward proximating, but in fact
identifying the Absolute. Hence, St. John argues that faith induces our
assent to divinely revealed truths which, though not necessarily in conflict
with understanding and reason, nevertheless inexorably transcend
them:
“... faith ... makes us believe truths
revealed by God Himself, which transcend all natural light, and exceed all human
understanding, beyond all proportion ... Hence it follows that, for the soul,
this excessive light of faith blinds it and deprives it of the sight that has
been given to it, inasmuch as its light is great beyond all proportion and
transcends the faculty of vision ... The light of faith, by its excessive
greatness oppresses and disables that of the understanding, for the latter of
its own power, extends only to natural knowledge ... “ 14
The disproportion between
faith and knowledge, St. John argues, becomes somewhat clearer by way of
analogy. The analogy, I think, is particularly interesting, for it is frequently
surprising to contemporary but ill-informed critics of medieval thought that the
natural epistemology articulated in scholasticism --- an epistemology by and
large derived from Aristotle --- is thoroughly empirical in nature as the
following excerpt demonstrates relative to the inquiry at
hand:
“... the soul, as soon as God infuses it
into the body, is like a smooth, blank board upon which nothing is painted; and,
save for that which it experiences through the senses, nothing is communicated
to it, in the course of nature, from any other source... 15 Wherefore, if one should speak to a man of
things which he has never been able to understand, and whose likeness he has
never seen, he would have no more illumination from them whatever than if aught
had been said of them to him ... If one should describe to a man that was born
blind, and has never seen any
color, what is meant by a white color or by a yellow, he would understand it but
indifferently, however fully one might describe it to him, as he has never seen
such colors or anything like them by which he may judge of them, only their
names would remain to him ... Even so is this faith with respect to the soul; it
tells us of things which we have never seen or understood, nor have we seen or
understood aught that resembles them at all. And thus we have no light of
natural knowledge concerning them, since that which we are told of them bears no
relation to any sense of ours; we know it by ear alone, believing that which we
are taught” 16
Common categories, St.
John argues, are essential to the transmission, the communication, of knowledge
--- and any description, however exhausttive, however carefully nuanced, that
cannot appeal to categories commonly shared, will avail nothing to
understanding. And this, of course, is precisely the difficulty the mystic
encounters in any effort to convey his experience of the Absolute. Since
knowledge necessarily appeals to experience to meaningfully inform
understanding, and the experience of the Absolute in the person of God is
unavailable outside of ecstatic union, the cognitive faculty of understanding is
not merely inadequate to, but is altogether incapable of addressing the
Absolute. Understanding, then, must be not merely suppressed, but entirely
superseded by a cognitive faculty that does not rely upon, derive its
information from, the reports of the senses gathered through the medium of
experience. And this cognitive faculty, of course, is the infused theological
virtue of faith. The author of the Letter to the Hebrews summarizes it this way:
“… faith is the assurance of things hoped for, the conviction of things
not seen.”17 It is faith, then, that informs us, albeit obscurely, of
things of which we have had no experience whatever; things so radically
dissimilar to all other experiences that no adequate parallels, no analogies,
will descriptively suffice. It is, in fact, very much along the lines of what
St. Paul attempted to describe to the Corinthians:
“... no eye has seen, nor ear heard, nor
the heart of man conceived, what God has prepared for those who love
him”.18
Faith, then, is quite
different from understanding. Each addresses entirely different spheres, and
each are informed by radically different categories. Understanding is
determinate, clearly articulating and comprehending its object and verifying the
data submitted to it by reports of the senses. Faith has far less specificity.
While apodictically certain, it is indeterminate. It verges upon but does not
clearly comprehend its object; it requires no corroboration, no authentication
by sense, deferring instead to the veracity of the Author from whom it holds its
articles to have been delivered. And it is only implicitly cognitive of these
revealed articles as inarticulate expressions of the Absolute which itself is
incapable of being exhausted by any and every expression of its being.
Indispensable as they are, these articles of faith are only impoverished media
of a true understanding which abolishes itself in the experience of, the
immediate confrontation with, the Absolute. And this means that for St. John,
faith, in transcending the canons of ordinary understanding, remains necessarily
and eternally unavailable to it. The elements of dogma, the articles of faith
--- these self-expressions of the Absoluute --- ultimately involve, for St. John,
the post-rational assent to the very doctrines held to be infallibly taught
through the magisterium of the Church concerning the revelation of God through
Scripture and sacred tradition.19 Unlike understanding
which is proactive in acquiring knowledge, the object of faith, St. John
insists, is passively received --- either through revelation preceding
union, or through the divine infusion in the state of
ecstasy.
The Three Theological Virtues and the Impetus to
Union
Our understanding of
faith relative to the mystical experience now becomes somewhat clearer. Faith,
to recapitulate, is the ill-defined and tenuous apprehension of something only
implicitly understood. In transcending what is explicitly, determinately
cognitive, faith passes from all the limiting frames of ordinary reference into
that state of unknowing which is the explicit negation of all the
contradictions to, and the contrarieties of, God in the created and finite
spheres of understanding and sensibility. The soul, St. John argues, is then
rendered more proximate to God in having been negated to the other --- the
contraries --- of God in nature and reason. Although in this state of simple
proximity the soul is not yet what God is, it is not what God is not. And
for this reason it is preeminently disposed to receiving God in mystical
union.
By now it is probably
clear, although somewhat prematurely, that the union of the soul with God is
not, cannot be, achieved through the three natural faculties of the soul: will,
understanding, and memory. 20 While much remains to be addressed especially in regard to
the faculty of understanding, it is perhaps best that we pause at this point to
better gain perspective of the whole. Mystical union, as we may already
anticipate, is rather to be achieved through the three theological virtues
corresponding to these three faculties:
“... the soul is not united with God in
this life through the understanding, nor through enjoyment, nor through
imagination, nor through any sense whatsoever; but only through faith, according
to the understanding; and through hope according to the memory; and through love
according to the will. These three virtues ... all cause emptiness in the
faculties: faith in the understanding, causes emptiness and darkness with
respect to the understanding; hope, in the memory, causes emptiness of all
possessions; and charity causes emptiness in the will and detachment from all
affection and from rejoicing in all that is not God.” 21
Each infused theological
virtue, we can see, is the negation of its corresponding natural faculty, and
insofar as these virtues succeed in their negative functions, just so is the
soul disposed, or receptive, to the state of infused contemplation. These
virtues, like many elements of the mystical experience that are steeped in
polarity, are in fact double-sided. On the one hand they are seen to be
negative, disabling the faculties which they supersede even as they are enacted
within them. On the other hand, they are seen to be positive, informing the soul
even as they displace the natural faculties they have negated. At this point,
however, St. John considers them largely in their negative aspect. Faith is the
explicit negation of understanding: it abolishes the mediatory function of
reason in apprehending its object intuitively. The object of faith is
transcendent, and therefore inaccessible, to the rigorously defined and
therefore limited architectonics of the categories of understanding. While these
are sufficient to addressing finite objects in the created order, they do not,
cannot, suffice in addressing the Absolute. Consequently, they are abolished in
the enactment of faith.
Hope, on the other hand,
is equally the negation of its own corresponding faculty in the memory which,
for St. John, is really a kind of residual faculty of understanding. Unlike
understanding itself which is actively engaged in acquiring, coordinating, and,
through the dialectic of reason, synthesizing the data delivered it by the
senses, memory --- strictly speaking --- is a passive repository of either the
synthetic fabrications of reason or of impressions acquired through the senses.
And I say strictly speaking for this reason: memory of itself essentially
consists in mere recollection; the recollection of things and concepts no longer
contemporaneous with that exercise of reason or the immediate sense experience
by which they were initially acquired. Once acquired, of course, these initial
acquaintances --- until repeated, in the case of sense experience ---
immediately devolve to memory. There they passively form the repository of
acquired knowledge to which reason or understanding subsequently appeals, and
consequently amplifies, when synthesizing or analyzing new data submitted by the
senses or acquired through the activity of reason. Imagination, however, which
for St. John is a sub-faculty of memory --- that in turn is subsumed beneath
understanding --- acts to creatively synthesize and manipulate the data
deposited in memory in much the same way that understanding does --- with two
important exceptions. The exercise of the imagination, while not antithetical
to, or even necessarily exclusive of, reason, is nevertheless unconstrained by
the canons of syllogistic reasoning that apply to understanding. It quite
freely, and quite often prescinds entirely from the protocols of logic.
Both analytic and synthetic, imagination systematically analyzes the part
from the coherent whole and is quite capable of synthesizing incongruent and
illogical fictions from essentially unrelated data. No laws, in other words, are
discoverable in the exercise of the imagination apart from the route the data
take to inform it. But more importantly, imagination is remote from
immediacy: while initially informed by the senses, it subsequently acts
independently of them. It may take its clues from the senses, but the products
of the imagination have no correlate in reality. In short, they are not factual
reports, but elaborate fictions. Fictions which, in the end, are composites of
created things initially derived from the senses and ultimately sharing, with
all other things in memory whose provenance lays in sense, in that contrariety
to God which is preclusive of union. As faith was seen to abolish understanding,
so now hope in supplanting memory abolishes it, for the theological virtue of
hope, St. John tells us, is by definition, directed to that which is not yet
possessed.
22
But, we are likely to
object, are not faith, hope, and love resident in memory as well? In that state
of negativity preparatory to union, may not the contemplative be said to
recollect, to remember the articles of faith, which in turn inform hope
and articulate the object loved? After all, these were, St. John had argued
earlier --- and prior to being assented to --- first learned, acquired through
the hearing, and, we presume, deposited into memory. Is not the mystic, then,
appealing to elements within the very deposit of data (memory) which we had
understood to have been abolished by hope? St. John, unfortunately, is not at
all clear on this point. But there is, I think, a semantic issue involved here
concerning the notion of recollection which does not readily lend itself to the
categorical opposition St. John seems to place between memory as a natural
faculty and hope as an implicitly mnemonic virtue. We are, however, clear on one
point, and that is that the memory as a natural faculty is in fact negated ---
effectively abolished --- relative to things created. In being supplanted
by hope, it is expropriated of every datum corresponding to the created
order.23 But the soul does not then possess no at least implicitly
mnemonic faculty whatever. Hope, which has replaced memory, materially possesses
nothing, but rather, formally anticipates the possession of
something. Of what? It anticipates the possession of the object which the
articles of faith address, the object of which faith is cognizant, God --- which
the soul does not yet possess, but only hopes to possess. That is to say, hope
anticipates, since it does not possess, what faith recognizes but does not
clearly know. Faith is the reservoir of hope which appeals to things uncreated,
and unlike memory, unpossessed. Hope then is seen as the antithesis of
memory in possessing nothing, and as the supernatural counterpart to
memory in anticipating what it does not possess, but what it nevertheless
latently recognizes through faith.
There are, moreover,
distinct differences discernible between the way in which data are preserved in
memory, and the way that the articles of faith are preserved in the latently
mnemonic theological virtue of hope. To begin with, we do not possess the
articles of faith in the way we possess the impressions of the senses, or, say,
the theorems of Euclidean geometry. Geometric theorems, for example, are
rationally, and even empirically demonstrable; they are characterized by
a deductive certainty deriving from analytical principles so clearly
defined, so self-evident as to be unequivocal and incontrovertible. The inherent
specificity of geometry as the paradigm of purely deductive reasoning, and
therefore the paradigm of deductive certainty--- of incontestable knowledge for
philosophers from Plato onward --- stands in stark contrast to the obscure and
indeterminate articles of faith which very clearly are not the conclusions of
syllogistic reasoning, possess nothing in the way of deductive certainty, and
are by nature not susceptible to being demonstrated either rationally or
empirically --- although, as we have said, they may not of themselves
necessarily be in conflict with reason. In short, the articles of faith do not
qualify as knowledge --- certainly not along the lines that would fit a purely
rational paradigm. And knowledge, either derived analytically from the exercise
of reason, or acquired through the reports of the senses, or indeed as the
synthesis of both, is, after all, what we understand to be passively archived in
memory.
But we might further
object that this deposit of data in which memory consists typically comprehends
a vast number of concepts which do not share, are not characterized by, the
rigorous deductive certainty of the geometric model we have invoked. In fact,
much of that deposit of knowledge that we call memory is really inchoate, and
quite nearly as vague as the articles of faith themselves. However this may be,
it nevertheless remains that they are also susceptible of being fully
articulated by subsequent reasoning; or, more apropos of our argument, since we
understand these incompletely articulated concepts to be merely deficient
in formation, it is entirely possible for them to be fully informed by
subsequent experience. Such concepts deriving from, and constructed around,
empirical acquaintance, or the impressions of the senses, are, therefore,
verifiable through, and capable of being augmented by, further experience. And
this is to say that the object of faith implicit in hope does not constitute
data in precisely the same way that rational concepts or sense impressions
do.
To summarize, then, our
understanding of the differences that obtain between hope and memory, we may say
that memory, unlike hope, is characterized by specificity, and the data resident
in memory are susceptible of further elaboration subsequent to further
investigation. The corresponding faculty of hope, on the other hand, is
radicated in faith --- not reason or sense --- and its object, unlike memory,
only vaguely, indeterminately, imprecisely, corresponds to a reality that was
not empirically acquired, is not empirically available, and is, therefore, not
verifiable. Memory and hope, then, while yet sharing parallel mnemonic
functions, effectively qualify as contrarieties in the epistemological account
of St. John.
This regrettably
involuted account, necessary to distinguishing memory from hope, finally puts us
in a position to understand why St. John will later argue that the soul is
unified through the three theological virtues 24, why this unity results in the soul’s singular
intentionality in God (its being exclusively, absolutely centered upon God), and
how this facilitates the soul in its movement toward God in the soul’s
possessing within itself no contrary to God. Let us look at this more closely.
Since the soul’s faculties are no longer diffused among a multiplicity of
objects, but are, rather, in a common state of negativity (or proximity) ---
each characterized by its respective theological virtue --- the soul is unified
both in this negativity, or night of the soul, common to each faculty,
and by intentionality, in that each of these virtues are theological in
nature, or exclusively directed to the one, singular object in God. Simply put,
all the faculties have entered the one same night: negation. And all the
theological virtues address the one same object: God. This translation of the
natural faculties into their corresponding theological virtues constitutes what
St. John will henceforth refer to as spiritual negation, or the
spiritual night of the soul 25 which is a pivotal point in the movement to mystical union
as we shall later find in Part 2.
Whereas we had found the
night of the senses to consist in the detachment from the created
external order in nature according to each faculty, so now the night of
the spirit will be found to consist in a similar detachment from the created
internal order of spirit. And once spiritual negation has been achieved,
the soul will have entered into a state of absolute negativity, for it is
the bilateral, absolute, and unqualified negation of the two created aspects of
bidimensional man: the natural dimension relative to nature, and the spiritual
dimension relative to spirit. This state of absolute negativity, in fact,
corresponds
to what St. John
otherwise calls “annihilation” 26, for it is, as it were, the annihilation of the soul’s
natural existence:
“... the soul must not only be
disencumbered from that which belongs to creatures, but likewise, as it travels,
must be annihilated and detached from all that belongs to its spirit ... This
... is death to the natural self, a death attained through the detachment and
annihilation of that self, in order that the soul may travel by this narrow
path, with respect to all its connections with sense, as we have said, and
according to the spirit as we shall now say ...” 27
Epistemology or Heterodoxy? The Annihilation of the Soul
This is the inauguration
of that “terrible night” of which St. John so often speaks, the night which must
be traversed in faith alone. 28 Here every other standard of reference to the world of
experience ordinarily understood, fails, evanesces, before the negativity of
night. And here it becomes absolutely critical to the purpose of our
commentary that we correctly understand what St. John refers to in speaking of
the concept of “annihilation”. The various phenomenologies that have
historically evolved around the concept of mysticism are almost universal in
incorporating this mercurial and extremely fragile term, and there is far from
unanimity among them concerning its significance. This is particularly true for
the Christian mystic. First of all, it is not, we must hasten to add, a type of
nirvanic annihilation of the self much as we understand in certain Vedantic
phenomenologies broadly construed as mystical, for in St. John’s account the
self, however attenuated through the process of negation, is nevertheless
understood to be preserved in super-natural existence. Not, to be sure,
in the exercise of its natural faculties ordinarily understood --- but rather
through the theological virtues which at once annihilate (negate) the self
relative to the natural faculties, and preserve the self as the
presupposition of that personal and residual consciousness within which the
theological virtues are enacted, exercised.
Annihilation, because it
is so easily misconstrued, is one of those volatile concepts within Christian
mysticism that readily lends itself to charges of heterodoxy, the sanctions
against which, at the height of the Counter-Reformation (1560-1648), were
stringently applied. Despite this fact, it is not the case that St. John, as a
contemporary figure in this tumultuous period, simply deferred to orthodoxy out
of expedience as some may suppose, or worse yet, deliberately couched his terms
in equivocal language to conceal a covert agendum antagonistic to accepted
doctrine or ecclesiastical authority. There is not a shred of evidence to
support this contention. St. John was unwavering in orthodoxy, and would
undoubtedly have answered that, if his mystical doctrine was entirely consonant
with the deposit of faith articulated by the Magisterium of the Church, it was
not, for that reason, a procrustean accomplishment; a matter of merely
accommodating his doctrine to the formal requirements of faith --- but rather
that the articles of faith must be seen as having informed his doctrine --- as
indeed they had --- which in turn was a vindication of that dogma whose elements
were subsequently authenticated in the mystical experience
itself.
Identity and Individuation: Noesis or
Nuance?
But to return to our
point, the annihilation of which St. John speaks appears to be essentially the
radical reduction of the self to an irreducible state of consciousness. This
consciousness, we have already said, necessarily presupposes something of
which it is conscious. To restate our point succinctly, our consciousness is
always a consciousness of. Of what? Well, certainly of something.
And this something, of course, can no longer be the deliverance of sense and
reason already transcended. It is, rather, an anticipatory consciousness
informed by the articles of faith alone, and exclusively directed toward God
apart from any other object of intention. In essence, it is a state of pure
intentionality. The self has completely receded from all relativity to
everything outside itself: it is perfectly receded from, and therefore utterly
without reference to, the non-self, both in nature, as negated, and in God, as
yet revealed. In this state of absolute recession, the soul has only the dim,
merely formal cognition of God --- unaccompanied as yet by any empirical
acquaintance --- provided it through the three theological virtues which are at
once, paradoxically, the very principles behind this annihilation, and
simultaneously the means of the preservation of the self subsequent to it. While
much of this remains to be discussed in greater depth in Part II, it is
nevertheless important to an understanding of St. John’s thought at this point
to recognize that the self --- that is to say, personal consciousness --- in
fact survives the annihilation of which St. John speaks in his account. And it
is precisely this residual self-consciousness, this implicit but nevertheless
distinguishable apperception in the face of the Absolute which preserves a
distinction in identity even as this union abolishes contrariety in
nature.
The implications that
evolve from this are worth considering further. We had, for example, spoken of
the self earlier as having been brought to an irreducible state of consciousness
epistemologically poised in an act of pure intentionality. But what, we must now
ask, is the self so understood? Our very notion of identity, of our self,
would seem to be bound up with a great many material and historical antecedents
which must then necessarily be borne along with our identity beyond negativity.
Our individual identity --- who we are --- defined, by and large, by our unique
historical antecedents would appear to be a necessary component of a coherent
conception of the self. But let us look at this anew from the phenomenological
perspective of the mystic. We are accustomed to being individuated by precisely
those elements which, through the via negativa, have been negated and
transcended: namely finitude and temporality. We perceive ourselves to be such
and such an individual apart from other individuals by virtue of certain clearly
defined material limits --- our bodies, for example, describe a finite area that
is discrete from the bodies of others; our minds, while similar to others in
their cognitive faculties, are unlike others in that our thoughts are not
identical to the thoughts of others; my experiences in all their subtleties, and
the arrangement and chronological order of these experiences, are not identical
with those of others, having been acquired, enacted, if not in different frames
of time then in different locations in space; still yet, my parents are not your
parents, or if they are, my birth was not precisely coincidental with yours, and
I never had myself as my brother. In short, there are a thousand ways in which
we individuate ourselves from others and acquire a sense of identity that is
essentially composed differentially.
And so our question is:
Can we in fact possess an identity apart from these individuating elements or
circumstances? And if so, in what does that identity consist? Indeed, does one
lose one’s individual identity altogether in mystical experience, and
does this consequently entail some absurd and essentially meaningless form of
cosmic consciousness? These, and other questions like them, some rather
frivolous, others quite serious, enable us to see why mysticism is often the
breeding ground of redoubtable epistemological difficulties --- as well as a
good deal of nonsense. Within each of these instances or circumstances we find
time or finitude or both as the individuating principle behind the conception of
identity. But it is equally clear that the radically reduced notion of the self
consequent to the mystic’s subjection to the via negativa entirely
prescinds from the self as historically articulated. The mystic in essence
acquires a new identity, not that of the self reflexively identified ---
that is to say the self historically identified with the utterly personal
existential enactment of its own being chronologically considered at a
different, elapsed, point in time --- rather, the mystic’s identity now refers,
not back to himself, reflexively --- but to God. And this new identity, in fact,
is merely the re-appropriation of the soul’s primal identity as the
imago Dei, the image of God. This notion of identity, which is always and
essentially reciprocal in nature with an other relative to which it is
the same, remains to be discussed more fully later on. We only touch upon it
here to further illustrate the point that the annihilation of the soul in no way
compromises, but rather attenuates the identity of the soul which nevertheless
remains intact beyond absolute negation.
Faith as Negativity: The Knower and the Unknown
God
Returning once again to
our discussion of the relation that obtains between faith and understanding, we
had found that no proportion, or as St. John puts it, similitude, exists between
the understanding and God for reasons already discussed and principally
involving the notion of incommensurability:
“... all that the imagination can imagine
and the understanding can receive and understand in this life is not, nor can it
be, a proximate means of union with God ... [ for ] all that can be understood
by the understanding, that can be tasted by the will, and that can be invented
by the imagination is most unlike God and bears no proportion to Him
...” 29
In the face of this
incommensurability, a requisite to union must consist in a transformation that
will bridge this gap which is infinite; that will, in effect, restore a measure
of commensurability between the means and the end, cognition and God. This
transformation, however, cannot be effected by, since it is clearly beyond the
natural ability of, the created and finite soul. It can only, therefore, be
divinely initiated. And this, we have seen, occurs when God leads the
soul, through faith, into the state of negation. But how are we to understand
faith --- which up to this point has largely been a negative factor in
St. John’s account in the way of abolishing understanding --- as now capable of
restoring this commensurability? Well, to begin with we had already seen that,
for all its obscurity, faith nevertheless entails certain positive elements in
the form of implicitly understood articles ultimately derived from the
self-revelation of God to man; articles which, for St. John, are to be received
in that simplicity which is consonant with faith:
“ ... the understanding, profoundly
hushed and put to silence ... leans upon faith which alone is the proximate
means whereby the soul is united with God; for such is the likeness between
itself and God that there is no other difference, save that which exists between
seeing God and believing in Him. For even as God is infinite, so faith sets Him
before us as infinite; and as he is Three and One, it sets Him before us as
Three and One; and as God is darkness to our understanding, even so does faith
likewise blind and dazzle our understanding. And thus, by this means alone, God
manifests Himself to the soul in Divine light, which passes all
understanding.” 30
Faith, in other words,
transcends the limitations of understanding in affirming of God those attributes
which the understanding in its limitations, and without involving itself in
contradiction, could not possibly affirm. And so in transcending understanding,
faith simultaneously transcends limitation implicit within understanding --- and
in doing so simultaneously establishes commensurability with the infinite and
the unlimited. Such a transcendence will inevitably entail a cognitive
transformation as well. Determinate understanding with all its limitations is no
longer sufficient. In fact, it has already been abolished in the negativity of
faith. Abolished --- but also superseded, as we had already seen, by a
faculty quite different, a faculty which, as the negative of understanding with
its distinct concepts and determinate categories, will necessarily be indistinct
and indeterminate.31 And this type of cognition, not radicated in an
acquaintance with its object either empirically acquired through sense or
rationally acquired through the analytic or synthetic activity of reason ---
that is to say, which does not acquire its object mediatively --- is
essentially intuitive in nature.
“Natural” and “Supernatural” Modes of
Understanding
So we find that, despite
the negativity of faith, it is, after all, not the case that all
understanding categorically ceases, but merely a particular kind of
understanding, for within the comprehensive faculty of understanding itself, St.
John distinguishes two quite different modes: the natural and the
supernatural. The former refers to the distinct and determinate mode of
ordinary cognition both appropriate and sufficient to addressing the world of
ordinary experience, and consisting in finite concepts actively applied to
finite data. The latter corresponds to that intuitive mode of cognition
subsequent to the state of negation in which faith has superseded natural
understanding. The former we have already examined. It is the latter with which
we are now concerned. This supernatural knowledge, as St. John calls it, is, to
additionally complicate matters, then further subdivided into corporeal
and spiritual modes through which knowledge is communicated to, and
passively received by, the soul.
32 Understanding at this point becomes,
as it were, rarefied in that epistemological margin between nature and spirit.
It is at the outermost extremity of both, while completely sharing in the unique
character of neither. Let us, then, look at each mode as it informs
understanding and see what further conclusions remain to be
drawn.
The “Corporeal” Mode of Understanding
The corporeal mode
of supernatural understanding, St. John tells us, consists in those
communications to the soul which proceed either through the external sensuous by
way of the bodily senses, or through the internal sensuous according to the
imagination. At this point we can safely say that St. John has already
demonstrated 33 that the imagination is dependent upon empirical data
acquired through experience, and that, therefore, no proportion whatever can
possibly exist between God and the synthetic constructs of imagination.
Incapable of proximating God, imagination is summarily disqualified as a
proximate means to union with God. The very specific and determinate nature
common to every product of the imagination is profoundly incommensurable with
the infinite reality of God. Consequently, the internal sensuous according to
the imagination must be negated of all the various forms and images which are
either the products of its own synthetic activity, or which derive from a
supernatural agency communicating these forms and images to it,
34 for without exception they entail contrariety to God. That
this applies with equal and greater force to those supernatural phenomena
sensuously embodied in the external order is already clear. Our treatment, then,
of imagination, in an effort to leave no element unaddressed in our account, is
really parenthetical to our articulating an epistemology of mysticism. By and
large the constituent elements of imagination may be subsumed under the broader
category of sense, and stand merely to be abolished in the movement toward
contemplation.
The “Supernatural” Mode of Understanding
On the other hand, St.
John’s discussion of the supernatural mode of understanding is a good
deal more illuminating. Even a casual reading of St. John reveals that, in an
effort to be as precise as possible, his systematic treatment, especially in
regard to the faculty understanding, becomes increasingly schematized. The
category of understanding, for example, is further divided into sub-categories
of natural and supernatural modes of understanding. The supernatural mode, to
take just one element in this bifurcation, is then further analyzed into
corporeal and spiritual modes, and the spiritual mode, in turn, further
subdivided into distinct and special and confused and general
modes. 35 This is no gratuitous exercise in speculative analysis. St.
John’s objective, we must remember, is always practical. In taking such a
rigorous and systematic inventory of understanding, St. John effectively
attempts to address an issue involving the single greatest liability to which
not only the mystic, but the entire mystical enterprise itself, is exposed: the
problem of error. Although we had briefly examined this problem earlier, let us
look at it once again in light of the present context. Supernatural
understanding, as St. John calls it, is either communicated distinctly and
specially through visions, revelations, locutions, and the like --- or generally
and obscurely, that is to say, in a manner lacking both in specificity and
clarity. In essence, however, St. John’s entire discussion of knowledge
supernaturally communicated to --- not actively acquired by --- the soul, is at
least implicitly his treatment of the impediment of error, both here and
elsewhere.
Consequently it is, at
one and the same time, an ad hoc critique of human understanding
confronted with the supernatural --- to the end of establishing a canon of
authenticity to which the mystic may ultimately appeal with unquestionable
certainty. And it is precisely this type of critical analysis --- to which the
Christian tradition of mysticism owes a great debt to St. John --- that is
central to our accreditation of the mystical experience as in fact veridical.
For unless quite definite criteria are established concerning the authenticity
of the contemplatives mystical experience --- that it is a unique
experience corresponding to, not simply a solipsistic or reflexively interpreted
reality , but to a reality independent of the mind of the mystic ---
Christian mysticism will fail to exempt itself from the most remarkable and
bizarre array of pseudo-mystical states, including delusional psychoses, which
are often otherwise broadly, and erroneously, characterized as “mystical” .This
problem, worthy of a chapter in itself, will be examined more extensively later
on. For the moment it is sufficient to note that St. John is acutely aware of
some of the problems created by this type of confusion. For example, he insists
that,
“... he that esteems such things
errs greatly and exposes himself to the peril of being deceived
36 ... [ for ] a readiness to accept them
opens the door to the devil that he may deceive the soul by other things like to
them, which he very well knows how to dissimulate and disguise, so that they may
appear to be good; for, as the Apostle says, he can transform himself into an
angel of light.” 37
This premature and
clearly parenthetical treatment of the problem of error equally serves to
underscore the imperative of faith in the soul’s journey to union with God, for
it is faith, as we will come to understand, which constitutes the one
epistemological constant to which the several modes of understanding are
subordinated throughout.
Dealing first with the
distinct and special mode of supernatural understanding, St. John tells
us that these very specialized apprehensions are, to begin with, sensuously
communicated to the soul --- understanding does not play an active, or
intentional role in acquiring them much in the way that it does in its
interpretive interaction with data delivered by the senses subsequent to being
actively addressed by understanding. The notion of intentionality relative to
the understanding is entirely absent in the case of these apprehensions as they
come to the soul --- which at this point, we will remember, is passive ---
through the five bodily senses. It is most urgent, St. John argues, that the
soul maintain an attitude completely skeptical to these apprehensions; in fact,
if at all possible, to entirely disregard them.38
A Dark Impedimence: Diabolical Deception
Given the disproportion
and contrariety which we have seen to exist between God and the created order
(all that is not God), St. John further argues that the greater the apparent
corporeity and exteriority of the apprehension, the less warrant we have to
presume its origin to be in God. The possibility, if not the likelihood, both of
human error and diabolical deception relative to these sensuously embodied
communications is, for St. John, far greater than in communications to the
spirit; and for this principal reason: our judgment, accustomed as it is to
defer to the superficial reports of the senses --- not just as an ordinarily
reliable index of a reality, but characteristically of a reality presumed to in
fact correspond to its appearance --- is accurate only to the extent to
which appearances actually coincide with the reality they ostensibly signify.
And this is simply another way of saying that we characteristically, even
necessarily, judge only on the basis of appearances. And while, on the one hand,
real correspondence often exists --- our interaction with the world around us
would be impossible or chaotic otherwise --- on the other hand disqualifying
instances clearly abound: most often as a matter of mistaking appearances to
authentically represent realities to which they actually do not conform, or less
often but equally real, by subreption through diabolical malice --- in either
case the resulting misjudgment is what we call error. And what this
effectively means is that sense experience does not necessarily constitute a
confirmation of reality. And this is St. John’s whole point. This is why
the contemplative must not defer to the senses, however credible their reports
may appear.
Moreover, St. John
argues, in their tangible dimensions, these sensuous communications cannot in
reality bear any proportion to, and are in fact the ontological opposite of, the
spiritual reality which they purport to convey. 39 Even were such communications divine in origin, these
supernatural reports would serve merely as the vehicle, the character of which
invariably, ineluctably, colors our interpretation of the actual significance.
Invested as they are with clarity and distinctness, the forms of these
apprehensions further tend to overshadow the implicit spiritual significance
they are intended to communicate independent of their sensuous expedient. It is,
then, crucial for the mystic to act in utter disregard of any such
communications, and in so doing avoiding the occasion of the two principle
possibilities of error. However, it now becomes problematic as to how one thing
(the sensuous) contrary to another (the spiritual) --- as clearly they have been
throughout our account so far --- can be the vehicle of its antithesis, that is
to say, how the spiritual can be sensuously embodied at all. St. John provides
us with no clear answer to the problem. In a sense it stands clearly aside from
his practical intent. But not from ours. I think, however, that one solution is
suggested by the logic of the argument itself.
Any supernatural
manifestation of necessity introduces itself within the natural order.
This having occurred, a radical duality is subsequently generated, the two
distinct components of which are nature and spirit On the one hand we have what
we might call unqualified nature in the simple material sense, and for
lack of a better term, qualified spirit. What we have called qualified
spirit, we might say, is super-existent in nature. Although subsisting
independently of the material order, it is nevertheless capable of assuming
additional, if fundamentally extraneous, ontological characteristics essential
to its introduction to, or appearance within, the material order. But it does so
only under some clearly defined conditions ontologically dictated by the nature
it assumes. Being in nature and assuming quasi-natural dimensions, it
must conform to the two ultimate constituents of nature as the very ontological
frames --- the very matrices of finitude --- presupposed in every conception of
nature as such, namely, time and space. Simply put, any
supernatural manifestations must occur somewhere and sometime.
However these manifestations may be able to contravene every other protocol of
nature through their yet undiminished supernatural character, as manifestations
in nature, they are necessarily subject to these two laws
governing all appearances in nature whatever. In other words, they must
share definite characteristics common to, if in fact they are to occur as
appearances within, the material order.
Despite this
incorporation, however, this spirit-in-nature---which every supernatural
manifestation essentially is --- yet remains other to nature as spirit. That is
to say, it nevertheless remains unqualified spirit, spirit unmodified or
unconditioned by nature; spirit merely introduced within and only
physically --- not essentially --- constrained by the laws of appearance,
the two laws alone which it cannot contravene, but to which, as we have said, it
must submit as a condition of any appearance whatever. Assuming physical
specificity as a condition of its appearance --- not as essential
to its nature --- it becomes qualified, subject to laws from which it is
characteristically, essentially immune, and to which it submits itself merely as
an expedient to its appearance in nature. But if this, in fact, is how
spirit is capable of being sensuously embodied, it does not answer why
they are embodied at all. This question is answered by St.
John.
More on “Spiritual Communications”
Before going further we
must point out that at this stage in the Ascent, St. John is treating of
the mystical experience as it pertains to the beginner who is just being
brought into the first stages of mystical union and who is not yet completely
withdrawn from the senses.40 As a result, these spiritual communications are given
sensuous form in order to be rendered proximate to ordinary, sensuous
understanding. In fact, as we have already seen, they are merely an expedient
--- addressed as it were to the determinnate mode of ordinary understanding in
order to lead it the further on in its desire for union with
God.41 The form which this communication takes is, to sensuous
understanding, merely the necessary vehicle of the spiritual reality behind it
which transcends the sensuous form, even as this reality is eclipsed by it in
the immediacy of sense. But the nature of this super-existent reality concealed
beneath the superficies of form is nevertheless such that it succeeds withal in
producing its effect independently of the form. The noetic realization is
obscured by, because the soul at this point is merely attentive to, the
form of the communication. In the words of St. John, it is “secretly”
communicated to the soul.
Now we must admit that
this strikes us as rather odd. If these communications are capable of producing
their effects independently of the sensuous form in which they are embodied; and
if, furthermore, the phenomenal features which such communications assume by way
of mere expediency are to be ignored altogether as a likely source of error ---
then why are these communications not effected in the soul without the
appearance of the sensuous form that is both unnecessary to their producing
their effects and, at the very least, the likely occasion of misjudgment and
error? I think that this is a serious question that requires an answer. And the
answer, I suggest, is offered within the context out of which the problem
arises. It is unquestionably within the power of God to produce effects within
the soul of which the soul is not cognizant. Or even to produce effects within
the soul which the soul acknowledges but does not apprehend in either an
experiential or noetic sense. A few instances which immediately come to mind
concern the sacraments of Baptism, Confirmation, and Holy Orders, each of which
are held to impress certain indelible characters upon the soul --- as well as
supernatural capabilities --- only the external significance of
which is recognized and acknowledged. The actual character, seal, or impress of
God upon the soul is neither cognitively accessible nor subject to empirical
verification. In the case of Baptism, it is entirely possible for a child to be
baptized and subsequently mature in complete ignorance of his faith and his own
baptism --- all the while possessing the baptismal seal, and all that it
signifies, without recognizing it.
The power conferred in
these instances, as well as the effect itself --- not, of course, the ritual
signifying the effect --- may be said to have been secretly
communicated to the soul. Now this analogy that we have chosen is not at all
inappropriate to our purpose. We must recall, once again, that the present
discussion revolves around the contemplative who is not yet totally withdrawn
from the senses. While the effect of the communication is in fact wrought
independently of the form, the sensuous form serves to signify the
reality being enacted completely supernaturally, secretly, invisibly, within the
soul. It is a sign to the soul --- which is still sensuously oriented ---
of something being enacted supernaturally. And as a sign, it points to,
signifies, something beyond itself of which the sign constitutes no
material element. Moreover, as a sign, it is an indication of the proximity and
presence of something else of which it is merely a sign. And this is
precisely the manner in which God first moves the soul to greater desire for
union with Himself. So in answer to our question, can God produce effects within
the soul without adverting to sensuous phenomena, we must unequivocally state,
yes. But his doing so with a soul still primarily oriented to the senses would
effectively move the soul no closer to God, and so be apart from his
purpose.
... And More on the Notion of the Impedimence of
Error
Let us look a little
closer now at the nature of the error to which the soul is liable in adverting
to the sensuous form of the these supernatural communications. First of all, St.
John argues, the soul errs in judging these apprehensions to be as they
sensuously appear. In pronouncing judgments that appeal to the sheer phenomenal
features of such occurrences, the soul illegitimately insinuates a spurious
commensurability between nature and spirit which does not, and cannot,
metaphysically obtain. And it is precisely because of the disproportion that
exists between spirit and nature that any such embodiments of spirit are pure
contingencies, exigencies in which no necessary connection is discernible
between the appearances and the realties ostensibly signified by them. The soul,
in order to avoid error then, must not only prescind from the sheer phenomenal
dimensions of such appearances, but suspend its judgment concerning them
altogether. 42
There is, moreover, a
second and potentially greater danger involved in giving credence to these
communications and what they purport to convey, and this, for St. John, lies in
the very real possibility of diabolical deception. The dysteleological presence
of personified evil on the ontological fringe of spirit toward which the
contemplative moves is of genuine concern to St. John. It is the perfectly
disvaluable presence whom, as we had seen earlier, Jesus describes in no unclear
terms as “... a liar and the father of lies.” 43 and whom St. Peter calls “[the] adversary, the devil, [who]
as a roaring lion, walks about seeking whom he may devour.” 44 The mystic, then, in addition to the liability to error
connatural with judgment, confronts the possibility of supernatural error
foisted upon the soul by no less than an agency metaphysically diabolical in
nature and historically inimical to the ultimate interests of man --- which, not
simply for the mystic but for every Christian as well, preeminently lies in
union with God. Confronted with so redoubtable a foe, far more powerful,
tremendously more resourceful, vastly more intelligent, and invincibly evil, the
soul, for St. John, has but one recourse --- and that is to advert once again to
the methodological suspension of judgment. St. John maintains that since God is
more disposed to communicate with the soul through the spirit, rather than
through sense, all such sensuous communications should be least methodologically
--- to proceed, not from God, but ratherr, from the devil. St. John is clear on
this point: the realm of matter and sense is particularly susceptible to the
artifice of the devil who, through exercising his influence over the sensuous
and material, actively endeavors to deceive the soul and to frustrate it in its
efforts to achieve union with God.45 All judgment, then, must be categorically suspended and the
ordinary canons of interpretation which the mystic invokes before the world of
appearances must be entirely relinquished as inadequate before such
extraordinary occurrences if the soul is at all to succeed in avoiding the
impediment constituted by error, and so achieve union with
God.
For St. John the chief
danger, however, in submitting to such communications --- and ultimately, the
diabolical stratagem is directed to this end --- lies in the soul’s subsequently
abandoning the principal means of union with God which we have found to be
faith. In failing to disregard these communications, the soul consequently
abandons that faith which takes for its object the unrevealed --- and in
so doing proceeds, not according to the only proximate means of union with God
--- which is faith --- but according to the understanding in relation to
its proper object which is revealed, and which St. John has already
demonstrated at length to have no proportion whatever to God. But what if this
supernatural communication does in fact proceed from God --- as very well it
may? Does the soul not err in withholding its assent? This would appear to be a
very cogent objection, for it would seem that by withholding its consent, the
soul would then be subjecting itself to the very liability it is expressly
committed to avoiding: error.
But this is not the case,
St. John answers. If a given communication does in fact proceed from God, then
it produces its effect on the soul independently of the soul’s judgment and
assent:
“... if [ any communication ] be of God, [
it ] produces its effect upon the soul at the very moment when it appears or is
felt, without giving the soul time or opportunity to deliberate whether it will
accept or reject it. For, even as God gives these things supernaturally, without
effort on the part of the soul, and independently of its capacity, even so,
likewise, without respect to its effort or capacity, God produces within it the
effect that He desires by means of such things, for this is a thing that is
wrought and brought to pass in the spirit passively ...” 46
But why, we must now ask,
would God continue in such supernatural communications if they are likely to be
the occasion of error, or worse yet, a defection from faith? Considered more
carefully, however, there is something subreptive in this objection that makes
it spurious, for if we look closely we find that it is really anachronistic. We
must answer that, essentially, God does not so continue. Through these
communications, we have seen, God is leading the beginner into the state
of contemplation, and in so doing, God initially cooperates with the limited
nature of the soul by introducing sensuous forms and images to the understanding
--- principally, St. John tells us, in tthe act of meditation. Gradually,
however, God leads the soul from the active state of meditation
together with its various forms and images, into the passive state of
contemplation in which the limited nature of sense in transcended
through, and in fact supplanted by, the simple assent of
faith.
To further emphasize the
point, St. John uses an interesting analogy to demonstrate the necessity of the
soul’s remaining passive and exercising no judgment whatever relative to such
apprehensions. We have, St. John argues, no less a paradigm than Scripture
itself:
“... although sayings and revelations may
be of God, we cannot always be sure of their meaning; for we can very easily be
greatly deceived by them because of our manner of understanding them. For they
are an abyss and a depth of the spirit, and to try to limit them to what we can
understand [would be in vain ] 47 ... let it be realized, therefore, that
there is no complete understanding of the sayings and things of God
...
48
[ whereas in themselves
they ] are always certain, they are not always so with respect to ourselves ...
One reason is the defective way in which we understand them ... To many of the
ancients many of the prophesies and locutions from God came not to pass as they
expected because they understood them after their own manner ... “
49
These communications, he
continues, are equally capable of being apprehended by the understanding without
the active mediation of either inner or outer sense, without corresponding
phenomena in the external order, and, moreover, without the active engagement of
the imagination:
“[ These ] four apprehensions of the
understanding ... we call purely spiritual, for they do not (as do those that
are corporeal and imaginary) communicate themselves to the understanding by way
of the corporeal sense; but, without the intervention of any inward or outward
corporeal sense, they present themselves to the understanding, clearly and
distinctly, by supernatural means, passively --- that is to say, without the
performance of any act or operation on the part of the soul itself ... “
50
Those apprehensions,
then, that were previously invested with qualities distinctly accessible to the
senses, are now received by the understanding with an intelligible
clarity and distinctness which parallels in the intellect the definition with
which these apprehensions were invested in order to be first accommodated to the
senses. It is, however, an intelligible definition, a definition no
longer concealed, as it were inchoate, within distinctly sensuous perimeters. In
a word, it is completely unconditioned by corporeity and exteriority. But how
can visions, locutions and the like can be rendered non-sensuous at all? Not
only non-sensuous, but purely intelligible? It would seem, at first glance, as
though St. John had inadvertently overstepped every criteria of meaning in his
pursuit of ultimate realities --- but a closer look reveals otherwise. The
solution to this enigma, we find, is suggested in certain terminological
transitions that occur within the text. To wit, at one point St. John describes
these four apprehensions --- including locutions and spiritual feelings
--- as “visions of the soul”, and “intelllectual visions” respectively.
51 It would appear, then, that the terms “revelations,
“locutions”, etc., as we find them variously applied to these supernatural
apprehensions, are essentially employed analogically. 52 While some correlation, however attenuated, undeniably
obtains between the terms in the analogy --- otherwise it would be altogether
useless ---the complete amplitude of what is signified characteristically, even
essentially, exceeds an inflexible criterion of meaning. And this, after all, is
the whole purpose of adopting an analogy --- to verge upon an amplitude of
meaning accessible through no other means; by approximating --- not by achieving
--- a satisfactory meaning. And, to enunnciate the obvious, a totally
satisfactory meaning would not require the use of analogy. So understood, the
terms “visions”, “locutions”, etc., to which St. John adverts, are intended to
approximate by way of analogy an aspect of reality that only remotely
corresponds to the meanings imbedded in a language that is not, and cannot be,
sufficient to the descriptive task. Language, predicated as it is upon shared
experiences, is simply too impoverished to accommodate the amplitude, the
infinite amplitude of the Absolute. Even the peripheral, the most marginal and
obscure experience of the Absolute, in some sense, for St. John, analogically
approximates a vision, or a locution, in its intelligible
clarity:
“... all these four apprehensions may be
called visions of the soul; for we term the understanding of the soul also its
sight. And since all these apprehensions are intelligible to the understanding,
they are described, in a spiritual sense, as ‘visible’. And thus the kinds of
intelligence that are formed in the understanding may be called intellectual
visions. 53 From all these the soul derives spiritual
vision or intelligence without any kind of apprehension concerning form, image,
or figure.” 54
But something more
remains to be said about the nature of these four apprehensions that figure so
largely and are treated so extensively in Book II of the Ascent. All of
them, we have found, are equally subsumed under the comprehensive term “vision”,
and this would seem to effectively attenuate any radical distinction between
them. There must, then, be a single characteristic universally shared among them
such that either the mode of reception or the mode of communication is the same
in all relative cases. And since a distinction, however tenuous, nevertheless
remains between these several communications --- in that they are clearly and
consistently differentiated within the schema St. John has developed --- this
unitary characteristic cannot be in the mode of communication; it must therefore
be found in a certain mode of reception. And this receptive mode, we have seen,
is described as a “vision” by St. John; a vision which may more properly be
designated an intuition since it is explicitly unmediated in nature. As
an intuition, then, this communication is non-sensuous; it is merely intuited
without mediation of any type, rational or sensory. Moreover, the clarity and
distinctness with which it is invested must not be mistaken as referring to the
content of the communication --- this still remains concealed from the
understanding --- rather, it is to be understood as referring to the
experience itself which is clearly and distinctly perceived, not
clearly and distinctly understood. This interpretation, I think, is clearly
borne out in the following passages:
“... although these visions ... cannot be
unveiled and be clearly seen in this life by the understanding, they can
nevertheless be felt in the substance of the soul ...
55 And although at times, when such knowledge
is given to the soul, words are used, the soul is well aware that it has
expressed no part of what it has felt; for it knows that there is no fit
name by which it can name it ...” 56
This very complex notion
of intelligible apprehensions or visions, then, is more readily understood as,
in clearly evidencing the characteristics of, an intuition: they are immediately
apprehended, perceived as pure experiences communicated to the soul
spiritually, and without any mediation whatever.
The Spurious and the Counterfeit: The Imperative of
Faith
But it is no less clear,
as St. John once again points out, that these four apprehensions are equally
susceptible to being contrived, or perhaps better yet, counterfeited,
diabolically. It is of the first order of importance, then, that some very clear
criteria be established to distinguish between the diabolical and the divine
relative to these apprehensions. Although St. John fails to provide us with a
clear answer on this subject, our most immediate question, I think, will
inevitably be --- why? Why indeed go to the trouble of establishing criteria to
distinguish between what is authentically divine, and what is spuriously
diabolical in origin? After all, St. John has forcefully argued that when
confronted with such supernatural apprehensions, the contemplative must
disregard them totally, both as inimical to faith which alone is the
proximate means to union, and as the possible occasion of error. If in fact,
then, the disregard is to be total, the source, or origin of such communications
would seem to be entirely irrelevant. One and all they are to be dismissed. The
mystic, in any event, is to act in disregard of them; however, St. John
proceeds to argue, the subjective effects of these apprehensions ---
independent of the resolute disregard of the mystic --- are to the soul who
is not yet totally withdrawn from the senses, that is to say, to the soul
who is just being brought into the preliminary stages of mystical union,
indications of the predilection of God who, through the accidental
qualities of these subjective effects, stirs the soul to a greater desire for
union. In a sense, then, God is understood as permitting these accidental
qualities, ex mero motu, to attend the effects being secretly wrought in
the soul. They are essentially signs to which invisible realities, in the way of
actual effects occurring in the soul, correspond. On the other hand, those
apprehensions effected diabolically, St. John contends, are in every sense
entirely fraudulent. That is to say, there is no authentic correspondence
between the sign and the reality it spuriously signifies: no effect
whatever is wrought in the soul --- no effect, that is, apart from the
soul’s subjective response to the sign. And this is worth
examining further.
For St. John, the only
criteria to which the contemplative can appeal in attempting to discern the
authenticity of what is perceived to be the divine invitation to mystical union
consists, at this early stage --- a stage, we will remember, in which the mystic
is yet susceptible to the senses --- largely in the subjective effects
produced in the soul by the respective apprehensions. Diabolical communications,
St. John argues, typically render the soul apathetic toward God; they
characteristically foster inordinate pride, a pride in which the soul sees these
communications as signal tokens of God’s unique predilection for it, and
consequently dispose the soul to be inclined toward precisely these types of
phenomena which, in effect, are so many inducements to abandon pure faith. The
soul must, then, and for this crucial reason, proceed in absolute detachment
from them, irrespective of its judgment concerning their source, and continue in
the darkness of faith alone. 57 But does this
really answer our question? In other words, if the soul is to prescind entirely
from, not only the apprehension, but its accidental and subjective effects as
well, how are we to reconcile this with the soul’s acceptance of God’s
invitation through the very effects he is committed to disregarding? The answer,
I suggest, is to be found in the very detachment that the soul is consistently
exhorted to exercise. Perhaps we can put it another way. The mystic, through the
accidental qualities that attend these phenomena, is, despite his intentional
disregard, nevertheless perceptibly influenced by them --- because they
actually and simultaneously produce a real effect in his soul. They are,
after all, and as we had said, authentic signs of invisible realities. On the
other hand, there are no realities whatsoever effected in the soul by the merely
fraudulent signs contrived by a diabolical agency. Both signs, then, may in fact
be safely ignored --- but only one produces an autonomous effect independent of
the of the assent of the will.
But what of the criterion
itself? Just how reliable can criteria be that appeal to what are fundamentally
subjective impressions? Indeed, it is a commonplace in ordinary discourse there
is hardly a less stringent or less qualified standard of discrimination to which
we can appeal than the simplicity of feeling, nothing more naive than the
subjectivity of sense. But the problem at hand is really quite an extraordinary
one, and while this objection may indeed hold true in ordinary states of
affairs, I think we are compelled to look at it more closely, certainly more
critically, relative to the mystic’s own unique predicament, for upon further
consideration, it turns out that what appears to be, on St. John’s part, an
unsophisticated model of judgment, inevitably emerges as the only possible
criterion available through the logic of the account. Our difficulty in
accepting this criterion, I suggest, vanishes when, by simple substitution, we
understand by the ambiguous term “feeling”, the more accurate term “intuition”
.We must bear in mind, even as we had argued earlier, that what we are in fact
dealing with in this type of supernatural apprehension is ultimately a pure,
unmediated experience. Not, of course, relative to the actual
effects being produced in the soul --- since these are accomplished
“secretly”--- but rather, relative to the accidental qualities attending
these undisclosed effects. These accidents, concurrent with, but unessential to,
the effects being actually achieved, are a matter of experience --- and
experience remains the only criteria available to judgment. All the canons of
rational discrimination, we will remember, including every judgment inflected by
reason, have been sublated according to the uncompromising demands of the via
negativa. Reason, then, antecedently abolished, can pronounce no judgment,
for it can apply no logic to elements of experience to which it has no access.
For the soul reduced to
the passive simplicity of experience-only, there remains merely the
intuition, or in the words of St. John, the feeling, in which this
experience consists --- and it is this simple subjective perception which alone
can possibly constitute a criterion by which the soul is capable of evaluating
the several types of experiences or apprehensions to which it is subject in this
obscure night of the spirit. The distinct and special mode of
supernatural understanding which we have discussed above is, as we had suggested
earlier, really a parenthetical treatment of error which St. John addresses to
emphasize the imperative of pure faith in the soul’s journey to union. In a
sense it is propadeutic to better understanding the general and obscure
mode of supernatural understanding which is really the aspect that is of
particular interest to us in developing a mystical epistemology, for here we are
dealing with the direct, if confused, intuition of God. Unlike its distinct and
special counterpart, this general and obscure mode begins, surprisingly enough,
in the soul’s active practice of meditation prior to its being brought
into the advanced state of contemplation. And it is here that the relation
between meditation and contemplation first becomes
clear.
The “General” and the “Obscure” Mode of
Understanding
Where the distinct and
special mode of supernatural communication had its origin solely in the
divine or diabolical initiative independent of the dispositional attitude of the
soul --- which was, in fact, exhorted to be entirely passive to these
communications --- the general and obscure mode, on the other hand,
begins in the discursive act of meditation. Here the mystic endeavors to
achieve, through increasingly articulated acts of reflection, a greater
knowledge, and therefore a greater love of God (the two are clearly equated by
St. John throughout the text). This knowledge and concomitant love of God,
increasingly attending each particular discursive act, and amplified in the
totality of these acts, through repetition ultimately generates what St. John
calls a continuous and habitual knowledge and love of God as its familiar
object:
“... the end of reasoning and meditation on
the things of God is the gaining of some knowledge and love of God, and each
time that the soul gains this through meditation, it is an act; and just as many
acts, of whatever kind, end by forming a habit in the soul, just so, many of
these acts of loving knowledge which the soul has been making one after another
from time to time come through repetition to be so continuous in it that they
become habitual ... And thus that which aforetime the soul was gaining gradually
through its labor of meditation upon particular facts has now through practice
... become converted and changed into a habit and substance of loving knowledge,
of a general kind, and not distinct and particular as before.” 58
What St. John appears to
be saying is that the various discrete acts of meditation, by virtue of
repetition, coalesce into a general sense of the numinous. Although generated
collectively by these individual and discrete repetitive acts, this
comprehensive sense of the numinous appears to transcend each of them in their
particularity. The soul thus comes, through practice and habit, to what St. John
calls a confused and general knowledge of God which may better be described as
an intensely focused attentiveness to --- and consequently a receptivity towards
--- that of which it has yet only obscurre knowledge. 59
Once again, and
typically, the precise mechanics involved in this psychological transition
remain unaddressed by --- because in a real sense they are unnecessary to ---
St. John, and remain merely to speculated upon. By now, however, St. John has
provided us with the necessary heuristic concepts to assist us in understanding
this transition more completely. Having transcended the discrete and particular
acts characteristic of meditation, the soul must be understood as having
effectively transcended meditation itself, together with the specific and
determinate forms apprehended within it. In transcending these distinct forms,
then, the soul has transcended the activity itself by which they were
acquired --- and as a result has simultaneously entered into the passive
state of contemplation. In other words, the general and numinous sense that
resulted from a continuous and habitual knowledge and love of God has itself
resulted in an epistemological transformation in which not only is the
particularity of form transcended, but the activity that produced that form as
well. The result, whatever it may be, cannot be an epistemological state
characterized by a type of activity that has already been transcended. It must,
then, as a result of this transition, be passive. And not simply passive,
but as a consequence of the transcendence of distinct and clear form, it must of
necessity be general and confused relative to God. In other words, in
transcending this clearly discursive function which passes from one particular
to another, the soul at once and necessarily undergoes a cognitive
transformation resulting in, and characterized by, indeterminate generality ---
a generality in which the penumbra of hitherto distinct particulars merge into,
effectively become continuous with, others in a way that a discursive faculty is
no longer able to accommodate. And it is precisely this indeterminate type of
cognition, this indistinct epistemological state precursive to contemplation,
which St. John understands as the general and obscure
mode.
But that this mode of
understanding is supernaturally communicated to the soul --- and St. John
maintains that it is --- is not entirely clear in the text, for we have seen it
to essentially result from a process of repetition, practice, and habit, in all
of which the soul itself appears to be the principal agent. But by the same
token it is no less clear that in having transcended meditation the soul has
simultaneously transcended what is fundamentally a formal manifold --- a matrix
of distinct forms --- the features of which, however embellished by the
imagination with supernatural qualities, remain natural objects addressed
in the discursive activity of meditation. That is to say, the object taken in
meditation, however meticulously constructed to represent our conception of a
supernatural reality, is always invested with distinct formal features deriving
from, and only occurring within, nature. They are, one and all, distinct,
finite, temporal, and invariably represented as material. And necessarily so,
otherwise they would be incapable of being apprehended by sensuous imagination
as the synthetic faculty operant in every meditation. Consequently, in
transcending, in going beyond, natural objects properly addressed in the
discursive act of meditation --- regardless of the manner in which this
is accomplished --- the cognitive soul has already, and necessarily,
passed on to supernatural objects of contemplation. Nor can the
soul be the author of these supernatural objects, still less the agent behind
this transition, for as a natural agent it cannot produce supernatural effects,
that is to say, effects which are categorically disproportionate to its nature.
This kind of transition simply does not lie within the natural province of the
soul. It must, therefore, be divinely initiated. And this is precisely
the point argued by St. John who maintains that it is God alone who, from
beginning to end, moves the soul --- which, through the prompting of grace,
cooperates with God --- to union with him through infused contemplation.
60
This is not to say,
paradoxically, that the epistemological transition from meditation to
contemplation is immediately recognized by, even as it is enacted within, the
mystic. It is not, as we may suppose, a sudden quantum leap between utterly
incommensurable categories, but rather a gradual transition from distinct and
clear, to confused and general knowledge:
“... when this condition first begins, the
soul is hardly aware of this knowledge, and that for two reasons. First, this
loving knowledge is apt at the beginning to be very subtle and delicate, and
almost imperceptible to the senses. Secondly, when the soul has been accustomed
to that other exercise of meditation, which is wholly perceptible, it is
unaware, and hardly conscious, of this other new and imperceptible condition,
which is purely spiritual ... 61 This general knowledge is at times so
subtle and delicate, particularly when it is most pure and simple and perfect,
most spiritual and most interior, that although the soul is occupied therein, it
can neither realize it nor perceive it ... [ in fact ] when this knowledge is
purest and simplest and most perfect, the understanding is least conscious of it
and thinks of it as most obscure.” 62
Apparently, then, in the
transition from mediation to contemplation, this general and obscure knowledge
is so subtly introduced, so insusceptible to determinate understanding, that it
often escapes not so much a conscious realization, as understanding altogether.
The soul only implicitly, tentatively, experiences God, understanding
neither that which it only perceptibly experiences, nor how it
experiences this obscure intuition of the Absolute. When this “knowledge”, as
St. John calls this intuitive apprehension, is “purest”, or entirely
imperceptible to sense, the transition from meditation to contemplation is
effectively complete. Cognition transcends the perimeters that circumscribe ---
and in so defining, limit --- the forms, figures and conceptions of natural
understanding to which the experiences in contemplation remain forever and
necessarily opaque. It is the “fleeting touch of union” of which St. John
speaks, the pre-noetic confrontation with the Absolute before which
understanding is abolished to nature.
1 AMC
2.8.4
2 AMC 2.8.5 cf.
1.4.4-7
3 AMC 2.4.4 also
cf. 2.26.18
4 AMC 1.13.11+12
also cf. 1 Cor. 2.9 & 2 Cor. 6.10
5 AMC
2.1.1
6 Understood as
encompassing the world of men and matter, as well as the celestial hierarchy of
created spirits ( cf. AMC 2.12.3+4 ).
7 see page ___
of this commentary
8 AMC 2.1.1 ,
DNS 2.23.2
9 Jn.
14.6
10 Jn. 8.44, Gen
3.1-15
11 AMC
2.11.3
12 AMC
2.10.4
13 Rom.
10.14-17
14
AMC 2.3.1 also
cf. 2.9.1
15
This
surprisingly modern epistemological analysis, by the way, precedes the great
17th century empiricists by more than a century, and is treated in
much greater detail by Saint Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274 AD) some four hundred
years prior to Locke and Hume. Cf. S.T. I Q.84 Art. 1-8, Q.85 Art. 1-3 and in
passim. Also, De Potent. Dei Q.3 Art. 5.
16 AMC
2.3.2+3
17
Heb.11.1
18
1 Cor.
2.9
19 cf. AMC
2.22.11, 2.27.1+4, 2.29.12
20 Books I, II,
& III of AMC respectively
21 AMC 2.6.1+2;
cf. DNS 2.21.11
22 AMC
2.6.1-4
23 AMC
3.2.4
24
AMC
3.16.2
25 AMC
2.6.6
26 AMC
2.7.4,7,+11; cf. DNS 2.4.2 & SC 17.11+12
27 AMC
2.7.4+7
28 AMC
2.2.1
29 AMC
2.8.4-5
30
AMC
2.9.1
31 AMC
2.10.2-4
32
AMC
2.10.2
33 e.g. AMC
2.8.4-5, 1.3.3, & 2.3.2+3
34 AMC
2.12.2-3
35 AMC
2.10.4
36 AMC 2.11.3
emphasis added
37 AMC 2.11.7 cf.
2 Cor. 11.14
38 AMC 2.11.2,5,7
& ff.
39 AMC 2.11.2
& 2.19.5+11
40
AMC 2.12.5
& 2.17.3
41 AMC
2.11.9
42 AMC 2.11.2
& 2.26.18
43 Jn.
8.44
44
1 Pet.
5.8
45 AMC
2.11.3
46 AMC
2.11.6
47 AMC
2.19.10
48 AMC
2.20.6
49 AMC
2.19.1
50 AMC
2.23.1
51 AMC
2.23.2&3
52
AMC
2.23.3
53
AMC
2.23.2
54 AMC
2.23.3
55
AMC
2.24.4
56 AMC 2.26.4
emphases added
57 AMC
2.24.8
58 AMC
2.14.2
59 AMC
2.15.2-5
60 AMC 1.1.5
etc.
61 AMC
2.14.7
62 AMC
2.14.8
(Continued below)
III
The last faculty remaining to be discussed is memory. It is
the subject of the third and final book of the Ascent and with it we will
effectively conclude our examination of the fundamental principles presupposed
in our analysis of St. John's metaphysics in Part II of our commentary.
Our approach, to be sure, in dealing with memory, will be much the same as in
our treatment of the will and understanding, and for this reason we shall be
spared much unnecessary detail. But first, let us be clear about what St. John
understands by memory, and in answering this, we shall at once discover
the reason for the brevity of our account. For St. John, memory is simply the
repository of forms received through the five senses 1 and in its
subordinate capacity as imagination, it is capable of variously
synthesizing these forms and producing still other forms with which the soul had
hitherto been unacquainted, at least in their synthetic unity. In effect, then,
memory is the subsumption of nature under the synthetic activity of imagination.
All the imperatives, then, that apply to nature, and all the principles involved
in its negation prior to union, equally apply to nature as internalized in
memory and synthesized in imagination. Very briefly, then, since the memory is
principally occupied with retaining and synthesizing various sensuous forms
ultimately deriving from nature, we can succinctly state that, as Spirit, God is
contrary to nature, and conversely, as subsumed under nature, form --- delimited
and finite --- is contrary to God. 2 The soul, then, is once again constrained to subject itself
--- this time relative to the faculty off memory --- to the rigors of the via
negativa. just as it had done relative to the will and understanding, in
order to eliminate
within itself that
contrariety to God which is preclusive of union. It must become transformed,
together with the will and the understanding, into that otherness of God to
nature, and as a consequence, rendered other to its own natural
economy.
Once more we find that
two levels of negation are discernible in this transformation: the negation
of nature according to memory, in which the soul ceases to appropriate and
synthesize forms variously derived from the senses, thus negating nature. And,
implicitly following from this first order of negation, the negation of
memory according to nature in which the memory, having ceased from
appropriating and synthesizing these sensuously derived forms, has effectively
ceased in its natural function qua mnemonic. This resulting state of absolute
negativity --- the categorical negation of nature and memory --- is, for St.
John, simultaneously the transformation of the memory into the negativity of
hope, its corresponding theological virtue which is understood by St. John to
essentially constitute a state of radical dispossession.
3
There is, interestingly
enough, one notable exception --- and this only occurs in the Alcalà edition of
1618 --- to the rule which requires the memory to be completely emptied of all
forms and images: and this is the Sacred Humanity of Christ who, as both True
God and True Man, remains, for St. John, the most proper object of both
meditation and contemplation.4 However true this may be, to leave our answer simply at this
is to gloss over some very real difficulties that arise as a result of this
exception, for a good deal more than the simple humanity of Christ is insinuated
into our account through it; indeed, through a broader consideration, it
implicitly involves elements which have been found to be antagonistic to union
elsewhere in the account. This type of incongruity occurs once again in the
Dark Night of the Soul, and while I think these are significant features
that must be dealt with, the broader issues from which they arise must be
addressed more in terms of St. John’s own historical context than from any
strictly epistemological consideration. Our discussion of this apparent
inconsistency, inviting though it may be at the present, must wait until our
examination of the Dark Night of the Soul where the opportunity will
better present itself within another context altogether.
We have already found,
much in line with our previous analyses, that the memory must be negated of all
knowledge, form, and figure in order to be transformed into its corresponding
theological virtue of hope which is explicitly negative:
“For all possession is contrary to hope,
which, as St. Paul says, belongs to that which is not possessed. 5 Wherefore, the more the memory
dispossesses itself, the greater is its hope, and the more it has of hope, the
more it has of union with God ... and it hopes most when it is most completely
dispossessed, and when it shall be perfectly dispossessed, it will remain with
the perfect possession of God in Divine union.” 6
This is a somewhat
misleading passage, for one gets the impression that when the negative moment is
actualized in perfect hope, this alone is sufficient to effect union with God.
But we have clearly seen that this is not the case. There is no ‘causal’
connection between attaining the state of negation and the realization of union,
still less a necessary transition logically implied, as we shall later
see. For the moment let us simply say that in achieving the state of perfect
dispossession which St. John calls hope, the soul is not for that reason, and at
once, brought to union with God. Rather, as we had seen in the case of love
(will) and faith (understanding), it is only brought into a state of
proximity to God --- the state of absolute negativity not only relative
to nature, but to itself as well.
This persistent emphasis
on the negative dimensions of experience within the several ‘nights’ that we
have examined is, in this concluding chapter of the Ascent, clearly
explained as ultimately having one purpose:
“... all means must be proportioned to
the end; that is to say, they must have some connection and resemblance with the
end, such as is enough and sufficient for the desired end to be attained through
them.” 7
Now, we have seen that no
positive commensurability is capable of being established between metaphysically
incommensurable categories, between the means and the end --- how then, we must
ask, is this statement to be understood? This passage, I think, is extremely
interesting in several respects, and before passing on to a consideration
of our own immediate question, I think it would be worthwhile for us to consider
another issue, not entirely tangential from our present purpose; an issue that
really ought to be addressed, if only briefly, in light of what St. John has
said above. Understanding this first will provide us with a broader perspective
of the constant dialectic that occurs throughout the text. And it is this: a
kind of teleology is suggested in the account which, positively considered,
ultimately finds its ground in what, for St. John, is man’s essentially
reflective ontology in relation to the Absolute, as image of the Absolute
--- an Absolute itself understood in terrms of love. We had addressed this point
briefly earlier. While some degree of commensurability is capable of being
established between man and God through love, love itself --- through which
alone this commensurability is possible --- is not an inherent metaphysical
feature of man’s essential ontology independent of the Absolute. Love in fact
is the essential ontological feature of man qua image of
God, but for St. John, as we shall later see, man’s essential ontology is of
itself the mere possibility of reflection --- given the
Reflected. And this is to say that the soul is, substantivally considered, not
in itself an autonomous being, but rather, being-contingent-upon-the-Absolute
--- that is to say, being heteronymously derived, and not self-subsistent
apart from the Absolute. And this, of course, is not merely entirely consistent
with a traditional theological understanding of the nature of the soul --- but
in fact is an expression of it. In other words, it is not the case that the soul
of itself is understood to be commensurable with God, but that the soul
as the image actively reflecting God is, and it is seen to be
commensurable only insofar as it does in fact reflect the Absolute. And this, in
turn, is essentially to say that man’s being, fundamentally considered, cannot,
for St. John, be established independently of God. Consequently, the authentic
nature of man’s being is only teleologically actualized through his
participation in God --- and this direct participation is what St. John
ultimately understands in the notion of union. We will discuss this in much
greater detail the second part of our commentary.
Means and Ends
Returning once again to
the point from which we departed, we had said that since no positive
commensurability can be established between metaphysically incommensurable
categories, between the means and the end, how are we to understand St. John
when he insists that the “means must be proportioned to the end”, and sufficient
for the desired end to be attained through them? It would appear that the
‘means’ of which St. John is speaking are, after careful examination, the three
theological virtues that we have been addressing in one form or another all
along. And St. John has been unequivocally clear about the negative nature of
these virtues. The sort of proportion, then, that St. John appears to be calling
for might well be more appositely described as negative commensurability;
a commensurability achieved through abolishing all contrariety to God in the
via negativa, and simultaneously positing at each successive moment in
the account a theological virtue, explicitly negative in nature, through which
alone, he has repeatedly insisted, the soul attains to a state of
proximity to God. And this is further to say that what we confront here,
in effect, is a kind of teleological negativity; a movement toward establishing
commensurability negatively; not so much, as St. John inadvertently
misleads us here, in the form of resemblance, as in the absence of
contrariety.
Let us take a different
tack. Through these various negative moments, or ‘nights’, the soul only becomes
commensurable with the Absolute inasmuch as it is no longer
incommensurable with it. It is not so much commensurability understood as
rendering the soul to be what God is --- this is not possible, for God is
infinitely inexhaustible --- but not to be what God is not. In other
words, the soul achieves proximity to God negatively. It proximates, is
commensurable with God, not in that it possesses characteristics in common with
God, but in that it does not possess certain characteristics that God
also does not possess --- and this essentially is the concept of negative
commensurability. Implicit, of course, in the concept of negative
commensurability is the logic of negative predication. According to this logic,
we are unable to derive logical warrant for ascribing a community of properties
or attributes, positively considered, to intrinsically different things simply
because they share identical predicates negatively considered. Not-red can be
yellow or blue. Given something characterized as Not-red, we have no
logical warrant whatever to understand this as indicating blue rather
than yellow, or any other color in the spectrum for that matter. In fact, we
have no warrant whatever of predicating anything at all of it, outside of the
fact that it is Not-Red. Negative predicates, in other words, provide us with no
information whatever about being positively considered.
Perhaps we can shed more
light on this fundamental feature of mysticism by considering another dimension
to the problem. It is very difficult to see how hope as a virtual state of
negativity on the one hand, can be proportioned to God who, on the other, is the
plenitude of being. To attempt to answer this in terms of negative
commensurability is not to establish proportion or resemblance, as we have just
seen, but merely, and at best, non-contrariety. How then is ‘proportion’ or
‘resemblance’ effected? To answer this we must return for a moment to our
previous understanding of the virtue of hope. As the opposite of possession ---
which for the memory consists in the retention of created (natural) knowledge,
form, and figure --- hope may equally be seen to be the implicit opposite of
nature. And as we had seen earlier, the opposite of nature in the metaphysical
understanding of St. John is spirit --- which is both proximate
and similar, and therefore, proportioned to God. This very clearly follows if by
spirit we understand not-nature as synonymous with spirit --- and
this synonymy is unmistakably implied throughout the account. Whatever
not-nature understood as spirit is, it is something positively predicated of
God. St. John, then, argues consistently when he maintains that the three
theologicalvirtues are in fact proportionate to God, and therefore the only
proximate means to mystical union with him.
A Matter of Form
At this point, the memory
has been negated of all created knowledge, form, and figure; it no longer
archives, reproduces, or synthesizes the store of data it initially acquired
through the senses, but rather assumes an attitude of totally passive
receptivity. But what, precisely, is the memory receptive to in this
state of negation? On the one hand it cannot be phenomena delivered by reason or
sense, both having been antecedently abolished. And yet, on the other hand, what
are we left with if all figure and form have been categorically abolished along
with reason and sense? But, St. John argues, they have not been so ---
except relative to matter and reason.. It is not the case that the concept
of form itself has been
abolished --- indeed, it is a fundamental principle of the scholastic reasoning
with which St. John was so well acquainted that God himself is, in the words of
St. Thomas Aquinas, “of His essence a form, and not composed of matter
and form.”
8 What has been abolished, rather,
is form as limitation --- a limitation specific to nature and coterminous
with matter or co-conceptual within reason. It is, to extrapolate upon Aquinas’s
own argument, form that is not self-subsisting, but dependent upon matter as the
individuating principle of the form.
But the notion itself of
form, as preeminently exemplified in God, is not limited to matter and reason.
And it is this type of form which, St. John argues, is passively received either
as purely spiritual intuitions, or, in the case of those mediated by sensuous
form and figure, received not according to their various sensuous
configurations, but rather, according to the spiritual
form
9 latent in these impressions. The soul, St. John tells us,
remains indifferent to the accidents, or accidental qualities if you will, that
attend these essentially spiritual perceptions, for the memory has been
effectively negated to all capacity for (natural) form and figure.
Regrettably, St. John does not ---
perhaps by the very nature of the experience, cannot --- elaborate on the nature
of these spiritual forms. I think that the latter case is most likely, for in
themselves they appear to be, from the general drift of his argument, absolutely
pure intuitions, immediate experiences that, as such, are essentially
recalcitrant to language --- which, we had said earlier, presumes shared
experiences to its intelligibility. I also think it unlikely that the term
form relative to spirit, in the way St. John conjoins the two,
denotes the type of specificity and distinctness we ordinarily associate with
our sensible apprehension of material compositions. It is, I think, much more
likely that the term form, at least in the present context, denotes
something a good deal more ambiguous, something more in the way of a ‘distinct
spiritual impression’ or a distinct intuition entailing nothing more in the way
of perceptible phenomena.
This interpretation seems
to be borne out by St. John’s insistence that the memory in the state of
negation is nevertheless capable of recollecting these spiritual forms of
uncreated knowledge as simple noetic intuitions:
“Now, after the soul has experienced one of
these apprehensions, it can recall it whenever it will; and this not by the
effigy and image that the apprehension has left in the bodily sense, for, since
this is of bodily form, as we say, it has no capacity for spiritual forms; but
because it recalls it intellectually and spiritually, by means of that form
which it has left impressed upon the soul which is likewise a formal or
spiritual form ...”
10
These forms, then, of
which St. John speaks, appear to be sheer noetic intuitions containing
nothing analogous to the clear, distinct, and determinate phenomena apprehended
by the senses and which we characteristically understand as instantiating form.
The intuitive character of these specialized forms is most clearly expressed in
the element of experience necessary to their being
recollected:
“... by no form, image, or figure which can
be impressed upon the soul does the memory recall these [spiritual forms], for
these touches and impressions of union with the Creator have no
form, but only by the effects which they have produced upon it of light,
love, joy, and spiritual renewal, and so forth ...” 11
That St. John has, in
this passage, encountered some terminological difficulties as a consequence of
his attempt to inflect the rigorous and basically inflexible limitations in
language, is obvious, for in attempting to describe these essentially
indescribable (intuitive) spiritual forms --- that is to say, in an effort to
accommodate them, to make them accessible, to reason --- he simultaneously and
paradoxically describes them as having no form at all. This apparent
contradiction seems to result from his having failed to clearly articulate the
meaning of “spiritual form” in and of itself; especially as it is to be
distinguished from our understanding of the word “form” in ordinary discourse.
In fact, the term form in the second sense (“... have no form ...”)
refers to our understanding of the word as it applies to distinct, clear, and
sensuously embodied apprehensions --- and not to the noetic intuitions
themselves. This contention, I think, is particularly borne out by St. John’s
insistence that the memory recalls these spiritual forms “only by the
effects which they have produced upon it”, which he then goes on to
enumerate them as light, love, joy, renewal, etc.
Now, implied in all this
is a latent connection between recollection, or memory, and knowledge --- and
not just knowledge, but a particular kind of knowledge: uncreated
knowledge. And this
connection clearly implicates the element of experience. This uncreated
knowledge communicated to the soul and subsequently archived in memory is not
retrieved abstractly in the way that, say, geometric theorems are, nor in the
remote way that empirically acquired knowledge (which is no longer concurrent
with the experience through which it was initially acquired) is. While the
form of each of these types remains, in a manner of speaking, resident in
memory, the matter to which the form corresponds clearly does not:
neither the line which in essence we spatially conceptualize, and
from which we extrapolate a purely rational geometric definition, nor yet
impressions of sensible objects with which we once had immediate,
empirical acquaintance and now retrieve as remote from the material
objects themselves. What we recall is the form of the object, and not,
obviously, the object itself which is no longer concurrent with the
form.
This, however, is not to
say that the form and the object can no longer coincide. Clearly they can ---
but only upon a renewed experience of the object. And this coincidence,
or concurrence remains only as long as the experience itself remains. For St.
John, however, the recollection of these forms is independent of a concurrent
experience of the matter from which these mere forms are derived. In
other words, the object is only formally retained in the
soul.
On the other hand, the
spiritual forms of which St. John speaks appear to essentially produce an
effect on the soul, the matter of which is the experience of the
effect, which to recall, in turn, is to renew the experience in which the effect
consists. And this --- a recollection concurrent with the experience from which
it evolved --- is only possible because it is neither abstractly, nor remotely
retrieved from memory; rather, the recollection entails an immediate experience
because it is essentially the soul’s experience of itself, or more
precisely, the self modified by the effects of grace introduced by these
spiritual forms which now inhere subsistently in the soul and as such are
always concurrent with it as intuitions of itself.
As we now clearly see, it
is not the case that will, understanding, and memory are categorically
abolished: that the soul no longer wills, or has cognitive activity, or has
remembrance (as much of the language we have used thus far appears to imply).
The soul in fact is annihilated --- but not unto itself; rather it
is annihilated relative to the natural exercise of these faculties;
faculties which, in the end, are not categorically abolished in and of
themselves. Rather, the annihilation of which St. John speaks consists in the
transformation of these natural faculties into their corresponding
theological virtues which, utilizing the epistemological structures framed by
nature, 12 supplants the natural activity (unable to accommodate
supernatural phenomena) with supernatural activity which alone is sufficient to
it.
An Explication of the Notion of the
“Faculties”
Now that we have arrived
at a rudimentary understanding of the faculties involved, it is equally
important to examine the relation between them. To begin with, understanding and
memory, as St. John points out, both in their natural capacities, and in the
state of negation, are not of themselves autonomous; rather, he seems to imply,
they appear to be unified in their subordination to the will.13 Here, in this last division of the Ascent, St. John
finally concludes his treatment of the soul in its sensuous economy with some
closing remarks on that faculty through which the soul, as an organic unity,
attains to the consummate state of perfection, or beatitude in God. It remains
only to be demonstrated that the three faculties of the soul --- will,
understanding, and memory --- are in fact integrated, unified, in the will’s
transformation into the cardinal theological virtue of love. In treating of the
relation of the four passions --- joy, hope, grief, and fear --- to the three
theological virtues, St. John argues the following:
“... these four passions of the soul are so
closely and intimately united to one another that the actual direction of one is
the virtual direction of the others; and if one be actually recollected the
other three will virtually and proportionately be recollected likewise. For if
the will rejoice in anything, it will as a result hope for the same thing ...
Wherefore ... wheresoever one of these passions is, thither will go likewise the
whole soul and the will and the other faculties ...” 14
Although at this point he
is arguably dealing only with the passions, a broader understanding of the
dialectic involved is clearly warranted, for according to the gist of this
argument, the nature of the will is such that the remaining faculties are
unified through the intentionality of the will, and it is precisely this
facultative union through intentionality which we must now attempt to grasp
before venturing any further. What St. John appears to be implying at this point
is simply this: in the state of negation into which the contemplative has
entered, we are unable to understand either the aspirations of hope or the
convictions of faith apart from the object of intention first appropriated
through the will. Through an irreducible act of will (love), an act divinely
inspired, the soul appropriates to the understanding the articles of faith
relating to the object of its love, and these articles of faith, in turn, are
archived in memory to inform hope. And this is simply to say that understanding
and memory, faith and hope, acquire a facultative union through the
intentionality of the will, relative both to the exercise of each faculty in
accordance with the intentionality of the will, and in the object
respectively acquired by each faculty subsequent to this exercise. In other
words, the soul hopes only for what it loves, and the object of hope is only
accessible through faith which is fundamentally appropriated through an act of
will. Delete any element and the dialectic is incomplete, the intelligibility of
each virtue vanishes. In short, we cannot understand hope apart from love, nor
faith apart from hope.
But let us carry this a
step further; in fact, to its logical conclusion. God, as we have seen, has
clearly been equated with love by St. John throughout the account: man is made
in the image of God, and this image of God in man is love. These faculties,
then, so unified in love, are at least implicitly unified in God. But
there are, in fact, two levels of unity corresponding, respectively, to the
unity in God only implicit in the state of nature, and the unity in God rendered
explicit in what St. John calls supernatural
transformation.
Perhaps we can best
summarize his line of reasoning this way: As latent in the state of nature,
any love is an implicit unity in God through the created participation of
the soul in God as the imago Dei. The soul’s ability to love derives
from, is radicated in, its created nature as the image of God who is
love; consequently the unity of the faculties in any love implicitly owes this
unity to God. In other words, the unifying nature of love is only latently
discernible within and remotely ascribable to, God. The soul, in fact, is
unified in its love for anything. That this unifying agency of love
derives essentially from the soul’s ontological status as the image of God, is only implicit in its
nature.
As explicit in
transformation, however, love is that reflective resonance become explicit
between the Imaged and the image --- the unifying nature of love is seen to
derive immediately, essentially, from God in the soul’s noetic realization of
itself as image of the Absolute. In this state of transformation, the soul’s
unifying capacity qua image, and that in which it is unified, are explicitly one
and the same --- and this sameness is nothing less than union in God. The soul
is no longer unified in its love for the other of God in nature, a love
metaphysically constrained from union by the ontological disparity between the
lover and the loved, in the absence of that reflection in which the lover
realizes his being to be one with the Beloved, a reflective existence
inseparably bound to the Reflected. Rather, it has realized itself as the
reflection-of-God into God, and it is in dealing with this divine
reflexivity to which St. John, on increasingly explicit levels, devotes the rest
of his treatises, all of which fundamentally derive from the mystical doctrines
and presuppositions which we have examined in the Ascent of Mount Carmel.
It is, in effect, the soul’s ascent to the mount of the transfiguration; the
realization of the reflection of divinity lying deeply, profoundly, in the soul
of every man and woman. The nature of this union, this reflexivity or resonance
that is the apotheosis of the soul in God, now remains to be examined in Part
II.
1 AMC
3.2.4
2 We must not
conclude, however, that the notion of form does not apply to God. Indeed,
it does not apply to God as limitative. But as Self-subsisting and
unindividuated by matter, form is, for St. John, as well as for his predecessors
in the Scholastic tradition, clearly ascribable to God. Cf. ST Q.3
art.2
3
AMC 3.7.2 &
3.11.2
4 AMC 3.2.14
(Editio Princeps, Alcala, 1618)
5
Heb.
11.1
6 AMC
3.7.2
7
AMC
2.8.2
8
cf. ST Q.3
art.2
9 AMC 3.14.1
& 2. This rather perplexing notion reappears in Part II where it
becomes somewhat clearer.
10
AMC
3.14.1
11 AMC 3.14.2,
emphasis added
12
Which is simply
another way of saying that grace builds upon nature.
13 AMC
3.16.2
14 AMC 3.16.5
& 6
(continued below)
PART II
THE METAPHYSICS
An Enchiridion to Reality
It should be reasonably clear by now that the Ascent of
Mount Carmel --- and, for that matter, a significant part of the Dark
Night of the Soul --- is not, nor was it intended to be, a theoretical
treatise in speculative mysticism. It is, as we had insisted from the beginning,
first and foremost an enchiridion, a practical guide for the contemplative. Each
of these complimentary treatises were, in fact, written largely upon the
insistence of St. John’s notable contemporary, St. Teresa of Avila, and were
primarily intended for the use of the contemplative nuns of the newly reformed
Order of Discalced Carmelites. Hence, St. John’s almost inordinate preoccupation
with the relevance of such practical issues as the via negativa, the
relation of the theological virtues to mystical experience, natural and
supernatural modes of understanding, diabolical deception, and the notions of
judgment and error.
I think it is very
clearly the case that St. John could have written otherwise and dealt
cogently with issues of speculative interest to theologians and philosophers
alike, but in a greater sense I think he would have viewed this as an altogether
gratuitous exercise. The speculative aspects of mysticism --- while of the
greatest interest to the epistemologist --- are entirely aside from the point.
They are, in a very real sense, superfluous to the mystic who has not merely
speculated upon, but experienced the Absolute and who, in light of this
experience, has consequently been completely reoriented to the priorities
pertaining to his existence. Speculation is well and fine inasmuch as reason is
held --- among the tenets of Christian doctrine --- to pervade the universe.
This type of speculative enterprise may indeed result in a legitimate, if
limited and remote, understanding of the correspondence between constituent
aspects of the Absolute --- but this type of speculation is essentially
pointless, in a larger sense even meaningless, before the actual experience
itself. To wit: it may be of the greatest interest to me to endeavor to explore
and synthesize physics, chromatics, and ophthalmology in order to arrive at an
understanding of the experience of the color purple which --- being
color-deficient --- I have never seen, and am unable to see. But were I suddenly
to acquire adequate color perception, I would, I think, dispense with this
exercise altogether in favor of the experience itself beside which the analysis
is only, merely, academic to my purpose, and in any event would yield nothing of
that unique chromatic perception to me. Nothing, in other words, short of the
experience itself, would suffice. Now, while my sudden experience of the color
purple will not radically reorient my life, the direct experience of God, I
suggest, will. For it involves a good deal more than the
characteristically brief experience itself described by the mystics. It
effectively serves to validate, to authenticate, everything which faith binds to
the existence of God. And this in turn will decisively reorient my priorities
subsequent to this experience --- a reorientation that will result in an
entirely new and different perspective corresponding to no longer a perceived,
but an experienced Reality. To the mystic, then, the emphasis is
inexorably practical, for it is not merely theory, but reality --- in fact the
ens realissimum that he has encountered vis-à-vis God. Does this, then,
abrogate faith? Not in the least. Indeed, for St. John faith has been the
indispensable means to this realization.
But St. John’s treatise,
we must equally insist, is not simply a practical guide to mystical union
--- although it was written as such. Forr us, as we had stated in the beginning,
it is also a propadeutic to the possibility of articulating a mystical
epistemology. And while St. John clearly did not understand himself to be
formulating an epistemological doctrine in the writing of his several treatises,
there are, nevertheless --- and quite necessarily --- clear epistemological
elements, assumptions, and presuppositions implicit within the texts which lend
themselves to the development a coherent mystical epistemology. That they do so
at all is no small tribute to the profound insight, the keen intellect and
precise reasoning of their author. In fairness we must say that St. John clearly
understood his task as being descriptive, and not primarily analytical. He was
concerned with describing --- as much as inherently is possible --- the mystical
experience in all its myriad and luminous facets; and when, periodically, he
does undertake to analyze the concepts involved, it is done of expedience, and
only to supplement the account, to substantiate the description, and to
demonstrate both its logical nature and its clear correspondence with orthodox
doctrine. And this is to say that since the epistemological elements in St.
John’s doctrine are implicit only, it is the task of the reader to elicit form
from --- indeed, occasionally to impose form upon --- the various arguments as
they occur throughout the treatises if he hopes to arrive at that implicit
synthesis which binds the whole of his account into a coherent epistemological
doctrine.
The Spriritual Night of Negation
The Ascent of Mount
Carmel, it will be remembered, dealt principally with the ‘night of sense’
or sensuous negation, and this was seen to necessarily precede the possibility
of mystical union --- once again, we say ‘possibility’ because sensuous negation
of itself, as we had found earlier, is no guarantee that mystical union will
then follow, in the sense that it should causally necessitate it --- and
this theme is not immediately abandoned in the Dark Night of the Soul. In
fact, it necessarily precedes the ‘night of the spirit’ or spiritual negation as
one of the antecedents or premises in the logic of mysticism. Nevertheless it is
only addressed transitionally as that residual sensibility prior to the negation
of spirit which itself is the complete subjection of sense. As a stage of
transition, however, the eradication of sense is not something abruptly
achieved; it is more a gradual and centripetal movement away from the
superficies of sensibility --- toward the metaphysical subsistence of
spirit. Moreover, very definite subjective indications accompany this
transition: for example, meditation and sensible imagination --- which hitherto
provided the soul with a framework of orientation relative to God --- no longer
serve as reliable criteria of the soul’s spiritual progress to
union.1 In other words, that residual sensibility to both
subjective and objective phenomena, both of which are other to God ---
and this shall be extremely important later on --- which formerly provided the
soul with a frame of reference in its relation to God, suddenly and inexplicable
fails:
“When they are going about these spiritual
exercises with the greatest delight and pleasure, and when they believe that the
sun of divine favor is shining most brightly upon them, God turns all this light
of theirs into darkness ... and leaves them ... completely in the dark.”
2
This failure of
sensibility to orient the soul to God effectively brings to completion the night
of sense and inaugurates the night of the spirit. Sensibility, as an
epistemological factor, is thus abolished relative to God.
This may strike us, at
first, as a rather dramatic conclusion; one which we are initially inclined to
see as essentially both radical and readily contestable. After all, we well may
argue, the very notion of mystical union essentially --- indeed, by definition
---consists in
the experience of
God. And does not the very notion of experience itself presuppose sensibility?
This is quite a paradox. How shall we answer it? To what can we appeal that will
not at once involve us in a contradiction? If mystical union is essentially an
experience, and if, furthermore, the very notion of experience is
radicated in sensibility, how are we to understand the experience, not simply as
subsequent to, but as necessarily preceded by, the abolishing of the very
sensibility which the experience itself appears to presume? We must, I suggest,
look for our answer in a more comprehensive understanding of the key notion of
participation, and while we had addressed this notion briefly within the
context of several previous discussions, it now becomes critical to examine this
concept more closely. To begin with, in the state of infused contemplation, were
the soul’s relation to God characterized by a rigorously explicit
individuation--- that is to say, one in a which a clearly perceived and
reciprocal relation of disparity existed --- then the notion of union
would be meaningless. There would be, not merely an implied, but an explicit
distinction between that which experienced, and that which was experienced; in
fact, the type of relationship generally understood in terms of the distinction
between a subject and an object --- that is to say, the subject which
experiences, and the object experienced. But it is precisely this type of
distinction which the mystic’s notion of union cannot admit of. We are faced,
then, with an apparent dilemma: on the one hand there can be no union, and on
the other, no experience. No union because of the inherent bifurcation of
subject and object; and, in the abrogation of sensibility, no experience
possible of the one by the other. To further complicate matters, were the notion
of union unqualified and absolute --- presuming, of course, the possibility of
union at all, given this dilemma --- it would appear to involve, at the very
least, the annihilation of the distinct identity of the one or, subsequent to
what amounts to a substantival union, a modification in the identity of the
other.
Both alternatives are
equally unacceptable to St. John. And not merely because they are alien to the
mind of the Church, but simply because they are not consonant with the
metaphysics underlying his mystical doctrine. In fact, the apparent dilemma is,
upon a closer examination of this metaphysics, found to be essentially spurious,
resulting not so much from defective, as from incomplete reasoning, for yet a
third concept remains to be addressed; a concept in virtue of which issues
involving our dilemma, together with the problem of identity, are ultimately
seen to be unrelated to our account --- and this is the notion of
participatory union. St. John had argued the point earlier, and we will
restate it once again: Sensibility can, and must, be abolished in a notion of
union through participation. As long as sensibility is retained, then the
inherent subject/object distinction is retained as well.
The Central Notion of Participation
As we have suggested,
however, an examination of the notion of mystical union as it evolves in the
account of St. John reveals that this union is not characterized by the
subject/object distinction at all --- which is an external distinction,
one to which the notion of sensibility applies. Rather, we find, it is
characterized by the participant / participated-in distinction --- which
is an internal distinction, one to which an attenuated notion of
identity applies. Subject is eternally other to object in their purely
external relation. However, the distinction that obtains between the participant
and that-participated-in cannot so readily be rendered into terms that lend
themselves to this type of complementary antithesis. It is not a relation
characterized by inherent and reciprocal otherness, but rather, by inherent
sameness --- by an attenuated notion of identity implicit within the
concept of participation itself. Let us put this more clearly to our purpose.
The very notion of participation itself implies a logical antecedent in the form
of an existential proposition in virtue of which alone the notion becomes
meaningful: the logically prior element --- the participated-in, or
unparticipated being --- is that in virtue of which the latter --- the
participating-in, or participated being --- assumes certain definite predicates
deriving from, and in fact identical with, the former..3 We find, however, that the notion of participation is
generally spoken of in reference not to some form of being, but to some form of
activity. We do not participate in “beings” ordinarily understood as
discrete ontic existents, but rather, in activities predicated of being. But if
this in fact is the case, it is not so much a relation of identity which obtains
between the two things to which the predicate activity is attached, as a
sharing in identical activities, and this is quite another thing. “Activity”
clearly is not in itself a substantival existent; there is nothing apart from
the activity which itself is merely a predicate of being, and not in
itself a being. Activity, then, is not a being, but something predicated of
being. What, then, can the nature of this logically prior element be, such that
it admits of the notion of identity --- especially inasmuch as it may possibly
apply through the concept of participation? In the logic of mysticism there
must be an essence which coincides with activity, otherwise
participation in this activity would never result in an identity between the two
elements involved, merely a sharing in identical activities. In God, however ---
and here is the crux of the matter --- being and activity are held to
coincide.4
In the Book of Exodus ---
which is really the locus classicus of the conception itself within
mystical theology at large --- God reveals himself to Moses as the “Ego sum qui
sum”, or “He who is” .God is a being who is active being, that is
to say, being understood not simply as static ontology, but as dynamic activity.
In the words of St. Thomas Aquinas, he is the “quod est esse
simpliciter”, or that which is absolutely. In other words, God is an
activity whose essence coincides with his activity --- or conversely, God is an
essence whose activity coincides with his essence.5 However one looks at it, since God is the esse ipsum,
the Being-in-Itself, his activity is, as such, quintessentially substantival,
identical and coincidental with his being. So understood, it is not merely the
case that we achieve a more adequate ontological perspective of God, but at one
and the same time we finally arrive at a coherent understanding of the dynamics
of union itself. We had stated earlier that our understanding of the notion of
participation was invariably tied up with a conception of activity; that we do
not characteristically understand ourselves as able to participate in beings as
such, but rather, in activities predicated of being, in which case we may be
said to share in identical activities, and not in the being itself in which
these activities are enacted. But since God is a Being whose essence is
activity --- to participate in this activity is to participate in a
Being, to participate in God; in fact, it is to assume, participatorily,
those very predicates which attach to this Activity which is God --- and
as a participatory relation, to assume, not the identity of God, but
an identity with God. In this state of consummate or perfect
participation which we call ecstatic union, the notion of otherness, then, does
not, indeed, cannot, coherently apply. It is fundamentally, if only temporarily,
abolished in what has become effectively an apotheosized
identity.
Participation and the Problem of
Identity
Paradoxically, however,
this is not to say that a distinction does not yet persist, or is no longer
discernible between the soul and God. Unlike the Neoplatonists and other
pre-Christian, and for that matter, post-Christian, and Vedantic phenomenologies
in which the distinct identity of the soul is held to be categorically
annihilated in its union with the Absolute --- leaving no vestige of personal
identity and, subsequently, no latent notion of individuation --- the Christian
mystic understands himself to be, even in the most sublime, the most intimate
moment of ecstatic union, at least implicitly cognizant of his unique
ontological status as a participant in the being of God, and not as
constituting the Unparticipated Being Itself. The distinction which remains,
however --- unlike that which preceded union, and which, we will remember, was
characterized by an irreconcilable ontological polarity --- is now an
internal distinction; it is a distinction ultimately sublated in what is
essentially a notion of participated identity. What we mean is this: the
soul in the state of ecstatic union essentially possesses an identity that is
ultimately seen to be at once both inherent and acquired: it is inherent
in that the soul is implicitly constituted as the imago Dei, and this
fundamentally reflective ontology presumes the Absolute as reflected. In other
words, the Absolute as the imaged is presumed in the identity of the
image. On the other hand, it is no less acquired in that this
image becomes explicit --- informed, actual --- only through, and subsequent to
--- in other words, in virtue of --- uniion with the Absolute; it is acquired in
that its identity as image can only perfectly coincide with the Absolute --- and
so be totally, authentically, enacted, realized --- given the Absolute in
that unobstructed encounter we call mystical union in which the Imaged is
brought perfectly to bear upon the image. Its identity as the imago Dei
is no longer implicit in the state of union, and that identity, reflecting the
Absolute, now of necessity perfectly coincides with it.
If the distinction
between the soul and God so understood, however, still strikes us as tentative,
it does so because it is essentially incomplete. Indeed, a casual analysis of
this metaphysically nuanced distinction in and of itself is likely to
precipitate several problems involving semantic issues that must be clarified
first if the distinction we have made is not to be found ultimately spurious.
Our most important question, then, is this: Has an adequate notion of
distinction really been achieved after all? And while we should find it tiresome
to ferret out every possible point of contention --- and I am certain there are
many in this commentary that I have not begun to anticipate --- this particular
issue at hand cannot be turned aside without our account suffering needlessly,
so let us look at our argument once again. In effect we have said that the soul
is the image of God and that its identity as such is most authentically acquired
and subsequently enacted when it encounters, in that unobstructed moment of
union, God whom it then faithfully images. But here is the problem. If the
identity of the soul is exclusively defined by, and is essentially coterminous
with, the identity of God, it is very difficult to distinguish any individuating
factor through which the unique personality of the soul is preserved subsequent
to this union of identities. The ontological distinction we have examined so far
yields only an abstract notion of differentiation; one which does not seem to
culminate in a preservation of unique and separate identities. The image
still appears undifferentiated from the Imaged. It is well to say
the two in fact are distinct, but upon what is this notion of distinction
predicated if the one is held to be indiscernible from the other; if the
identity of the one is equally ascribable to the other? How are we to respond to
this? Are we then, by the logic of our own argument constrained to say that the
soul, in virtue of the ontological parameters defining its being solely in terms
of its reflective nature qua image, loses its unique identity in its union with
the Absolute? If so, then we have arrived at a conclusion essentially no
different from that of the Neoplatonists. And this is clearly not what St. John
intends to argue, nor, in fact, do his metaphysics lend themselves to this
essentially abbreviated conclusion. For our answer, I suggest, we must look
closely at what St. John says relative to the identity of the soul in
this state of union.
In an extremely important
passage previously cited, St. John tells us that the soul in the state of
ecstatic union “appears” to be God Himself 6, and I think that a
closer look at what is actually involved in this notion will prove useful.
This apparent identity authentically corresponds to the identity of
God inasmuch as it is God’s image; it is the perfect, unblemished reflection of
God much in the way that a flawless mirror perfectly reflects the object held up
before it. The resulting correspondence, we might say, is such that the one is
indistinguishable from the other. But while there is no perceived
difference, the actual distinction between the two is of the greatest importance
--- for it is precisely upon this distinnction that the difference rests between
St. John’s account and non-Christian or heterodox interpretations. But let us
carry this analogy --- which is fairly common in the literature of mysticism ---
one step further. The mirror --- or the soul as the Divine speculum ---
is essentially incapable of reflecting the totality of the imaged, and
while this holds true of a material mirror reflecting finite matter, it is truer
still of the finite soul reflecting the infinite God. The frame, if you will, of
the image can only to a finite extent circumscribe the infinite aspects of God.
This does not make the correspondence in which the reflection consists less
authentic, only incomplete. And this is to say that, despite actual union, there
is nevertheless an ontological discontinuity inherent in that union --- a
discontinuity deriving from, and radicated in, the metaphysical inability of the
finite to exhaustively comprehend, and therefore to comprehensively reflect, the
totality of the infinite --- even as it participates within it. And this
is to say that the distinction which obtains between the two --- between the
finite soul, albeit participating in God, and the infinite God --- is already
ontologically explicit.
Let us now return to our
earlier question, our problem, really: if the two in fact are distinct, to what,
in our attempt to establish unique identities, can we appeal in distinguishing
between them if the one is effectively the undistorted image of the other? Well,
to begin with, I think it is clearly arguable that the unique constitutional
characteristics of the soul are no more abolished in union with God than the
constituent elements entering into the composition of a mirror are abolished in
the mirror’s being actualized before an object. Nothing in the way of the
unique nature of the soul or, for that matter, the mirror, is abrogated
as a result of its actualization before its proper object. The soul remains no
less a particular soul, and the mirror no less a particular mirror. In acquiring
an identity with God, nothing in the way of the unique constitutional identity
of the soul is lost --- quite to the contrary, it is enhanced in the
actualization of its created nature, a nature that was created to
be the image of God. It is, in other words, essentially a restatement of
the axiom that grace does not destroy, but perfects nature. And this is to say
that the unique identity of the soul, however modified subsequent to union, is
nevertheless preserved within it. It is not the case that the
nature of the soul is transformed --- still less abolished --- but
rather, that the identity of the soul is enhanced; in a manner of
speaking, transformed, in that apotheosized realization of its nature as image
of the Absolute. The complementary notions of reflection and participation are,
then, mutually implicated in the moment of union: the soul’s essentially
reflective ontology constitutes its inherent identity, an identity that
is subsequently enhanced and therefore acquired through participation in
God in the state of mystical union.
Participated and UnParticipated Being
Something more, however,
remains to said about the notion of participation which figures so
largely in St. John’s account. The concept itself is found to embody an implicit
ontological distinction that is not simply central, but crucial to the
metaphysics of mysticism. Participation is essentially a concept applied to two
very different types of being relatively considered: participated being,
or that which participates, and, by implication, unparticipated being, or
that-participated-in. And I think that we must be clear at the outset that while
the relationship between these two types of being, considered as such, is
necessarily mutual, it is not ontologically reciprocal, and what I mean is this:
participated being necessarily implies unparticipated being as that in which it
is said to participate, and unparticipated being, as a being that is
participated-in but itself unparticipating in any other being, necessarily
implies participated being --- given a participated being --- as that
which participates in itself. Perhaps a different tack will illustrate the point
better. Participated being cannot be said to participate in another
participated being. This would be tantamount to saying that it participates in
participation, which is absurd. It can only participate in being that itself is
unparticipated. But this is not to say that this relationship is ontologically
reciprocal. Unparticipated being in and of itself subsists independently of
participated being as that through which, that in virtue of which,
the being of the latter is derived through participation. Of itself it does not
presuppose as a condition to its existence, the existence of participated being.
Participated being, in other words, is derived being, while
unparticipated being, as totally underived, is totally self-subsistent.
Participated being, on the other hand, is not of itself independently
subsistent, that is to say, separable, from the being in which it participates
and through which its own being derives. And this is simply a rather complex way
of saying that the soul presupposes God to its own existence, and that God is
under no such ontological constraint relative to the soul.
Being, Becoming, and the Paradox of
Partcipation
Deeper implications of a profound ontological nature, however, soon emerge from this reflexive relation between participated-being and unparticipated-being, between the created soul and the Uncreated Absolute, for upon closer examination we find that the indispensable notion of participation itself cannot be abstracted from, because in some way it is fundamentally radicated in, the notion of becoming. Our focus up to this point has been upon Being and the aspectual negation of being through the via negativa. Notably absent has been a discussion of the role of becoming in the translation of being. Contemplative union (unio mystica) is, if nothing else, a becoming --- a becoming one with God, however attenuate the union. Through participation the mystic becomes one with the Absolute conceived as God. All this is well and good … until we are prompted to question two subtle, but deeply profound, ontological assumptions in earnest. What, we must now ask, precisely is the nature of this relationship which so rigorously obtains between the mutually implicative notions of participation in being, and becoming. Is not the inception of the first the cessation of the second? In attaining to being, albeit
participatorily, do we not eo ipso relinquish becoming? If we have arrived, has not all that was itinerant ceased? In short, is becoming abolished in being?
If this is so, however,it is fraught with perilous implications, not the least of which is profoundly inimical to the doctrine of St. John who is quite clear that despite the soul’s union with God, its being is nevertheless distinguishable from the Being of God in the way that the most perfect reflection in a mirror is ontologically distinct from that which is reflected in it. In other words, were the soul to transcend becoming and attain to unqualified being, it would be indistinguishable from God … it would be God. It would also be contra fide. How, then, do we respond to this enigma? How do we reconcile becoming with being without conflating the two in an ecstatic subreption? St. John regrettably, does not provide us with this answer … but his metaphysical infrastructure, I suggest, does. Let us look more carefully, then, into the notion of becoming in its relation to participatory being in God. Vital issues are at stake here, issues of such metaphysical proportion that our answer will either repudiate or substantiate the metaphysical doctrine of St. John.
To wit: is becoming an inflection of being, other than an inflection of being, or is it coterminous with being? Unless we can cogently respond to this question, the metaphysics of participation itself --- a notion central to understanding the phenomenon of ecstatic union --- is deeply compromised, and what we have arrived at is merely a metaphysical synthesis on purely speculative ontological grounds. Fortunately, the general metaphysical schema to which St. John adverts elsewhere in passim provides us with an answer I deem to be at least implicit within the text and standing simply in need of further articulation. We must, then, speculate further upon the notion of becoming
within the general context St. John has provided --- becoming verging on being. The bourne at the edge of the Dark Night.
The most summary purview of the Western Mystical Tradition reveals, at least implicitly and with few exceptions, that for the mystic becoming is the created articulation of the uncreated eternal. There is no terminus to becoming vis-à-vis the Absolute, the Infinite, the Eternal, and in this sense it is perpetually parallel to it and only in virtue of it. Even while we may speculate that at any given point of becoming, the soul in conspectu aeternitatis subsumes as present all the permutations of its being, in all that has been, and to this extent incorporates being even in the indesinence of becoming; that is to say, if we presume that the soul incorporates as present all that has been up to any given point in the continuum of becoming, we still have not arrived at the soul as being --- only as a being-such-that-is-perpetually-a-becoming-of. From this perspective, the soul is indeed the imago Dei inasmuch as it embraces as eternally present all that it has been … up to this point in its becoming; however, what lies before it is not yet present, nor can the soul incorporate what it is not yet, into what it has been, into what it is has enacted, up to this point of its becoming. The soul may in fact be understood to exist in a quasi-eternal present --- but it is a present that has not yet, and never will, culminate in a terminus of its becoming such that it is a being whose being has been totally and completely enacted and can become no more than it is. But to attain to nothing more, to culminate in nothing more, to become no more than what the soul is, is to understand the soul not simply as having attained to being, but having become distinguishable from it. It would be a being whose essence has culminated in being. But only God’s Being is His essence, and only God’s Essence is His Being.
Rather than having understood the soul as having spuriously assumed unqualified being, we see the soul as the speculum of this Esse Ipsum, this Being Itself, as the finite image of what is absolute --- understanding at the same time that the Infinite and Absolute as imaged eternally exceed the boundaries of the finite image. However clear and authentic
the image, it is only an image in part, an incomplete instantiation --- not only of the Absolute, but of its very own being which is perpetually becoming, and is not yet what it will be, and when it is what it will be, it will still not yet be what it will be, for it remains to be more … to become more than it is, to perpetually verge on the Infinite and the Absolute … but never embrace it in its totality. Since human nature can never attain to the ontological status of Being Itself inasmuch as it can never assume the divine nature (even while participating in it), the perpetuity of its becoming-that-always-verges-on-being remains an indefeasible aspect of its created nature (or its nature qua created) --- and therefore remains unchanged --- even in eternity. What is more, that is the splendor and the happiness, the felicity enjoyed by the soul in what we understand to be the beatific vision. In a word, Becoming is inexhaustible --- because Being Itself is inexhaustible in God; becoming, as such, is a tangent to, because it is enacted in, eternity.
The souls’s participatory being in God does not, then, abolish its becoming. The ramifications of this understanding are many, not the least of which is a clarification of the state of the soul before the beatific vision. It is no more static than the vision it beholds; even as God is understood as a Being whose essence coincides with his activity, or alternately, as a Being whose activity coincides with his essence (as we had stated earlier), just so the state of the soul in conspectu Dei is dynamic, perpetually becoming in perpetually verging on inexhaustible being; perpetually reflecting, participating in, the consummate being of God which is quintessentially a perpetual enactment.
Identity: Abrogation or
Heteronymy?
This further underscores
the fact that the relationship of identity which obtains between God and the
soul is not one in which all explicit distinction is sublated in the dialectic
of participation: a residual distinction nevertheless clearly remains which is
fundamentally an ontological distinction. It is, in fact, a distinction between
Being-Absolute, and being-contingent-upon-the-Absolute. And this
is precisely the distinction between the Imaged and the image, the latter being
understood as heteronymously deriving its being from the former. This
distinction, however, does not diminish the fact that the inherent identity of
the soul as the imago Dei is, subsequent to union, radically enhanced to
such a degree that what can only be called a transformation occurs within it in
which the soul explicitly acquires through participation what it only latently
possessed through nature. It is, in fact, very much along the lines of what the
Apostle St. John wrote concerning the identity of the soul before the beatific
vision of God:
“Beloved, we are God’s children now; it
does not yet appear what we shall be, but we know that when he appears we shall
be like him, for we shall see him as he is.” 7
In other words, as a
consequence of seeing God, the soul shall be rendered like unto him. And this is
the metaphysics of participation.
As is often the case in a
critical analysis of any aspect of St. John’s account, just when we think that
we have succeeded in putting a particular issue to rest, another facet of that
same issue emerges later on in another and entirely different context, and this
is particularly true of St. John’s treatment of the notion of sensibility which
recurs in the opening Book of the Dark Night of the Soul. In a larger
sense, this is due, I think, once again to the kind of treatise he writes, the
protocols and limitations of which are less clearly defined than had he taken to
his purpose the type of examination we have presumed to undertake. And yet we
ourselves are constrained to follow the itinerary of this development in his
account if our commentary hopes to achieve the coherence toward which we have
endeavored from the outset. We had stated earlier that St. John had ascribed the
gradual failure of sensibility, which he describes as “... this blessed night of
sense...”,8 to the inexorable transition from the sensuous to the
spiritual, a transition in which the soul cooperates but which is, withal and
principally, effected by God:
“... the cause of this aridity [that
accompanies the inception of this dark night] is that God transfers to the
spirit the good things and the strength of the senses ... [ but ] the sensual
part of man has no capacity for that which is pure spirit, and thus, when it is
the spirit that receives the pleasure, the flesh is left without savor ... but
the spirit, which all the time is being fed, goes forward in strength ...
[although] it is not immediately conscious of spiritual sweetness and delight
... 9
Here, as we can see, we
are once again thrown back on the problem of sensibility. It can hardly be
disputed that the terms “pleasure”, “sweetness”, and “delight” which occur in
the above excerpt are explicitly sensuous terms, and it appears to be an
unpardonable solecism on the part of St. John to have adopted terminology
fraught with the very contradictions they appear to engender. But what
can be disputed, however, is the interpretation, the meaning which we
assign to these terms in light of the gradually unfolding logic of mysticism. In
effect, to accept these terms at face value, and not as analogical equivalents,
is to accuse St. John of violating the very principles from which he argues, a
position very difficult to maintain given the type of close reasoning that we
have seen and have come to expect throughout his works. So what in fact
does St. John mean by admitting of the possibility of what appear to be
sensuous experiences in the state of sensuous negation?
Perhaps this question can
be answered by way of analogy and in terms that lend themselves less readily to
a sensuous interpretation of the type St. John appears to imply. Clearly there
are different kinds of pleasures subsequent to different kinds of
activities. The delight, for example, which a mathematician might experience in
resolving a complicated differential equation is clearly of another kind to that
experienced by a child savoring sweets. The one pleasure derives from the
abstract contemplation of an intellectual good, the other from the sensory
experience of a perceived physical good. These pleasures are clearly of a
different kind; that is to say, the difference is not one susceptible to being
quantified --- it is not the case that the mathematician derives greater
pleasure than the child, but a different type of pleasure altogether. What is
more --- and apropos of the issue at hand --- in not having been initiated into
those goods which we have characterized as intellectual, the child is unable to
recognize the good otherwise implicit within certain other types of activity. In
effect, his inability to participate within activities to which certain goods
are intrinsic that are non-sensuous in nature, precludes the possibility of his
deriving pleasure from any good not sensuously derived, which alone is the good
to which he has been accustomed and to which alone he remains receptive. He is,
in a manner of speaking, conditioned to the good (for the moment, the
pleasurable) as deriving from the senses, and in order for him to experience the
good as intellectual, the physical senses must be held in abeyance as the sole
criterion of the good or the pleasurable. And this is very much like saying that
the experience of this latter type of good requires a kind of negation of the
sensuous. In fact, this understanding of the problem very closely corresponds to
St. John’s subsequent account of this transitional phase:
“If [ the soul in this state of transition
] is not conscious of spiritual sweetness and delight, but only of aridity, or
lack of sweetness, the reason for this is the strangeness of the exchange, for
its palate has been accustomed to those other sensual pleasures upon which its
eyes are still fixed. Since the spiritual palate is not made ready or purged
from such subtle pleasure, until it finds itself becoming prepared for it by
means of this arid and dark night, it cannot experience spiritual pleasure and
good, but only aridity and lack of sweetness.” 10
Sensibility vis-a-vis Experience: The
Problematic
More importantly, what
may be said of these pleasures and goods that the soul is capable of
experiencing and which St. John briefly describes above? In what, precisely, do
these pleasures consist, and why are they experienced? In short, what are
they? St. John is very clear in the passage above that such pleasures may be
legitimately anticipated subsequent to, though not necessarily as a consequence
of, a clearly defined preparatory process --- and what is particularly
noteworthy is that the requisite preparation consists, paradoxically, in
sensuous negation. In other words, the pleasures that the mystic may anticipate
are not merely inaccessible, but essentially unavailable until the manifold of
sensibility has been effectively abolished. And unless we are able to make a
distinction between sensibility and experience, the notion of pleasure
abstracted from sensibility will be a very odd notion indeed. After all,
sensibility --- or the ability to be sensibly affected --- is, by and large, not
simply a component, but a presupposition, of experience. It goes without saying
that the notion of sensation presupposes the notion of sensibility. And the
notion of sensation, in turn, while not strictly tautological with, is more
often than not defined in terms of, experience; to such an extent, in fact, that
we should find it very difficult to understand an individual, for example, who
claims to have had the sensation of “hot” apart from any
experience of it. Our question then is, while we cannot understand the
notion of sensibility apart from experience, can we understand the notion of
experience apart from the notion of sensibility? This, however, is not to say,
as I suggested a moment ago, that the two notions are therefore effectively
tautologous, or interchangeable. We can be said to experience the sensation of
heat, but we cannot be said to have a sensation of the experience of heat. We do
not sense experiences. We experience the senses, or more accurately, reports of
phenomena delivered by the senses.
There is, then, a very
clear distinction to be made between sensibility and experience. Moreover,
despite the relationship between sensibility and experience that is, by and
large, perceived as being mutual, even this mutuality itself can only be
predicated of certain kinds of experience that are explicitly sensuous in
nature to begin with. What is more, there are many other types of
experiences to which nothing physically sensible corresponds. For
example, our experience of delight in being given, say, a relic --- is a type of
experience that is independent of the tactile, sensible phenomena associated
with the relic. It may be said to derive from the relic, but the experience
itself is not one of the relic; rather, it is one that arises from our
possession of the relic in a sense that is not strictly tactile. That is to say,
our experience of the delight of possession is different from our
experience of the tactile quality of the relic. Nor is the experience of
the one, simply because it is tactile, more real or specific than the experience
of the other. And the upshot of our entire argument is simply this: the apparent
contradiction engendered by St. John’s use of the terms delight, sweetness, and
pleasure --- terms typically understood in a context of sensibility ---
subsequent to the soul’s induction into sensuous negation, is now
seen to be no contradiction at all. But more importantly it means that the
notion of experience extricated from a rigorous association with sensibility is
in fact a coherent notion relative to the purely spiritual intuition of God
subsequent to the abolishing of sensibility.
But let us say something
more of the nature of these experiences themselves. It might be argued that
these experiences, in and of themselves, appear to be extrinsic to that direct
experience of God in which union consists; indeed, that such experiences are
fundamentally subjective in nature and as such are merely accidental in a causal
way to God’s presence. That, in fact, as purely subjective experiences they do
not essentially pertain to that direct experience of union which is the
participatory assimilation of the soul into God in which nothing explicitly
other to God remains. In light of all this, are we really prepared to argue that
these experiences, experiences that are apparently radicated in the subjectivity
of the soul, constitute an essential feature of the mystical experience,
and not, after all, one merely accidental to it? For unless we can come to terms
with this objection, it becomes extremely unclear why St. John would advert to
these experiences at all --- and in so doing occasion this apparent
contradiction.
When we consider this
objection closely, however, we find that it fails either to discern or to
adequately explore two indispensable factors entering into any coherent
understanding of the mystical experience: the notion of participation and the
nature of God. It is indeed arguable, in fact I shall proceed to argue as much,
that these experiences are, in the logic of mysticism, not merely
accidental to God’s presence, as we might have mistakenly supposed, but
rather are logically consequent to a fully articulated understanding of
participation --- in which the soul’s experiences are in fact the
experiences of God. Moreover, they are fully experiences of God in a twofold
sense: they are the experience of God himself --- which is at one and
the same time a participation in God’s experience of Himself. Now, we
hasten to add that this is not to deny the subjectivity of such
experiences, for such a denial is clearly impossible --- there is no such thing
as an “objective” experience, of an experience not related to a subject. But it
is a shared subjectivity implicit within, and deriving from, the soul’s
mystical and participative union with God in which the experience of joy,
sweetness, etc., is that felicity which God experiences within himself,
and which --- as essential to the nature of God --- is that in which the soul is
understood to be participating through its union with him. The soul, in other
words, experiences the felicity of God by virtue of its participating in
God --- and because it is participatory, this experience is also
subjective.
While such an
understanding goes a long way in clarifying this particular, if only apparent
inconsistency in St. John’s doctrine, it hardly serves to exhaust our
understanding of this transitional phase to which St. John devotes fully one
half of the Dark Night of the Soul. It is extremely important to
understand that, as phase of transition in an otherwise dynamic
development, it is bound to suffer from that characteristic indeterminacy that
is always latent in any notion of becoming. Anything on the verge of
becoming is neither totally what is was, nor what it shall be. And it is
precisely this intermediate penumbra, vacillating between the superficies of
sense and spirit in which the soul is at once both and neither, which poses
perhaps the single greatest challenge to an understanding of mysticism. Not
infrequently, problems encountered in an approach from one of the two
perspectives result from suppressed theses answerable only in terms of their
alternatives, much as we had found to be the case with the apparently
inconsistent notion of the pleasurable relative to union. These apparent
inconsistencies --- and there are many --- demand a place in our account. Some
of them, like beads of mercury, may at first elude our grasp until in
frustration we hammer them with analysis against the anvil of the text and find,
after sorting out the pieces, that when brought together once again the whole is
coherent in a way we had not first fully understood. And very much like the bead
of mercury, in the end we shall find that reason, after all, may merely touch
upon, but never enter into that divine circle penetrable only through
faith.
The Imperative of Passivity
St. John, we will
remember, has been unmistakably clear that this transition from the sensuous to
the spiritual presupposes; indeed, requires, a disposition of total passivity on
the part of the soul. In fact, that cooperation with the Divine initiative which
throughout has characterized the soul’s movement toward union is, from the very
beginning, directed precisely toward attaining this state of passivity that is
both consequent to, and is now seen to have been the principal goal of, the
via negativa in each of its multifaceted aspects. And what this
essentially means is that all the contradiction and contrariety which has been
an impediment to the soul in its quest for union is, in one form or another,
ultimately seen to be occasioned by activity on the part of the soul,
activity that effectively precludes the activity of God within
it:
“... the beginning of contemplation ... is
secret and hidden from the very person that experiences it; ...[ and ] the souls
to whom this comes to pass [ must be ] troubled not about performing any kind of
action, whether inward or outward ... It does its work when the soul is most at
ease and freest from care ... For in such a way does God bring the soul into
this state, and by so different a path does He lead it that, if it desires to
work with its faculties, it hinders the work which God is doing in it ...”
11
But let us at once clear
up what is really a non-issue before it culminates in absurdity, and allow St.
John the author a certain latitude that would permit the type of inexactitude
that we should find inexcusable in St. John the theologian. He clearly is both,
and for the most part integrates the two admirably. An exegesis, however, of the
type we have undertaken must be as flexible as the text itself and where it must
be unsparing in the criticism of concepts, it must equally submit to the
occasional ambiguity in literary form. And all this, of course, is apropos of
the opening lines in the passage quoted above. In effect, St. John appears to be
saying that we can have experiences of which we are unaware --- and since every
experience presumes cognition of some sort, this strikes us as patently
absurd. And so understood it is. But to succumb to this overly rigorous
interpretation is really a failure to come to terms with the limitations of the
text which had already been set out beforehand. Yes, we can press the point and
accuse St. John of carelessness, but I really think it is unnecessarily
punitive, and in the end, quite trivial. St. John simply means that the
beginning of contemplation occurs in the soul “secretly”, as he would say, or in
such a way that the soul is unaware of what God is effecting within it; a point
we had addressed earlier in another context. This small matter having been
clarified, we can now pass on to what is actually significant in the
text.
While it is true that the
soul cooperates with God in order to arrive at the passive state of
negativity, it is equally and paradoxically true that its achieving this state
is not the result of the efforts of its own will --- except negatively
considered. Were it in fact the case that the soul attained this passive state
by its own efforts, then in effect the soul would be subject to no limitations
that had not been voluntarily appropriated in the first place, and the
subsequent exercise of its will would alone determine the extent to which these
limitations were in fact actual constraints. Rather simply put, limitations not
independent of volition are really no constraining limitations at all. And it is
clearly St. John’s argument that it is ultimately God who is leading the
soul into these various nights, the conditions of which, once entered into, are
no longer subject to the soul’s volition. And this is further to say that the
notion of volition apparently extends no further than the soul’s implicit
accession to be subject to new limitations, an assent --- already presumed in
the soul’s ascetical activity described in the Ascent of Mount Carmel ---
to limitations imposed no longer by nature, but by spirit.
Let us sort this out a
bit more. In having left the limitations --- generally construed in terms of
physical laws --- imposed on the will by the order of nature (our will, for
example, is constrained by laws which prevent us from passing through walls,
should we will to do so), the soul has, upon the inauguration of the night of
the spirit, simultaneously subjected itself to other limitations
constraining the will in the order of the spirit. We have seen, by way of
illustration, that the will is unable to engage discursive reason --- it is
effectively constrained from doing so by the principles of the via
negativa through which alone the soul gained access to the spiritual order
in the first place. It is not the case, then, that limitation is abolished. In
one form or another it is metaphysically inherent in the very ontological
structure of the soul. But while it is not abolished, the parameters defining
the concept of limitation are translated, redefined, to accord with a different
metaphysical environment into which the concept itself has been brought. It is a
limitation of mind or spirit analogous to the former physical limitations
experienced in the order of nature. This seems to be clearly maintained by St.
John when he makes such statements as the following:
“The soul can no longer meditate or
reflect in the imaginative sphere of sense ...12... its inability to reflect with
the faculties grows ever greater ... and brings the ... and brings the workings
of the sense to an end …”
13
But we must be careful,
on the other hand, not to construe this development as depriving the will of its
freedom. In every event, in every movement, the soul remains free by an act of
will to spurn the divine embrace and to disengage itself from these new
constraints simply by rejecting the via negativa --- and all the
limitations subsequent to it --- by the same formal act of the will through
which it first submitted to them. It is not that freedom of the will has been
relinquished, but rather, that freedom has been redefined in light of newly
acquired limitations.
Consent, Constraint, and the Paradox of
Freedom
But what precisely are
these limitations to which the soul has consented, and by what is it
constrained? St. John, regrettably, is not clear on this point, but then again,
neither should we expect him to be. It is undoubtedly and unavoidably a
shortcoming in any type of exegesis that attempts to extrapolate concepts only
latent in a text, that the systematic schema toward which it strives as an end,
and around which the coherence of its own account evolves, tends to unfairly
indict its source as defaulting in a systematic obligation that was never its
intended purpose to begin with. In very deed, were this the case our own present
study would be altogether superfluous. While it is true that St. John does not
elucidate on the nature of these limitations, they nevertheless compel our
interest as vital components to our understanding the complexity of the
transition in which they occur
and the effect on the
will as a consequence of it. These limitations, let us say, first of all appear
to be relative to the order of nature. From the entire line of argument that St.
John has pursued up to this point we may say that these limitations are subsumed
under a more comprehensive relation of opposition existing between spirit and
nature which we had earlier discussed at length. These limitations, in fact, are
readily translated into functions of opposition in which the corresponding and
diametrical attributes of each order (finite/ infinite, temporal/eternal, etc.)
delimit the possible functions of the soul within each respective order.
That is to say, the limitations which the soul experiences in either sphere
function in accordance with the broader ontological demands of each order. Once
introduced into the spiritual order --- the demands of which, it will be
remembered, required the negation of nature --- the soul has necessarily
been inducted into that otherness of spirit to nature --- an otherness to which
the order of nature, apart from divine intervention, effectively forms the
limitation to the order of spirit. As such, a phenomenal inversion occurs
relative to the will; for in the order of nature the soul was constrained by
inherent limitations in the exercise of its will over the order of spirit ---
limitations clearly defined by, and coterminous with, supernatural realities
which were typically unavailable and therefore inaccessible to the exercise of
the will. In other words, the spiritual, broadly understood, did not constitute
the immediate context in which the will was characteristically exercised; rather
the will was seen to have been limited, confined, in its activity to the natural
order --- and as such to have shared in that otherness of nature to
spirit.
This situation, however,
is inverted through sensuous negation, or the negation of nature. First
of all, we have seen that the spiritual order is achieved explicitly, solely,
through the negation of nature. This in itself would suffice to explain new
limitations on the will. But what is more, as other to nature through its
subsumption under spirit, the will no longer functions in that context which
would admit of its exercise over nature. And what this means is that nature
forms the will’s absolute limitation once the will is subsumed under spirit.
This, however, is not to say that the will shall be exercised, merely
that such exercise must be subject to implied limitations; limitations which, in
this period of transition, the soul experiences relative to meditations,
reasoning, and the like. And yet ultimately, as we shall see, the exercise of
the will subsequent to negation is understood in terms of the will’s
identification with the will of God, and the limitations which it presently
experiences relative to nature are in the end overcome, St. John argues, when
the soul becomes God-by-participation. 14
Transcendence through Negativity
As we had seen in other
and earlier contexts, the notion of the bidimensionality of man figures largely
throughout the works of St. John. But we must be extremely clear from the outset
that this notion in no way implies a dualism of the type we find, for example,
in the Zend-Avesta of Zoroaster or in the eclectic and largely Gnostic doctrines
of Manichaeism. It is, I think, necessary to emphasize this point simply because
St. John’s often graphic illustrations, not so much of the incommensurability,
but of the contrariety that exists between God and nature, and nature and
spirit, at least superficially lend themselves to this sort of misunderstanding.
But to misunderstand St. John in this regard is to misunderstand him completely.
It is to fail to grasp an entire tradition that coherently spans from early
patristic thought to late Scholastic reasoning; a tradition out of which his own
philosophy emerges and to which St. John is intensely faithful. The polarity we
find alternately between God and nature, and nature and spirit is, in the
philosophy of St. John, a metaphysical distinction rooted in ontology,
not a dualistic antithesis radicated in cosmology. It is not that matter, the
body, finitude, space and time are evil. Quite to the contrary, it is a basic
tenet of Christian theology that God --- ex nihilo --- created matter,
and the phenomenal framework in which it exists, as good. We do indeed discern
metaphysical incommensurability, perceive ontological contrariety, but within
the theological tradition to which St. John vigorously ascribes neither is
extrapolated to signify an inherent distinction interpretable in terms of a
perceived antagonism between the intrinsically good and the irremediably evil.
This is entirely outside the perspective from which St. John writes, for in the
end, the distinction to be made is fundamentally one not between good and evil,
but between Being-Absolute, and every other kind of being, which is
being-contingent-upon-the-Absolute.
Since the bidimensional
nature of man which figures so largely in the thought of St. John is central to
the development of our epistemological account, let us look at it a little more
closely in the present context. It should be reasonably clear to us by now that
the transitional phase that we are currently examining constitutes both a
negating and a positing --- in fact, it is a negating of the
sensuous which is simultaneously a positing of the spiritual; or,
conversely, a positing of the spiritual which is a negating of the sensuous. In
other words, to transcend the senses is eo ipso to enter spirit as the
other of sense, an implied other, latent in that very bidimensional
conception of man around which the entire phenomenology of Western mysticism is
essentially constructed. But what is important for us to note here is that such
a transition relative to a bidimensional nature effectively results in a
unilateral negation --- a negation of only one of the two dimensions in
which the being of man is simultaneously enacted.15 And while the positing of the one is the negating of the
other, it is, for this reason, not the case that the personality of the soul in
either event is extinguished in the transition; rather, it is very clearly
understood to be preserved within it. Were this transition, on the other hand,
understood to entail a bilateral negation, the result, very obviously,
would be quite otherwise --- it would not be a transition at all, but
annihilation. And this is really another way of restating one of the obvious and
irreconcilable differences that exists between competing traditions of
mysticism: to the Christian mystic, the soul, or the personality, is preserved
through what is understood to be essentially a transition; it attains to
union with the Absolute, where other and conflicting interpretations see
this not so much as a transition, but as an existential terminus in which
the soul is effectively annihilated in its absorption into the Absolute.
What is of vital interest to us, however, is the fact that the dimension negated
subsequent to this transition is precisely the dimension inextricably bound up
with time, space, and matter --- such that, to pass into its other, is
consequently to pass into a dimension that is necessarily atemporal,
non-spatial, and immaterial. And it is precisely these categories which are
critically important, in fact absolutely indispensable, to the intelligibility
of the mystical experience. They form, as it were, the complementary keys to a
mystical epistemology.
Of themselves these
negative categories merely serve to underscore, to emphasize, those overwhelming
aspects of a perceived reality that cannot be comprehended under the positive
and limiting categories of space, time, and matter. But what is really of the
greatest interest to us is what follows from this negative positing relative to
the inherent possibilities of experience. As transcendent to time (atemporal),
such experiences are necessarily transcendent to reason
16 inasmuch as a
temporal element is implicit within, in being presupposed by, that passing from
one concept to another which cognitively characterizes the exercise of
discursive reason. Simply put, reason addresses concepts one or a few at a time
and moves sequentially, syllogistically through premises to conclusions, the
conclusions always being posterior to the premises --- all of which, of course,
presumes time. Exscind the notion of time from the notion of reason and reason
at once and necessarily ceases being discursive --- and cognition simultaneously
defaults to simple sensibility, or the sheer, intuitive, immediacy of
experience; experience from which reason can no longer syllogize nor upon
which reason may subsequently comment.
This, I suggest, holds
equally true of space. As transcendent to space (non-spatial), such experiences
are altogether transcendent to mediation, for mediation is implicitly a spatial
conception, inasmuch as it presumes space as the matrix within which the subject
is mediated to its experiences --- and this, of course, simultaneously and
equally implies the notion of otherness and externality. Subsequent to the
negation of space, then, any experience whatever will be necessarily divested of
otherness, of externality, of distance; which is another way of saying that the
experience will be immediate, as it were, perfectly subjectivized through having
transcended the medium of otherness in the form of space. And finally, though no
less significantly, as transcendent to space, such experiences are necessarily
transcendent to matter (immaterial) which itself presupposes space as that in
which alone matter is susceptible to configuration. Given this overwhelming
transcendence through negativity, all subsequent experience is, in a sense,
translated into self-experience since there is no longer an explicit other to
the self beyond the post-negative transition.
Epistemological Monism?
Thus the logic of St.
John’s mysticism inexorably moves toward a kind of epistemological monism
characterized by sheer immediacy and self-experience. But does this mean that
the negation of sense results in what must then be interpreted as mere
solipsism? It would seem, after all, that to pass beyond space, time, and matter
is to pass at once and altogether beyond the phenomenal frames of individuation,
and therefore beyond plurality into an inevitable monism. For St. John, however,
this is not the case, for just as we had found that the soul’s induction into
the spiritual order entailed a reorientation of the will given the new
limitations to which it is was then subject --- imitations radically dissimilar
from the former --- just so, now the previous frames of individuation --- space,
time, and matter --- are abolished in the inauguration of the spiritual order,
and new frames in turn are established which are radically and necessarily
different from those previously defined in terms of space, time, and matter ---
to which the soul can no longer appeal in having subsequently transcended
them.
Moreover, given what we
have called the mystical thesis --- that consciousness is unified in God
thorough the direct and intuitive participation in the divine existence --- this
individuation must occur in the context of a unity more comprehensive than the
individuation is distinct. In other words, the principle of individuation must
in fact be seen to be a function of a more comprehensive ontological unity; a
unity in ontology in which the notion of individuation is modalized into terms
of the Absolute and the contingent. And these, in turn, are precisely the
elements involved in the recurrent notion of participation. The participant qua
image (the image which becomes explicit in union) contingently derives his
ontological status from the participated-in as Absolute. His being as
participant, in other words, derives from the Absolute, and is identical --- qua
image --- with the Absolute --- but only contingently, and not absolutely or
essentially. And this is why, in participation, we find that experience
metamorphoses into an immediacy of identity conceived in terms of the immediacy
of self-experience. Ultimately, the one who experiences, and the
experienced are one, for the experience itself explicitly becomes
self-experience through the notion of participation. It is fundamentally a
realization of the self in its primal essence as image of God --- and yet
not God, for a residual distinction nevertheless and ineluctably remains in
ontology. As image and participant, the soul is not other to God, no more so
than the reflection in a mirror is other than the reflected --- and yet an
implicit distinction persists and individuation as latent-only is nevertheless
retained. Much of this, as we shall see, is borne out by St. John in later
passages.
But turning once again to
the text itself, St. John argues that certain subjective experiences invariably
accompany the initial stages of this transition to the night of the
spirit:
“... contemplation is naught else than a
secret, peaceful, and loving infusion from God which ... enkindles the soul with
the spirit of love ... 17 This enkindling of love is not, as a rule,
felt at first ... nevertheless there soon begins to make itself felt, a certain
yearning toward God, and the more this increases, the more is the soul ...
enkindled in love toward God, without knowing or understanding how and whence
this love and affection come to it ...” 18
What are we to make of
this? How are these, and other such paradoxical statements, to be understood in
the context of mystical epistemology? If we look at them once more, but this
time in light of the metaphysics that we have examined so far, a good deal more
is suggested than would superficially appear. First of all, the absence of
certain cognitive elements in the experience that St. John adverts to above are
seen to both logically and necessarily follow from the soul’s prior submission
to the protocols of the via negativa, the demands of which, we must
remember, required a total suspension of the faculties, a suspension so
complete, in fact, that it resulted in a state of cognitive negativity.
Following closely upon this is a realization that the notion of knowing
or understanding any subsequent experience becomes not so much
superfluous as essentially irrelevant to the account; indeed, the elements
constituting any subsequent experience as such are no longer synthesized
through reason to be accommodated to understanding --- both of
which presume definition in the reports submitted to them; a definition (and
delimitation) no longer available consequent to the soul’s subjection to the
via negativa. And this is really an unnecessarily complex way of stating
that what St. John really endeavors to verge upon is a conception of the simple,
immediate, unarticulated experience in which alone the possibility of
ecstatic union consists. And this is further to say that, in essence, the
attempt to know, to understand, the experience is to subvert it.
It is to introduce the very elements of contradiction to which the via
negativa was vigorously applied in an explicit effort to expunge
them.
The Imperative of Experience ... and the
Post-Experential
But how, precisely, does
this contribute to our understanding of mystical epistemology? Profoundly, and
in two ways, for the consequences of the immediacy of experience are themselves
twofold. First of all, that characteristic hallmark of all mystical experience
--- ineffability --- derives in fact froom the irreducible immediacy of
experience itself which, however exhaustively described, however carefully
nuanced, remains not just primarily, but essentially, an incommunicable
experience. Comprehending within itself no mediate elements, the sheer
immediacy of experience can no sooner be rendered intelligible, than the sheer
intelligibility of pure mathematics can be rendered experiential. Much as we are
unable to existentially instantiate the purely rational geometric “point” which
merely has position but no extension because it is a purely rational
concept --- and as such cannot be instantiated however infinitesimal the
material definition; just so the irreducible nature of experience does not,
indeed cannot, lend itself to intelligibility given the most exhaustively
nuanced description. We now see that as a consequence of having relinquished
reason --- and therefore intelligibility --- in order to be susceptible
to the mystical experience, such experience is, by this very fact, forever
disqualified from the descriptive utterances of reason. It is, in a real sense,
sheer experience at the cost of reason as mediate, such that the
pronouncements of reason will not, cannot, descriptively suffice.
Intelligibility, then, is summarily abolished, both by the demands of the via
negativa in suspending reason, and in the more rigorous demand for immediacy
by experience itself.
But this is not all. The
second consequence to follow from this imperative of experience concerns the
contingency of such experiences. These “fleeting touches of union” as St.
John often calls them are occasioned solely by God and depend totally upon the
divine will. The mystic of himself cannot produce or reproduce these experiences
that are independently and actively conveyed to it by the agency of God that
itself is perfectly free and unconstrained by any necessity not self-legislated.
In other words, the extraordinary nature of this experience derives from the
fact that it is not experience abstractly conceived as pure immediacy as such, a
state of mere immediacy to which the soul is necessarily related as to
the condition of the most minimal experience --- but the experience of
God who is not necessarily related to the soul as a condition to
its experience --- and this is to say that the experience is entirely
contingent --- contingent upon the will of God --- who, moreover, within himself
comprehends perfect freedom such that no constraint conceived as external to God
necessitates this extraordinary experience independent of the
self-legislating will of God. So understood, such experiences are not
properly caused, but willed, and as such are not characterized by
necessity, but by contingency.
These pure, non-cognitive
experiences appear to mark the inception of the Night of the Spirit,
which St. John calls:
“... this night from all created things ...
when the soul journeys to eternal things …” 19
The realm of mediation
--- sensible and intelligible --- graduaally recedes until the imperative of
pure experience paradoxically asserts itself as the only residual
medium between the soul and God, between ordinary cognition and mitigated
epistemological monism. And this is a rather surprising result, for the
sheer immediacy of experience would seem, by that very fact, to preclude any
notion of mediation whatever. Indeed, we had consistently argued all along to
experience as in itself irreducible. And so it is --- but it is an irreducible
medium between that which experiences and the experienced. For upon
closely examining the concept we find that it is neither the one, nor the other,
but presupposes each as a product of both in mediating the relation of the one
to the other. As the last vestige of mediation prior to union, it is, in fact,
that proximate relation to God prior to participation which St. John
addresses in the Ascent of Mount Carmel relative to the theological
virtues. 20 It is clear, for example, that the non-cognitive nature of
pure experience is very much consonant with that notion of faith which St. John
construes as a type of epistemological negation, 21 and both, we have seen, are in turn abolished in the
dialectic of participation. We must not for this reason, however, confuse the
two: faith is an attitude toward God given the perceived absence of God
--- experience is the realization> of God. And yet we have equally seen
that faith is presupposed by the experience as the condition of the very
possibility of the mystical experience. There is, then, a certain reciprocity
between faith and experience, inasmuch as there is no approaching God, no hope
of attaining to this transformative union, in the absence of
faith.
Still, at this point in
the movement toward mystical union, the soul’s relation to God remains, withal,
one of proximity --- not participation. A proximity in which a distinction is
yet implied and evident between the things rendered proximate. And yet the
distinction itself, we find, is often attenuate, for the relation that obtains
between the two elements entering into experience is often conflated into an
apparent identity in which, for example, the distinction between the experience
of cold and being cold, or the experience of heat and being hot, is not at all
that clear or critical. Now this would equally account for those experiences of
sweetness and joy spoken of earlier which, though not properly deriving from
participation in any explicit or noetic sense, nevertheless exemplify the
typical obscurity of the distinction existing between certain penumbral types of
experience. In other words, the nature of experience is such that it is not
always possible to draw a hard and fast distinction between that which
experiences and that which is experienced --- although in fact such a
distinction unmistakably exists --- especially in this state of proximity which
St. John describes, and which must not be confused with
participation.
A distinction, then, is
always implied in experience; a distinction, as we saw earlier, capable of being
rendered in terms of the subject/object bifurcation. So as yet, no kind of
monism is seen to result from this transition to the night of spirit: any
experience of God so understood is still defined by an explicitly apprehended
distinction between the soul and God, the experiencer and the experienced. But
the question nevertheless remains to be asked: must the notion of
experience always and necessarily apply to the soul’s relation to
God? And our answer --- St. John’s answer --- must unequivocally be, no. For
while our examination of the notion of experience revealed that, at least
implicitly, it presupposes the otherness of God to the soul, we had on
the other hand equally seen that the soul as the image of God demonstrates an
essential sameness deriving from a fundamentally shared ontology. Our
confusion, I think, results from an incomplete analysis of the soul’s
ontological relation to God in the dynamic movement of the soul to the state of
apotheosis in union: the distinction between the soul and God (as other) in the
notion of proximity relative to experience, is an external
ontological distinction, a distinction between subject and object that is, we
had found, inherent in the notion of experience itself. But the distinction
between the soul and God (as same) in the notion of participation relative to
union is an internal ontological distinction implicit in the notion
of the union of Absolute with contingent being as we have already seen, and as
such becomes, not an absolute, but a relative distinction.
Proximity versus Participation: an Epistemological
Vestibule
Proximity and
Participation are therefore two distinct moments in the movement to
mystical union, to which two quite different modes of relation to God apply.
This distinction, I think, becomes somewhat clearer when addressed in a more
focused context dealing with the notion of the self --- the notion of identity
--- relative to God as it occurs within these two moments. In the experience of
God as necessarily other in proximity, the self is experienced as
radically distinct from God. It is essentially a relation between God and the
soul mediated by experience in which the soul defines its identity qua
subject in opposition to God qua object --- hence the identity of the
self is derived apart from God; in fact, we may say that it is derived
essentially in opposition to God. But this distinction immediately breaks down
in the second moment when experience is transformed into participation
wherein no radical distinction is discernible, apprehensible, between the soul
as participant, as image, as being-contingent, and God as the Participated-in,
the Imaged, the Being-Absolute. As a consequence, the very concept of
experience that we invoke, especially relative to the notion of
apperception, becomes at once and necessarily analogical. The experience of the
self is the experience of God --- it is the experience of the self as
image-of-the-Absolute, and therefore of the Absolute. And the experience
of God is the experience of the self --- the experience of that in which
the self fundamentally consists qua image. Participation, then, generates a
relation of divine reflexivity: it is, in fact, the reflection of God into God
--- either as the Absolute reflected intto the contingent, or as the contingent
reflecting the Absolute. In other words, there is only God and God’s image ---
and it is self-reflexive from either perspective.
Several very important
consequences are seen to follow from this metaphysics. First of all, it is clear
in light of previous arguments that the dogmatic opposition of erstwhile
diametric categories --- finite versus infinite, etc. --- essentially breaks
down in mystical union, for the realization of God in the self is at once a
realization of the infinite-in-the-finite, and conversely the realization
of the self in God is in fact a realization of the
finite-in-the-infinite. 22 The two categories are not, after all, mutually exclusive
in any absolute sense. The infinite as the imaged is found to reside in
the finite soul as the ontological condition of the soul’s being (image). It is,
in fact, the ontological presupposition of contingent being. The
unfolding of this absolutely unique relationship reveals it to be characterized
not by opposition --- still less is it defined by a dialectic arising out of
opposition --- but it is one which is seen to demonstrate essential
relation. The perceived opposition (not, we hasten to add, the actual
ontological distinction) between the finite and the infinite breaks down, is
abolished in an ontological analysis that demonstrates God’s essential relation
to the soul as its presupposition in being, as the infinite-in-the-finite. But
what is more, this dogmatic opposition is not only abolished --- revealing not
opposition, but essential relation --- but transcended by the identity of the
finite soul with the infinite God in the moment of participation. And this is
the divine paradox at the heart of the metaphysics of mysticism. Finitude
participates in infinitude. In fact, it is seen to be merely quasi-finite, for
it is no longer dogmatically finite in opposition to the infinite.
However, it nevertheless only remains infinite by participation,
and that is to say, it is heteronymously infinite --- not in itself autonomously
infinite. It is, in a word, contingently infinite, and as such
incorporates a residual distinction within itself; a distinction deriving from
what is essentially a heteronymous identity of the finite with the
infinite.
Our argument, so far,
appears to consistently follow from principles to which St. John often tacitly
adverts without a good deal of elaboration --- but inevitably we must come to
honest terms with the text. This is not to imply disingenuity. The broad
extrapolation often required of a commentary of this sort is, I think, always at
least susceptible to forfeiting something of the authentic thought embodied in
the text itself in pursuit of a sometimes elusive coherence that was never
present to begin with. In an attempt to constrain this speculative impulse,
especially at this critical junction in our account, we must now candidly ask,
is it in fact the case that St. John himself explicitly equates the
experience of the self in mystical union with the experience of
God? It is extremely important to be clear upon this point, for no other
doctrine in the mystical tradition has been historically more susceptible to
confusion and more liable to error than the notion of personal identity as it
obtains between the soul and God subsequent to mystical union. So does St. John
indeed make the equation toward which we argue? Unquestionably. Consider the
following:
“... from this arid night [of the senses]
there first of all comes self-knowledge, whence as from a foundation rises this
other knowledge of God. For this cause, St. Augustine said to God
23: ‘let me know myself, Lord, and I shall
know thee ...’ ” 24
Now, this knowledge of
God that derives from and proceeds through introspective
self-knowledge, St. John effectively argues, would be impossible were
there not, first, some essential ontological connection between the soul and
God. Second, an abrogation of the perceived dogmatic opposition between the
categories involved. Third, the abolishing of mediation. Fourth, and closely
connected with the first, a coherent notion of participation to overcome the
subject/object bifurcation if this knowledge is in fact to be veridical. And
fifth and last, a relation of reflexivity. Unless these criteria are met, the
mystical doctrine that knowledge of God is in fact available through
self-knowledge is at best an untenable, and at worst, a meaningless statement.
Having uniquely established this notion central to, but not always coherent
within, the Western mystical tradition at large, St. John effectively concludes
his treatment of the night of the senses --- the transition is now complete, and
the way is prepared for the Night of the
Spirit.
1
DNS
1.8.3
2 DNS
1.8.3
3 This is
essentially a variation of the doctrine of exemplary causation used earlier by
the Scholastics.
4 cf. Ex. 3.14,
6.3; Ps. 90.2; Is. 43.13; Jn. 8.58; Rev. 1.4+8, 11.7 Also cf. ST1 Ques.13
art.11, Ques. 3 art.2+8; De Ente. c.4; Comm. Sent. 2 d.3 ques. 1
art. 1; De Verit. 9.21 a.2,c.
5 Aquinas puts
it in a slightly different way: “The Divine nature or essence is itself its own
act of being, but the nature or essence of any created thing is not its own act
of being but participates in being from another ... In the creature, the act of
being is received or participated .... To possess being is not be being itself
... it [ merely ] participates in
the act of being.” De Ente et Essentia, c.4
6 AMC
2.5.7
7 I Jn.
3.2
8 DNS
1.8.4
9 DNS
1.9.4
10 DNS
1.9.4
11
DNS
1.9.6-7
12 DNS 1.9.8,
emphasis added
13
DNS 1.9.9,
emphasis added
14 cf. DNS
2.20.5
15 The one, of
course, is held to have a direct bearing upon the other. A reciprocal relation
is understood to obtain not only between the soul and the body, but between the
natural and the supernatural realities simultaneously embraced and enacted in
the being of man. And while reciprocal, it is not held to be ontologically
equal. The existential principle enacted in man and understood as his being is
not equally predicated of the soul and the body. The being of the soul, while
largely enacted within the body, is nevertheless understood as independent of
the body. But the being of the body is understood to have no such independence
from the soul. The being of the soul is held to continue after the body has
ceased to be conjoined to the soul. But the being of the body is not held to
continue after the soul has ceased to be conjoined to the body. Despite the
organic unity of body and soul that is understood to constitute the total
created being of man, their existential disjunction entails the death and
eventual nonexistence of the body --- but is held to result in the perpetuity of
the soul. In a like manner, the consciousness coterminous with identity is
acknowledged not to diminish with a progressive dismemberment of the body, but
is, in fact, held to remain intact even as the physical locus of that
consciousness diminishes. And this is simply another way of acknowledging that
the being possessed of the mind --- if you will, the soul --- is of another and
greater magnitude than that possessed by the body. It is essentially, or at
least implicitly, a recognition of the subordination of matter to mind, of body
to soul, of nature to spirit. Man’s being, then --- at least from the Christian
perspective --- is understood to be preeminently radicated in the soul,
even as his divinely constituted nature consists in that union of body
and soul before which alone the doctrine of the Resurrection is coherent.
In fact, and paradoxically, for the Christian, the possibility of union at all
presupposes first the Incarnation as we shall later see.
16 cf. DNS
1.9.8
17 DNS
1.10.6
18
DNS 1.11.1
emphasis added
19 DNS
1.11.4
20 AMC 2.I-III,
2.6.1-6ff.
21 AMC 2.1.1,
2.3.1-3, 2.61-2, 2.8.4-5, 2.9.1, 2.10.4, etc.
22 LFL
3.17
23
Soliloquiorum 2
24 DNS
1.12.5
(Continued below)
The Metaphysics Part III:
The Twilight of Reason
The soul, we have seen, has stood at the twilight of reason;
it has been brought to the brink of being, beyond which lies the bourne between
the Uncreated Absolute and the absolute contingency of all creation. It is
filled with a light quenched in darkness, the darkness ex nihilo from
which all creation sprang and from which all creation shrinks. The last, most
certain guide, experience, blenches before the abyss and, like reason before it,
defaults entirely to faith in whose certitude alone remains the unwavering
pledge to transition, to transfiguration in the unquenchable light beyond.
Night, then, is the chrysalis once burst from which the soul will emerge in
unspeakable splendor, in the unutterable beauty of the image of God. This is the
plight of the mystic upon the inauguration of the Night of the Spirit.
But this crucial transition, as we had pointed out earlier, is not experienced
by the mystic as a sudden breach in continuity as our narrative might suggest.
Still less is it understood to follow causally from, that is to say, as a
necessary and immediate consequence to, the negation of sensibility. It is
really the culmination of a gradual, often subtle transformation which God alone
providentially effects in the soul; a point about which St. John is extremely
clear:
“The soul which God is about to lead
onward is not led by His Majesty into this night of the spirit as soon as it
goes forth from the aridities and trials of the first purgation and night of
sense; rather, it is wont to pass a long time, even years, after leaving the
state of beginners in exercising itself in that of proficients ...”
1
These two entirely
distinct moments, then, although methodologically related, are not logically
mediated or causally conjoined. Nothing in the way of necessity determines their
relation outside of the chronological order in which they must occur according
to the metaphysical logic of the via negativa. St. John, in this respect,
is clearly aligned with that tradition in Western mysticism, the broad consensus
of which holds that the mystical experience results from the beneficence of
extraordinary grace alone 2 and is, as we had already seen, and as St. John repeatedly
points out, entirely dependent upon God’s initiative. But what is of particular
interest to us here is what follows once this initiative is exercised on
the part of God. And here, once again, as in every transition, we find the
via negativa inexorably implementing the logic of mysticism, for this
night of the spirit to which the soul is invited is in fact the negation
of spirit --- the negative moment in which God, according to St.
John:
“... strips [ the soul’s ] faculties ...
leaving the understanding dark, the will dry, the memory empty, and the
affections in the deepest affliction, taking from the soul the pleasure and
experience of spiritual blessings which it had aforetime, in order to make of
this privation one of the principles which are requisite in the spirit so
that there may be introduced to it and united with it the spiritual form
which is the union of love.” 3
The Via Negativa, Annihilation, and Pre-Noetic
Transition to Union
The principle of which
St. John speaks in the above passage is unquestionably that of the via
negativa of which we have had ample illustration in the Ascent. But
while the role of the via negativa in the Ascent was purely
predispositional to the possibility of union and rendered the soul merely
proximate to God, this multifarious principle of negativity now assumes a
significance inseparable from, and in fact coterminous with, the mystical
experience itself. It is no longer a factor merely contributing to
predisposition and proximity, but is finally seen to be contemporaneous
with, and the occasion of, the divine infusion
itself:
“When the faculties had been perfectly
annihilated ... together with the passions, desires, and affections of my
soul ... I went forth from my own human dealings and operations to the
operations and dealings of God. That is to say, my understanding went forth from
itself, turning from the human and natural to the divine ... And my will went
forth from itself, becoming divine; for being united with divine love ... it
loves ... with purity and strength from the Holy Spirit ... and the memory has
become transformed into eternal apprehensions of glory …” 4
But how, we must ask, is
this accomplished through the via negativa? Why is it now seen to be
invested with the extraordinary significance of being the occasion
(albeit not the cause) of mystical experience, such that St. John would
be able to state that when the faculties have been perfectly annihilated it
becomes one with God to such an extent that its operations may be said to the
operations of God? For our answer, we must look closely once again to the text
itself --- but only after posing a more fundamental question still, a question
relative to an earlier statement made by St. John which, I think, carefully
considered, will provide us the means around which to formulate the answer to
our present question. To wit, how are we to understand St. John’s contention
that:
“... [ the
via negativa ] is one of the principles which are requisite in the
spirit so that there may be introduced to it and united with it the
spiritual form of the spirit which is the union of love.” 5
The principal role of the
via negativa as an existential application of the logical law of
non-contradiction to metaphysically incommensurable categories had, of course,
consisted in removing, or more properly, negating, all those elements
antagonistic to the soul’s union with God. In this role, however, the via
negativa had functioned merely propadeutically: in rendering the soul
proximate to God through eliminating all contrariety with God, it merely
predisposed the soul, made it receptive, to the possibility of union. However,
we had equally seen that an ontological gap, one interpretable in terms of
experience and opposition, nevertheless remained which the via negativa
of itself could not negotiate. The transition, we had found,
implied nothing in the way of necessity such that union with God followed as a
consequence --- rather, we had understood it to be solely dependent upon
the free will of God. If this, then, is the case --- as indeed it is --- our
next question really ought to be this: how, in fact, does God accomplish this
transition? That is to say, given the divine will, by what means is this
transition effected?
While it is undeniably
within the province of God to summarily bring the soul to the fullness of union
by a simple fiat, this has been neither the experience nor the testimony of the
mystics in general --- nor is it that of St. John. Like every other movement
that we have observed along the mystical continuum, the transition is not
sudden, abrupt, or immediate, but gradual; so gradual in fact as to be at first
imperceptible --- a phenomena to which St. John has already
alluded.6 So what is the means, what is this secret corridor through
which the contemplative is conducted to God across that great ontological divide
to which the soul was brought by the via negativa, but beyond which, of
itself, it could not pass? It is quite simply this: annihilation.
Annihilation is at once the end of the souls journey beyond contrariety, and the
beginning of the soul’s union in likeness. It is the beginning of the end of the
one that is the ending of the beginning of the other. In other words, the
perfect annihilation of which St. John speaks is at once the
pre-noetic transition to union --- already! Annihilation for the mystic is
the first and darkest moment of union. The last and final vestige of mediation
that precluded union --- which we had seen to exist in the notion of experience
--- vanishes in this perfect annihilatioon; an annihilation that leaves the
existence-only of the soul and God as the condition of that
existence.
The soul, in effect, is
annihilated in every aspect of its being except its being-only,
which necessarily is --- and implicitly had always been --- in union with God as
the condition of its existence, a union shortly to become noetically explicit.
So understood, annihilation is not a necessary consequence to the
via negativa. The farthest, in fact, that the via negativa can
bring the soul is to the sheer immediacy of experience-only which had always
implied a distinction --- and therefore could not produce union --- between the
experiencer and the experienced. And this distinction can only be expunged
through the annihilation of every aspect of the soul’s being with the
sole exception, as we had said, of its being-only --- which being derives
from God, and which then to extinguish is to utterly nullify. If, therefore,
annihilation is not a consequence of the via negativa --- then it can
only be effected by the divine will alone, which is to say, by
God.
But if the via
negativa can only carry the mystic so far, to advert to our earlier
question, how are we to understand it as concurrent with and the occasion of the
mystical experience? Clearly, as we have seen it to function thus far, it
cannot, as a principle and without modification, remain in the soul through, and
accompany it beyond, annihilation: its function, as we have repeatedly seen,
presumes contrariety and therefore distinction --- distinction which we had just
argued to have been abolished through annihilation. And while this is completely
true, it also appears to be true that the via negativa itself undergoes a
functional transformation. The principle, at least as we had understood it to
function previously, is no longer viable --- and yet St. John is clear that this
principle is nevertheless “requisite in the spirit so that there may be
introduced to it and united with it the spiritual form of the spirit which is
the union of love.” And this is to say that St. John is arguing it to be an
integral part of union with God. How can this be?
Well, let us approach our
answer this way. St. John effectively argues that the via negativa is a
principle in the soul. What does he mean by this? Essentially that the
via negativa itself constitutes a unique aspect of the soul’s
participation in God; a participation in that nature of God which is the
necessary self-separating of God from his creation. In other words, the via
negativa, we find, is implicit in God’s otherness to his creation. It is a
divine principle intrinsic to and eternally enacted in God --- and as
such, it is, eo ipso, in the soul as the image of God; the image
that is fully and authentically reappropriated through participation. It is the
occasion of union because it is already a union with God in his
otherness to nature. What was the separation of nature relative to God,
is now the separation of God relative to nature. In exercising itself in
the via negativa prior to participation, the soul, in fact, was enacting
a process intended not simply to remove contrariety to God --- but at once to
reveal its authentic nature as the image of
God.
The Prologue to Ecstatic Union
The night of spirit,
then, is in fact the prologue to ecstatic union, a union already marginally
effected --- but as yet ante-noetic in the negativity of spirit. In other words,
it is the celebrated “unknowing” that immediately precedes consciously
realized participation:
“the beginning of ... contemplation ... is
secret from the very person that experiences it. 7 ...[ for of] this spiritual night ... very
little is known ... even by experience.” 8
And it is precisely
because this night of the spirit is pre-noetic that the via negativa is
held by St. John to be not only requisite to, but contemporaneous with, and in
fact the occasion of, not simply union --- which, as we had seen, may be
“secretly” effected apart from any awareness whatever --- but the unfolding of
conscious mystical union. That is
to say, given this final
transition from proximity to participation the via negativa assumes an
altogether different task even while its function remains the same: it is no
longer a principle of absolute negativity --- a negating that results in sheer
negation --- as it was prior to the soul’s induction into spirit. Rather, it
paradoxically assumes distinct positive characteristics. It is now a negating
that is a positing: a negating of the superficies of being that simultaneously
reveals the being-essential, the being-fundamental underlying the superficial
strata of being that has no ontological consonance with that fundamental being
which is being the image of God. In other words, in negating, it discloses---
and as such, its movement is in fact contemporaneous with, and the occasion of,
fully-realized union with God. What is more, this further means that even prior
to conscious participation there is already an effective
ontological participation which then, and only then, becomes consciously
noetic upon the completion of the work of the via negativa. We now can
see that it is not the case that the via negativa caused
this union, but rather, that it made this union conscious, noetic, explicit. It
is God, rather, who is the cause of this union through his creation of the soul
in his image, an image whose being is ontologically radicated in the Being
Imaged.
Preempting the Problem of “Spiritual Forms”
In our eagerness to
pursue this point, however, we have neglected to address an equally interesting
and relevant concept that St. John brings up in a passage recently cited
concerning the notion of a “spiritual form.” In order to avoid any
subsequent confusion from a misunderstanding of this notion, it is very much
worth reviewing:
“... [ to be ] united ... with ... the
spiritual form of the spirit is the union of love.” 9
This spiritual form of
which St. John speaks is more clearly and intimately connected with the notion
of ecstatic union than would immediately appear, and it is not entirely, or at
least immediately clear why St. John chooses to render it with an abstraction
that is typically absent elsewhere. We may be inclined to think it entirely
likely that he chose to do so simply to emphasize a sense of contextuality in
dealing with this increasingly recondite Night of the Spirit. In any
event, the term unquestionably lends itself to being construed as synonymous
with “God”, and our question is, is that in fact the case? In a word, yes. It is
really a locus classicus in scholastic philosophy with which St. John was
entirely familiar since Thomism was the dominant philosophy taught at the
University of Salamanca at which St. John matriculated in 1564. For example, in
refuting the objection that God is composed of matter and form, Aquinas argues
the following:
“... every agent acts by its form, and so
the manner it which it has its form is the manner in which it is an agent.
Therefore, whatever is primarily and essentially an agent must be primarily and
essentially a form. Now God is the first agent, since He is the first efficient
cause ... He is therefore of His essence a form ...” 10
It is not, therefore,
merely highly probable, but virtually certain, that St. John’s use of the term
“spiritual form” in fact derives from Aquinas’s own analysis of divine agency in
terms of form --- and in fact is identifiable with God who is both form and
spirit. 11 This entire development, however, suggests something more
than the sense of mere contextuality to which we were inclined to attribute this
nominal transition. It is, I think, much more likely --- especially in light of
what we have recently discussed --- that at this stage of the development of his
mystical doctrine St. John wishes to emphasize that it is God alone who is the
sole agency in the mystical experience, and that this union of pure agency
12 with the passive (the
negated) soul is essentially that in which the mystical experience --- the state
of apotheosized being --- consists. We may even go so far as to say that the
being of the soul immediately prior to union is essentially a not-being (which
is not to say a non-being): it is being negatively considered, or perhaps better
yet, being reduced to the primal activity of being-only, to which no other
(positive) predicates attach. It is being extensively negated of every other
attribute, the actus essendi 13 whose activity is merely that of being and not of
being thus (or being such and such). As such it is a passive state, for
nothing more than being is predicated of its activity, or perhaps better yet,
nothing more may be predicated of its activity than this primal act of
being-only.
At first appearance this
might strike us as somewhat problematic given the sense of ordeal to which the
contemplative is subjected in this state, for St. John is very graphic in his
description of the suffering of the soul at this point, a suffering which would
imply something more than the soul’s apperceptive relation to its being-only,
but it must be remembered that the unique personal residuum which constitutes
the souls being qua personna --- that is, a personal being qua image of
the divine persona --- is preserved in the theological virtues as their
existential presupposition. But these virtues themselves, we will equally
remember, are functions of negativity. And what this means is that the
sufferings which St. John describes, far from amplifying the being
persona beyond being-only, result in fact from a privation of that being
--- they are in fact the result of beeing extensively negated of the
persona. And this further means that the being thus left is not being abstractly
considered; it is being instantiated in personal being, a being that is a
being-suffering---that is to say, being uniquely experienced in the
enactment of the dark night of the soul.
Now, St. John, as we have
seen, has already argued that this being is passive being. And this is to say
that only through participation in union will the soul reacquire active being,
and it can do so only insofar as it participates in agency. But we have equally
seen that the soul already participates in God ontologically prior to
this threshold of transformation in ecstatic union. This participation, however,
we had understood to be merely a participation in being-as-such, and not,
as we have argued, in being-thus. While it no longer possesses
contrariety to God, in its mere being-as-such neither does it possess any
similitude with God beyond being as the mere supposition of anything whatever.
And this could as well apply to a stone as to a soul. In other words, this type
of participation is of the most fundamental sort and really tells us nothing
whatever of that of which being-only is predicated, for it is largely being
considered negatively. It is the condition, but not the possibility of
discourse. Subsequent to the soul’s transformation in union, on the other hand,
it acquires a being-thus, being positively considered which
heteronomously derives from the being of another to which positive
predicates beyond being-only not only are ascribable, but in the
very concept of which these predicates are implied by definition. Seen from this
perspective, the mystical experience is totally dependent upon God as agency:
both as the agency alone through which the soul is brought to the state of
union, and as that agency in which the soul subsequently participates once union
has been effected.
The Empty Vestibule: an Analogical Tangent to
Understanding
Some further
considerations follow upon our understanding that an ontological participation
has, at this point, already been effected, a participation, we have seen, that
has not yet culminated in a clear realization that we might otherwise
characterize as noetic. The soul has just entered into the first stage of
mystical union but curiously its passive awareness remains incognizant of God.
Why is this? How are we to understand the soul to be in mystical union
with God, while at the same time unaware of it? The answer to this perplexing
question is suggested in the text itself, for relative to this inceptive state
of contemplation St. John argues the following:
“The clearer and more manifest are divine
things in themselves, the darker and more hidden are they to the soul
naturally... 14 [ for ] this divine and dark spiritual
light of contemplation ... [ is like] a ray of sunlight [ which ] enters through
the window which is the less clearly visible according as it is purer and freer
from specks, and the more of such specks and motes there are in the air, the
brighter is the light to the eye. The reason is that it is not the light itself
that is seen; the light is but the means whereby the other things that it
strikes are seen, and then it is also seen itself, through its reflection in
them; were it not for this, neither it nor they would have been seen. Thus, if
the ray of sunlight entered through the window of one room and passed out
through another on the other side ... if met nothing on way, or if there were no
specks in the air for it to strike, the room would have no more light than
before, neither would the ray of light be visible. Now this is precisely what
this divine ray of contemplation does in the soul ... it transcends the natural
power of the soul ... and darkens ... and deprives it of all natural affections
and apprehensions ... and leaves it ... dark ... [ and ] empty. The soul thinks
not that it has this light, but believes itself to be in darkness
...
15
in this state ... it is
fully prepared to embrace everything ...” 16
This passage is
remarkable for several reasons. To be sure, there is a clear continuity with an
entire tradition in mysticism that is immediately evident not merely in the
metaphorical structure of his argument, but in the metaphor itself that he
adopts. And while this point warrants pursuit in another context, it is entirely
aside from our present purposes. What is particularly noteworthy about
this passage is that it essentially constitutes an epistemological summary that
properly marks the beginning of St. John’s mystical epistemology. It is the
first time that St. John explicitly, if only analogically, treats of the noetic
element in mystical union.
Before going on to
examine the details involved in this cognitive analogy, however, a closer
examination of some of the statements he makes will prove helpful in clarifying
the critical distinction which St. John maintains between the natural
apprehension of God prior to the state of negation, and that intuitive noesis
which follows upon the soul’s union with God. For St. John --- as indeed it had
been for the Apostle Paul, who is widely acknowledged as the first mystic in the
Christian tradition 17 --- all created objects and concepts point to God, or at
least in some manner imply the existence of God.18 Consider the following abstract:
“... a ray of sunlight [ i.e. God: “
this divine ray of contemplation ...” ] ... is the less clearly visible
according as it is purer and freer from specks, and the more of such specks and
motes [ objects and concepts ] there are in the air, the brighter is the light
to the eye ...” 19
In other words, the
manifold of cognition is, for St. John, evidential: it somehow implicates or
communicates the existence of God. But it does so indirectly; it merely
reflects God, communicates God mediately:
“The reason is that it is not the light
itself that is seen; the light is but the means whereby the other things that it
strikes are seen, and then it is also seen itself, through its reflection in
them ...” 20
This mediate knowledge of
God, however, has been abolished in the via negativa through which the
mediating objects --- percepts and concepts variously --- had been
systematically eliminated, and with them, the ordinary mode of cognition which
had subsequently ceased altogether. The soul indeed is no longer aware of God,
for the objects variously mediating God to the soul --- in however inadequate or
impoverished a manner --- and apart from which the soul has no natural
apprehension of God whatever, have vanished, such that:
“The soul thinks not
that it has this light, but believes itself to be in darkness.”
21
It is this absence of
mediation, then, which ultimately constitutes this “terrible and dark
night” of which St. John so often poignantly speaks. It is night from the frames
of ordinary reference, from mediation --- and hence from cognition. And this
would explain why, contrary to what we may otherwise anticipate, this inceptive
state of union is not characterized by a sense of the numinous, an awareness of
God. It is the empty vestibule of which we had spoken earlier; the room which,
to use St. John’s analogy, despite its being suffused with light, remains dark
--- not only because the things with whiich it was formerly appointed are now
absent through the purgative and unsparing process of the via negativa---
but because the very walls defining it can no longer be
perceived.
While it is certainly
true that St. John’s analogy affords us little in the way of the close, concise,
analytical reasoning that we might in another context expect to accompany a
discourse on the first principles of a theory of knowledge, it no less
remains that this sort of purely academic inquiry is entirely subsidiary, if not
totally irrelevant, to St. John’s principle goal which is altogether practical,
and consequent to which his task becomes not analytical, but descriptive,
illustrative. And while this inchoate epistemological doctrine is only
analogically constructed, it is nevertheless sufficient for us to begin a closer
analysis of the cognitive elements we find in St. John’s description
of the actual mystical experience itself. First of all, it has previously been
shown at length that the state of mystical union presumes the absence of
mediation. And what follows from this absence has particular bearing on our
understanding the intuitional noesis in which ecstatic union consists. Take, for
example, St. John’s statement that:
“... in this state [ of negation, the soul
] is fully prepared to embrace everything... “ 22
To begin with, how should
we understand this very broad but clear epistemological assertion? Initially, I
think, we are reluctant to accept it at face value, for the soul of itself ---
and therefore, of course, its cognitive faculty --- we have consistently
understood to be finite in nature. It is therefore difficult to understand the
sense in which St. John asserts that it is epistemologically capable of
comprehending “everything”. We are inclined to see such precipitate statements
really as endemic to a class of literature only broadly understood as “mystical”
and which, regrettably, tend to put the entire mystical tradition into a
disrepute of which it is not worthy. Exaggerated statements of this sort ---
which regrettably but typically abound in the writings of other and less capable
authors than St. John --- when subjected to even the most superficial
examination are likely to result in
what may politely be
called inexactitudes as likely to derive from faulty reasoning as from poetic
excess.
Our question, then, which
begs to be generalized but which of necessity we confine to our present inquiry
is this: Given the indisputably finite nature of the soul, should we then
understand the above statement made by St. John as an instance of this type of
hyperbole which even the most scrupulous reasoners occasionally indulge? In
other words, is St. John’s statement that the soul is “prepared to embrace
everything” really meaningful at all in a way accessible to those of us
standing outside this closed circle of light? In a word, does this statement
coherently follow from the premises that we have understood thus far? And
this is really to ask a larger question still, and one which conceivably
implicates the credibility of St. John’s entire account: how much significance
are we to attribute to such utterances --- even if isolated --- and to what
criteria do we appeal in distinguishing between the prima facie value of
meaningful statements and their merely hyperbolized counterparts? And this, I
suggest, can only be answered in terms of the internal consistency of the text
--- which is to say in terms of the coheerence of the metaphysics underlying it.
If this is not forthcoming, if these metaphysical assumptions remain essentially
indemonstrable, then the entire enterprise to which we have set ourselves is
worthless, or what is worse yet, entirely factitious. So let us look very
carefully at this statement which is really paradigmatic of the reasoning of St.
John.
I think it is very clear
that, for St. John, the soul in this pre-noetic state exists as the sheer
potential of no longer limited, but universal cognition inasmuch as the soul in
fact is already seen to be participating in the divine essence. And what this
means is that when this participation is no longer merely ontological, but is
rendered noetic, the soul will equally participate in the divine mind since
every attribute of God coincides with his essence --- and as such, the soul will
share in that knowledge of God which is universal and unlimited. Moreover, and
what is of vastly greater significance still, the consequence of this epistemic
union has a direct and crucial bearing not only on the soul’s cognitive capacity
as such, but on the very manner in which this capacity is now
exercised.
Hitherto, the soul’s
acquaintance with things in general was mediated to it through sense experience
in the case of percepts, or through discursive reason in the case of concepts.
In either event, the souls knowledge was always mediate, it was an acquaintance
with things through sense or reason; in other words, they were acquired
mediatively, and more importantly still, acquired as modified by sense,
as accommodated to reason. But now, in virtue of this noetic union with
the Absolute, it knows them in and of themselves as purely objective and
unmodified realities. Its knowledge is, to adopt Kant’s terminology, an
acquaintance with noumenal reality, with the thing in itself, and no longer as
phenomenal, as the thing modified by, to be accommodated to, reason or the
senses. And this further means that the soul’s perception in the state of
ecstatic union will no longer be an indirect cognition of natural objects
and created concepts through the medium of experience --- which always
posited a distinction between the thing experienced and the one experiencing ---
rather, it will be a cognition of things directly through
God. Fully participating in the divine perspective, it will see through
the eyes of God, in other words, as God Himself sees. And this, I think, is what
St. John understands by the statement that the soul is prepared to embrace
everything, for consciousness at this point is no longer the possibility of
anything, as it had been prior to union, but of everything, for it
is consciousness which has completely transcended all finitude and limitation
through its apotheosis in God. The discursive dialectic of reason which
discovers the relation among objects and ideas is supplanted by an intuitional
noesis in which the distinctions characteristic in perceptions of finite
entities are sublated into a type of epistemological monism --- not one in which
these distinctions evanesce, or are ultimately seen to be illusory, but in which
each discrete entity is not dogmatically individuated or existentially isolated,
but rather is seen to contribute to, to be constitutive of, the coherent whole
of creation which itself not only ontologically subsists through, but is
teleologically ordered toward, God. The soul, then, has arrived at this deific
knowledge which is both intuitive and monistic because it has transcended the
four individuating frames of nature --- space, time, reason, and matter --- and
in having participated in the divine mind it necessarily shares in that single,
comprehensive, and universal knowledge which is properly predicated of God
alone.
The Vertical and the Veridical: the Problem of
Knowing
From a purely
epistemological point of view, two distinct vertical moments are therefore
observable in the mystical doctrine of St. John: the movement up to God (and
consequently to a veridical knowledge of God) in union, and the movement back
down to nature (and consequently to a veridical knowledge of nature) in
participation. And this last is indeed a surprising consequence, for it is
tantamount to asserting that the only veridical knowledge of anything is
to be found in God alone. Moreover, it is equally to assert that the
authenticity of man’s knowledge is, in the most fundamental sense,
directly dependent upon the possibility of his participating in the
knowledge of God through mystical union with God. And it is precisely a
misunderstanding of this contention that piques the critics of mysticism,
skeptics and faithful alike, who embrace a more conventional, if democratic
approach to knowledge, for the notion of the authenticity of knowledge has, at
this point in St. John’s account, taken an apparent, if decidedly esoteric turn.
Not only is God not veridically cognized outside the state of union
23, but neither is nature --- our knowledge under the
best of circumstances remains necessarily truncated by our finite nature. That
monistic whole, alone in which veridical knowledge may obtain, is, for the
mystic, available only through participation in the infinite and uncreated
knowledge of God. And where the skeptic would maintain that while such knowledge
is clearly conceivable, no such knowledge is possible, the mystic would retort
that not only is it conceivable, but it is, through divine dispensation,
actually available. The contention really revolves around, not so much a lack of
consensus concerning the definition of knowledge, but its possible scope, and
this question --- very much an indispensable part of our own epistemological
analysis --- would require a generalized summary that is clearly apart the
modest purview of our present inquiry --- although we shall attempt to address
some of the more pertinent objections arising out of this question a bit later
on in our commentary.
It nevertheless remains
extremely relevant to our own purposes to explore this question further within
our own present context. While it is very clearly arguable that the knowledge we
acquire in ordinary states of affairs is a matter of the most practical
importance and therefore demonstrates some genuine correspondence with
the phenomenal world at large, to the extent that we conceive our claims to
knowledge to be confirmed within and therefore validated by experience --- a
point which, I hasten to add, the mystic does not contend --- and even if
incomplete, inasmuch as it is nevertheless partial, it is at least partially
true, or in some at least limited aspect authentic, the implicit mystical
indictment of purely human knowledge --- knowledge acquired either solely by
empirical acquaintance through the senses or as conclusions drawn from
syllogistic reasoning--- remains no less valid. Human reason in and of itself
cannot discover, perceive, penetrate to causes, for it cannot perceive the
first, the uncaused Cause, which is God; it perceives an orderly concatenation
of events despite the remonstrance of reason that no nexus is discoverable
between them; it perceives in part what is essentially a whole, and what it
perceives, moreover, it modifies in acquiring, it subjectively invests with
qualities essentially extrinsic to the object; it never escapes itself so it
never achieves, attains to, objectivity. At best, man’s knowledge is incomplete,
and nature, while not sharing that same degree of opacity with God, is
nevertheless and at the very least recalcitrant to human knowledge given man’s
inherently finite approach to every conceivable datum. But this cognitive
recalcitrance, both to nature to a lesser degree, and God to a greater, is, St.
John argues, overcome in mystical union --- and it is overcome precisely because
the soul is enabled to participate in the infinitude of
God.
Certainly one of
St. John’s premises is a philosophic commonplace, for it is widely agreed, by
skeptic and mystic alike, that man’s knowledge, however extensive, is
necessarily incomplete. The very notion of complete knowledge implies
exhaustive cognition, universal in scope, and of infinite intension; and while
we hold ourselves, or the object, or both, either incapable of, or unsusceptible
to, this type of exhaustive scrutiny relative to a single item in experience,
still less do we presume it possible of that organic unity constituting the
world at large. But where the skeptic on his own resources has merely stumbled
upon the threshold and has pitched forward into what he finds absurdity, the
mystic has abandoned his resources altogether, and along with them the
contradictions and absurdities they entail, and has stepped across the
threshold; he has then turned and looked back and has reacquired in toto
what he erstwhile had only been able to appropriate in part. It is very
suggestive, in fact, of certain elements in Hegel’s Logic where all the
contradictions have been aufgehoben, the quarreling and competing
absurdities sublated into a unity greater than their disparity, a harmony
perceived in apparent discordance. But it is much more than this superficial
summary conveys. The point of the matter is that for St. John such knowledge is
only available in mystical states, and this knowledge alone qualifies as totally
veridical, for this type of knowledge alone is singularly complete. And what
this further means is that the knowledge, the entire truth, of a single item in
experience ultimately implicates the entire universe of experience, and that
until these latent implications are fully borne out, entirely realized, our
knowledge concerning any one item will always be in some way, and necessarily,
deficient.
But let us look to the
text one again relative to our interpretation of this intuitional noesis which
appears to be characteristic of the mystical experience. St. John describes this
cognitive transition in the following way:
“... the soul is to attain to the
possession of ... a Divine knowledge... with respect to things divine and human
which fall not within the common experience and natural knowledge of the soul
(because it looks on them with eyes as different from those of the past as
spirit is different from sense and the divine from human) ... this night is
gradually drawing the spirit away from its ordinary and common experience of
things, and bringing it nearer the divine sense which is a stranger and alien to
all human ways ... it goes about marveling at the things that it sees and hears,
which seem to it very strange and rare though they are the same that it was
accustomed to experience aforetime.” 24
The problem we confront,
I think, is very evident from the text itself: what in fact constitutes not just
adequate, but veridical knowledge? If on the one hand we define knowledge in
terms of the limitations inherent in human cognition, what we really have
arrived at is a definition of the scope of what is knowable and not a
definition of veridical knowledge. And much as we might desiderate otherwise, in
the ordinary state of human affairs we can hope to achieve no more. But at the
same time, these limitations are, after all, only temporal or spatial or both:
it is not the case that the type of exhaustive knowledge that we have
denominated as veridical is not at all possible, that is to say, in and
of itself, intrinsically impossible; rather, it is the case that it is
not possible given specific circumstances, in other words, in a temporal sense
--- either given human longevity, for wee shall never live long enough to acquire
that type of exhaustive knowledge --- or, for that matter, in the more
significant temporal sense in which we find ourselves incapable of excogitating
an infinite number of complex concepts simultaneously, and in so doing grasping
the relations that obtain between them, relations which essentially contribute
to a comprehensive understanding of them, for this we do discursively, as we
have already argued.
Nor indeed is it
possible, inasmuch as we are constrained by spatial limitations to which we are
perceptually subject, to grasp any given object of experience in its totality,
together with all its dimensions simultaneously; in other words, to perceive or
to grasp anything at all in the totality of its being in which alone we may be
said to know it, and not merely to know it in part, or aspectually. The problem,
then, is this, if we accept the human perspective not merely as
phenomenologically descriptive, but as normative, there is no place for the
epistemological assertions of the mystics and their utterances. The scope of
knowledge has been dogmatically defined a priori --- and despite the
testimony of disconfirming instances to the contrary. The threshold the mystic
has crossed, in short, has brought him not so much beyond the bounds of reason
as beyond the limits of accepted experience, and the transition becomes not a
transformation in truth but a descent into a preposterous, if elaborate,
fiction. The skeptic, in other words, in light of the perceived impossibility,
holds the type of knowledge to which the mystic testifies as really no knowledge
at all, let alone veridical knowledge of reality. On the other hand, if we take
the divine perspective as normative it becomes increasingly untenable to
maintain that what we call human knowledge really qualifies as knowledge at all;
indeed, given the subjective impedimenta we bring to our perceptions, it is very
difficult to assert that our knowledge is at all veridically related to its
object beyond its most superficial aspect. If we maintain both, we are unable to
account for the apparent disparity which exists between them. Let us put it
plainly. If indeed things are cognized as different in the mystical
state, and if moreover, it is only in the mystical state that unqualifiedly
veridical knowledge is at all available to man --- then what are we to say of
the epistemological condition of man humanly considered? That the so-called
knowledge of man is in fact no more than the mere apprehension of appearances to
which realities beneath the
appearances do not
correspond? Shall we then argue, as indeed Kant has before us, that given the
kind of constitution we possess we are condemned to appearances only,
appearances beyond which we cannot conceivably pass to das ding an sich,
the thing in itself secreted behind our own subjective projections? Ironically,
these competing perspectives, I think, both have a place in the thought of St.
John, especially in light of his own basically Thomistic natural epistemology
which is thoroughly empirical. But I would find the point of divergence between
the objections outlined above, and St. John’s own view on the subject, in two
essentially dissimilar interpretations of the nature of man inherent in each
account.
Empirical Considerations
The first objection we
encountered essentially interprets man solely, that is to say, exclusively, in
terms of his natural being, and indeed, from the point of view of those
who hold this position there is no other provable, empirically available, and
scientifically verifiable, dimension to his being --- man is neither more nor
less than an aesthetic (aisthetikos) being, a sensible organism endowed
with the faculty of reason and circumscribed by the limitations inherent in the
exercise of each. Any other purported dimension of man’s being that falls
outside the province of either is conjectural at best, or fictitious at worst
--- in any event it would be beyond the pale, and therefore outside the
competence, of the empirical sciences.
To a large degree St.
John would undoubtedly have endorsed at least the empirical assumptions in this
objection. But he would also have carried the issue further. Recognizing the
supernatural dimension of man, a dimension with which he had first hand
acquaintance, direct experience, experience as forceful as any delivered by the
senses --- and even more compelling, more cogent still --- he sees man’s
essential nature to consist in something more than the merely natural and the
sensible. And for the Christian mystic this recognition, it is important to
understand, in no way implies a denigration of nature and the senses which are
simultaneously perceived as indispensable components of man’s total
epistemological make up. It is a recognition, rather, of an ultimate and
irreducible ontological reflexivity underlying the mere superficies of man’s
being, the superficies beyond which sense and reason alone cannot penetrate, and
which, for St. John constitutes the very hypostasis of man’s being --- a being
that is being the image of God, a being-in-itself only possible through its
unique ontological status as a being-of-another. Given this metaphysical
realization a unique epistemology evolves from this experience, the logic of
which is every bit as coherent as that emerging from natural epistemology in the
context of its own phenomenological environment --- and this is to say that the
entire universe of experience, both natural and supernatural, is
fundamentally and profoundly rational from an epistemological perspective. The
distinctive epistemological contribution of mysticism derives from, and consists
in, its relation to the very categories before which natural epistemology
defaults, despite the corroboration of experiences it finds itself unable to
accommodate. The principles have not changed, but the environment
in which these principles now operate has: as a consequence they no
longer function in relation to natural, but to supernatural realities. In short,
just as the supernatural dimension of man is suppressed in the development of a
natural epistemology treating of man in his relation to the natural order, so
now the natural dimension of man is suppressed --- explicitly through the via
negativa --- in the development of a mystical epistemology treating of man
in his relation to the supernatural order.
While St. John’s
metaphysical assumptions about the essential nature of man have been discussed
here and elsewhere largely as logical conclusions drawn from his own descriptive
analysis of the activity of via negativa, the question nevertheless
remains to be asked: are these assumptions in fact, not just dissimilar, but
radically different from those encountered in natural epistemologies of the type
previously examined? In short, does St. John have an explicit doctrine to this
effect? If we anticipate an answer in the form of an abstract epistemological
excursus, we shall be disappointed, for this type of philosophical introrsion is
entirely aside from the purposes of St. John. However, it nevertheless becomes
unmistakably clear that such a doctrine is not merely implied in, but is
essential to, the coherence of St. John’s account. Consider the
following:
“This purgative and loving knowledge or
divine light acts upon the soul in the same way as fire acts upon a log of wood
in order to transform it into itself ... [ for the wood ] has in itself the
properties and activities of fire... 25 [ This ] divine fire of contemplative
love, [ then,] ... before it unites and transforms the soul into itself, first
purges it of all its contrary accidents.” 26
Now, these “accidents” of
which St. John speaks are unquestionably those very elements within man
exhibiting contrariety to God and which we had seen to have been removed by the
via negativa prior to union. We needn’t enumerate these contrarieties,
merely to note that among them discursive reason and sensibility --- among the
chief factors in a natural epistemological account --- are seen by St. John to
be merely “accidental” to man’s essential nature qua image of God.
27 Beyond these mere accidental qualities, and inaccessible to
reason and sensibility alike, lies a likeness (“it has in itself the properties
and activities of fire [ God ] ”) to God, an image or reflection capable of
being elicited and made explicit which we have seen to constitute man’s created
ontology. As we have said, for St. John, man’s ontic being is
being-image, and it is this most fundamental metaphysical assumption that
distinguishes St. John’s account from all others. In fact, strictly speaking,
given the several attributes St. John holds to be merely accidental to
man’s being, his account, otherwise substantially in agreement with,
nevertheless in certain aspects differs significantly from, the theological
tradition out of which his own epistemology arises and to which both Augustine
and Aquinas belong, a tradition in which the imago Dei is perceived in
terms of the intellect and reason.
28
A Paranthetical Problem of Accommodation
We hasten to add,
however, that this unique metaphysical perspective does not exempt St. John from
a clearly defined tradition to which he himself belongs, a tradition that is
both mystical and scholastic. His vivid analogy of light entering a dark room
29 for example, has its locus classicus in the
Pseudo-Areopagite’s opening chapter of De Mystica Theologica, while his
natural epistemology, as we have already mentioned, derives from St. Thomas
Aquinas’s own analysis some three centuries earlier, an analysis which in turn
borrowed heavily from Aristotle sixteen centuries before that. This is in no way
to diminish St. John’s unquestionable originality; it merely serves to indicate,
as E. Allison Peers has pointed out, 30 that a tremendous philosophic and mystical tradition has
been brought into focus in the creative mind of St. John.
On the other hand, this
is not to gloss over some very real difficulties which arise when St. John
attempts to align his own mystical doctrine with the tradition out of which his
own theology arises and to which he otherwise so tenaciously holds. There are
several passages within the text which leave us with an ineluctable feeling of
incongruity, the sense that a hiatus has abruptly occurred in the treatment. It
is as though some factitious element that does not readily accord with the whole
has been inserted into the metaphysical framework and has corrupted the text.
Moreover, when these, what can only be called interpolations, do occur, they are
brief and clearly parenthetical to the account. It is as though St. John is
giving voice to some alternative perspective to which he himself is not wholly
committed. The most notable example of this in dealing with his epistemology
occurs in the second book of the Dark Night. After providing a brief
summary of his own epistemological account of mystical union, St. John quite
suddenly --- and, we must add, very problematically --- inserts a passage which
appears to generate nearly irreconcilable tension between what are essentially
two distinct and competing interpretations: the one dealing with the immediate
and veridical cognition of God which we understand to be the central mystical
thesis, and the other an illumination theory constructed around a widely
accepted model of the hierarchy of being. 31 In this problematic passage St. John states the
following:
“... this dark contemplation infuses into
the soul love and wisdom ... [ and ] the very wisdom of God which purges the
souls and illumines them, purges the angels from their ignorances, giving them
knowledge, enlightening them as to that which they knew not, and flowing down
from God through the first hierarchies even to the last, and thence to men. ...
each one passes it on and infuses it into the next in a modified
form according to [ its ] nature ... 32 Hence it follows that, the nearer to God
are the higher spirits and the lower, the more completely are they purged and
enlightened ... and that the lowest of them will receive this illumination very
much less powerfully and more remotely. Hence it follows that man, who is the
lowest of all those to whom this loving contemplation flows down continually
from God, will ... receive it perforce after his own manner in a very limited
way” 33
The problems, of course,
resulting from St. John’s attempt to simultaneously accommodate both theories
are obvious at once: the mystic either has direct and immediate access to God
through ecstatic union --- a point which until now, St. John has vigorously
argued --- or he does not: his union with the Absolute is, in the end,
accommodated through an ascending hierarchy of intermediate
beings.34 In any event, it cannot be both. And yet both conceptions
figure largely in medieval thought, the former most prevalently among the
Schoolmen, and the latter among the mystics, although as we see, this division
is by no means exclusive. How can this be?
To answer this, we must
look briefly to the historical context in which St. John writes and attempt to
grasp something of the long-standing theological tradition from which this
hierarchical conception derives; a conception which, as we shall later see,
beginning with Ammonius Saccas of Alexandria, first found its most systematic
expression in Plotinus, Porphyry, Iamblichus, and Proclus in the anti-Christian
tradition, and which subsequently came to be adopted --- with obvious revisions
--- by Dionysius the Pseudo-Areopagite, Maximus Confessor, John Scotus Erigena
and St. Thomas Aquinas within the Christian tradition itself --- to say nothing
of the emphasis placed upon this theory in the extremely influential
philosophies of Avicenna (Abu Ibn-Sina) and Avicebron (Salamo Ben Jehuda Ben
Gebirol) outside the tradition of both. For the moment it suffices to simply
note the broad historical matrix from which this doctrine emerges in the way of
establishing the sense of continuity to be found within widely disparate
traditions; traditions which in sum form the basis for this metaphysical
conception of hierarchy to which St. John now almost parenthetically adverts.
Our immediate interest at this point, however, is not the historical development
of this doctrine as such, but, as we have said, lies in what appears to be its
blatant incongruity with the mystical thesis St. John had been so painstakingly
careful to establish and which, as a result, has become quite suddenly
problematic.
Here, for the first time
--- and for reasons that we shall soon ddiscuss --- we find a statement made by
St. John which I do not believe to be an authentic aspect of his real agendum,
or at least authentically descriptive of his actual thought. To begin with, it
is very difficult to understand how an epistemology which until now has dealt
expressly with the unmediated, unmodified, and therefore veridical
cognition of God as the most central thesis of the mystical doctrine, can
abruptly incorporate into itself elements no less expressly mediative and
modificatory. Indeed, the most casual examination of the epistemological
implications involved in this hierarchical doctrine of being relative to
mystical union reveals a divergence so great between the two apparently
competing interpretations as to preclude altogether the possibility of an
immediate and veridical apprehension of God --- consequently, the mystical
conception of God, together with the entire mystical thesis itself, is seen to
break down under the contradiction of conflicting metaphysics. It is, moreover,
equally troubling and extremely difficult to understand how so manifest a
contradiction could go utterly unobserved, or at least unresolved, in so careful
a thinker as St. John has proven himself to be. Is it really the case that he is
guilty of so egregious an oversight?
The evidence available
would seem to suggest otherwise. To begin with, we have already noted that a
kind of thematic incongruity is clearly observable within the account; a
precipitate, obvious, and awkward incompatibility which would seem to suggest
something in the way of a perfunctory gesture toward prevailing trends in
theological thought on epistemological issues to which St. John remains
uncommitted in light of the conclusions drawn from his own epistemological
analysis; conclusions, we will remember, which were not speculatively derived,
but based upon his own first hand experiences. Within these passages, moreover,
the logical coherence that consistently obtains between, and is always
observable within, the mystical dialectic that culminates in union --- a
coherence which otherwise characterizes the writings of St. John in general ---
is signally absent. Unlike every other significant concept which St. John
invokes in developing his mystical doctrine, the most central of which are
characteristically treated at great length and in much detail, this one doctrine
concerning the hierarchy of being is only accorded an elliptical treatment which
is essentially isolated from the overall mystical context, a context, we have
said, into which it appears to have been parenthetically inserted. This,
I think, is particularly noteworthy and deserving of further consideration. So
marked is this deviation, and so uncharacteristic of St. John that, except for
the mutual corroboration of even the earliest extant manuscripts, coupled with
St. John’s own distinctive style, we might too readily be persuaded that this
passage was in fact an interpolation insinuated into the text in an effort to
make it more closely accord with orthodox theological thought on this subject
which, at least within the tradition of Christianized Neoplatonism, extended as
far back as the unknown 5th century author of the
Areopagitica.
Given the internecine and
sometimes rancorous opposition to the reform of the Discalced Carmelites which
had been initiated by St. Teresa of Avila --- herself a mystic and contemporary
of St. John who had closely collaborated in her efforts --- together with the
greater historical context in which St. John wrote his treatises and of which
the Reformation was the most significant feature, 35 to say nothing of
the characteristic suspicion with which the writings of the mystics in general
were regarded (and quite often with good warrant), it would appear to be
virtually certain that the citation in question is, in fact, a conciliatory, if
perfunctory gesture to orthodoxy --- an orthodoxy, ironically, which St. John
never repudiates, even implicitly in his most abstract metaphysical statements.
This contention, I think, is further borne out by the fact that the Holy Office
--- more popularly known as the Inquisittion --- sat in tribunal to formally
condemn some forty propositions taken from the 1618 Alcala edition (editio
princeps) of St. John’s works --- only some 27 years after his death. The
condemnation, however, was never effected due in large part to the vigorous
defense of his works by the noted Augustinian scholar Basilio Ponce de Leon who
systematically demonstrated the orthodoxy of each of these forty propositions
against the charges of the Office, most of which stemmed from a confusion of St.
John’s doctrines with those of the Illuminists who held that due to the soul’s
passivity in the state of contemplation, it was incapable of sin regardless of
any act or omission. It is then all the more likely in this theological climate
fraught with suspicion that, despite St. John’s unwavering adherence to orthodox
doctrine, he would find it necessary to reaffirm his alignment with
orthodoxy.
While this, of course,
would explain the apparent lack of contextuality that we find in this and some
other statements of the sort, it does not resolve the metaphysical conflict the
statement generates. One cannot have the immediate intuition of God
mediately rendered through a descending hierarchy of being. And while I
am not suggesting that St. John was intentionally disingenuous in formulating
this contradiction, the apparent interpretation would be equivocal enough
to conveniently mollify the suspicious temperament of the age while at once
allowing an alternative interpretation more in line with his own reasoning on
the subject. To put it more plainly, I do not think that St. John consciously
contrived this contradiction out of expedience, still less out of duplicity. But
as a matter of interpretation it conveniently served both purposes. It was in
fact an accurate description, and it completely aligned with traditional
doctrine --- and it was, in fact, St. John’s own epistemological position! But
how can this be? Simply in this: what St. John describes in this problematic
passage is not the extraordinary illumination accompanying mystical union
36, but rather, the ordinary illumination accorded man
in the state of nature 37, for St. John is clear that:
“... this dark contemplation infuses into the
soul love and wisdom jointly ... 38 [ and that ] From this we shall
also infer that the very wisdom of God which purges these souls and
illumines them, purges the angels from their ignorances ... flowing down from
God through the first hierarchies even to the last, and thence to men ... for
ordinarily [ this illumination ] comes[ s ] through the angels ... “
39
That is to say, this
wisdom that accompanies union, a wisdom co-infused with love, is in fact the
self-identical source of that wisdom with which God illuminates men, through the
angels, in the unnegated state of nature. What St. John is saying, in
effect, is that the knowledge of God ordinarily given to man through the agency
of the angels according to the accepted scholastic epistemological schema, does
in fact constitute knowledge of God --- but only as it is acquired mediately in
nature, and not intuitively in union. By permitting this type of equivocal
interpretation, St. John is able to accommodate both without compromising the
integrity of either. It is extremely important, however, not to be misled by
this passage. We must clearly understand that this mediating and modifying
series of intermediary agents --- to which St. John adverts out of expedience
and in a manner sufficiently equivocal for the purpose at hand --- is
by-passed in mystical union through the soul’s direct and immediate
apprehension of God, unimpeded by any hierarchy
whatsoever.
This confusing and
clearly parenthetical treatment occurs nowhere else in the text and contributes
nothing essential to our understanding; on the contrary, it serves only to
obscure that pervasive theme to which St. John immediately returns in concluding
his treatment on the dark night of the soul, the dark night which has finally
receded through the soul’s noetic participation on God, for in these final
stages of infusion,
“... the soul become[ s ] wholly
assimilated into God by reason of the clear and immediate vision of God
... when it goes forth from the flesh ... this vision is the cause of the
perfect likeness of the soul to God, for as St. John says, we know that we shall
be like Him 40 ... not because the soul will come to have
the capacity of God, for that is impossible; but because all that it is will
become like to God, for which cause it will be called, and will be, God by
participation... 41 In this last step ... there is naught that
is hidden from the soul, by reason of its complete assimilation.”
42
The Divine Reflexivity
In these last stages of
mystical union, that relation of divine reflexivity, the intimations of which we
had seen to occur earlier and elsewhere, is at last finally explicit. The
mystical deduction becomes complete. It is clear that there is an ontological
connection between the soul and God which is more comprehensive, more
fundamental still than the being-only of the soul that derives from the
Only-Being of the Absolute; a connection in virtue of which alone a relation of
reflexive identity is possible such that “ the soul becomes wholly assimilated
into God by reason of the clear and immediate vision of God “ the nature
of which is such that “this vision
is the cause of the perfect likeness “ subsequently generated. And this
remarkable statement, I suggest, can only be understood in light of a
metaphysics constructed around man’s fundamentally reflexive ontology --- his
being the imago Dei, the reflection of God who is now clearly seen to be
not simply the ontic condition of the mere being of man --- but the exemplary
cause of his apotheosized identity.
This unique mystical
conception is not, as we had seen, merely constructed ex hypothesi; it is
fundamentally radicated in, emerges from, experience; an experience, moreover,
that is seen to accord not only with reason, but with the most incontrovertible
theological canon of all --- Holy Scripture --- for the conclusion drawn by St.
John of the Cross is essentially no different from that drawn by St. John the
Evangelist when he states that “ when he [God] appears we shall be like him,
for [because, in virtue of the fact that] we shall see him as he is.”
43 Apart from this mystical conception it is, I suggest,
impossible to understand how a “vision”, a seeing, a standing-before, can
produce, result in, “perfect likeness”, “assimilation”. This vision appears to
be the exemplary cause inasmuch as it presupposes a unique ontological matrix in
which the perfect likeness to be elicited already exists in posse,
as fundamental to, as essentially constitutive of, man’s irreducible ontological
being as the being-image-of. In other words, a vision, a standing-before, which
generates reflection already presupposes a reflective ontological nature
in virtue of which this vision is transformative. And this is to say that the
soul is already the possibility of this reflection as the unarticulated
image of the Absolute. In the state of union, then--- which consists in this
divine reflexivity --- this vision necessarily, inexorably, results in a
transformation in the essential ontology of the soul --- the soul qua image, qua
reflexive --- into the explicit reflection of God, and to such a degree and so
completely, that the soul in seeing God sees itself, and similarly, God
in seeing the soul, in effect, sees himself. St. John describes this
resonating dialectic in the following way:
“... such a manner of likeness does love
[union] make in the transformation of the two ... that it made be said that each
is the other and that both are one.” 44
Otherness, then,
conceived as a dogmatic distinction, is totally abolished in this state of
reflexive identity; it is sublated in that participative union that essentially
consists in the reflection of God into God. And this is the paradigm of the
mystical paradox. Through transcendence the soul has arrived at immanence. In
having gone utterly outside itself, the soul has discovered God within itself.
In having relinquished all, it has acquired the All; not in the way of some
vague poetic desideration, but as a distinct existential realization. The
resulting “oneness”, or the becoming one with God, which is a characteristic
feature of virtually all mystical phenomenologies, is, in the mystical
philosophy of St. John, quite different from every other competing system
essentially in this: not that it attains to oneness, but the oneness to which it
attains preserves even as it abolishes --- and in so doing apotheosizes, and not
abrogates. In that it derives, not from the mystical impulse itself in which we
discover only synapses of random intuitions that evidence little agreement
either among themselves or with reason at large; still less is it capable of
being indexed among the theosophical systems which, syncretistically
formulated in imitation of reason or imposturing as logic, conclude to a whole
that is inevitably opaque to logic, and dissonant with reason. Rather, the
oneness to which St. John adverts is the logical terminus to which reason
deductively attains through clearly defined and discernible copulas within the
logic of the mystical account. And this is to say in a broader sense that it
derives from a coherent metaphysics; a metaphysics out of which it arises much
as the conclusion to a sorites that has brought us through the via
negativa to the night of sense, the night of spirit, and finally to the
light of union --- to the face of God.
We thus find the mystical
epistemology of St. John to have culminated in that ontological resonance
between being-contingent-upon-the-Absolute and Being-Absolute, between the
Imaged and the image, the soul and God. Our understanding of this mystical
state, despite the consonance with reason that we have discerned within it,
remains abstract, remote, and at best only proximate. Discerning the internal
logic, we are, withal, unable to penetrate to the substance. We hold it to
accord with reason, but it only affords reason perspective, and not
understanding, for, in the words of St. John, not only is:
“... this dark contemplation secret...
45
not only does the soul
not understand it, but ... the soul is unable to speak of it ... the soul cannot
speak of it ... it can find no suitable way or manner to describe it ... and
thus, even though the soul might find many ways in which to describe it, it
would still be secret and remain undescribed ... it is like one who sees
something never seen before, whereof he has not even seen the like ...”
46
The intelligibility of
the mystical experience, then, presupposes as a condition of that
intelligibility --- the very experience itself. It is, in the last analysis, a
circle into which one cannot break, but to which one must be admitted; hence we
find the relatively esoteric nature of mysticism to derive essentially from the
inherent limitations of language, language which, as we had discussed earlier,
presupposes shared experiences to its intelligibility.
(continued below)
THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION
We must insist, however,
that although our understanding of this mystical state is only remote and
proximate, the external rationality of the experience is
nevertheless available to us; and this accessibility to, this consonance with,
reason is a compelling testimony in itself to what is at the very least the
probable authenticity of the mystical account. Let us look into this further. It
has been seen, by way of illustration, that given certain statements made by St.
John concerning the mystical thesis, certain other statements that he
subsequently makes about specific types of experience, not just follow, but
necessarily--- which is to say, deductively --- follow. For example, that
such states are consistently experienced in abstraction from time is both a
universal and uniform feature of the mystical experience. But unlike ordinary
facts or features of experience, it is necessary consequence of, and is
therefore deducible from, certain existential premises antecedent to the
experience --- in other words, this experience of abstraction from time is seen
not just to follow, but to necessarily follow --- to follow as a
consequence, as the logical outcome, of certain premises embodied in the via
negativa. That such experiences are characteristically atemporal in nature
follows of necessity from the fact that the suppression of time is the
condition of such experiences. Whatever the ensuing
experience may be, positively considered, we cannot say --- we cannot say that
such experiences will be of such and such a nature, for necessity --- as
Hume has vigorously, and I think correctly argued --- cannot be logically
ascribed to such assertions. The experience, in effect, may always be otherwise
than anticipated, for there is no inherent, that is to say, no logical
contradiction engendered in assuming so.47
At
this vital point we now find that our account has culminated in what is
essentially a convergence, an extremely critical juncture between epistemology
and metaphysics. Before we can so much as begin to presume to say
anything more coherent about the mystical experience described by St. John of
the Cross --- that is to say, if we presume to pass beyond what is more than
merely speculative --- we must examine the mystical doctrine of St. John in
light of the very serious Problem of Induction. If the mystical
philosophy of St. John of the Cross can offer us nothing more than what
contemporary philosophy to date has been able to proffer in response to this
enigma then our own account has ended on terms no less satisfactory than its
secular counterparts, and our own epistemological endeavor has resulted in the
same dismal conclusion, which is to say, that we can have no certainty whatever
concerning states of human affairs. It is my contention, however, as I had
stated at the beginning, that the philosophy of St. John of Cross offers a
unique and substantial contribution to the resolution of this recurrent problem.
Let us examine this further and very carefully, for in the mystical experience
alone, I suggest, we find the one disqualifying instance of the
problematic.
1 DNS
2.1.1
2
Which, by no
coincidence, is held to denote an extraordinary sharing in the life of
God.
3 DNS 2.3.3
emphasis added
4
DNS
2.4.2
5 cf. footnote
140 (DNS 2.3.3) emphasis added
6 DNS
1.9.6-7
7 DNS
1.9.6
8 DNS
1.8.2
9 DNS 2.3.3,
also AMC 3.14.1+2
10 ST I Q.3 art.
2, also cf. art.7
11 cf. Jn.
4.24
12 ST I Q.44;
art.4; De Potentia Dei Q.3 art.15 + ad.1, ad.2
13 the act of
being
14 DNS
2.5.3
15 DNS
2.8.2-4
16 DNS
2.8.3
17 2 Cor
12.2-4
18 Rom.
1.20
19 DNS
2.8.3
20
ibid.
21 DNS
2.8.4
22 DNS
2.8.5
23 cf. SC 6.4
ff.
24 DNS
2.9.5
25 DNS
2.10.1
26 DNS 2.10.2
emphasis added
27 This,
incidentally, is not to say that the soul does not reflect that consummate
reason which is to be found in the Divine intellect, much less that God is not
rational. This reason exhibited in God which the soul reflects participatorily
is the ratio of St. Augustine ( cf. Solil. 1.12-13; De Immort.
Anim. 6.11; 7.12; also cf. De Trin. 15.14 [Patrologiae Latinae 42
1077] and St. Thomas Aquinas (ST I Ques. 14 art. 7). It is intuitively
exercised, and is not, therefore, to be confused with its discursive counterpart
in man which, while a function of that same reason, is only finitely
applied.
28 cf. Aquinas,
ST I Ques. 3 art.1 rep. obj. 2; Ques. 45 art.7; Ques. 93 art.1-9; and Augustine,
De. Genes. Ad Lit. 6.12; De Trin. 14.16; De Civit. Dei
11.26
29 also cf. DNS
2.5.3 and SC 13/14.16
30 E. Allison
Peers, Ascent of Mount Carmel (Garden City, New York: Image Books,
Doubleday & Co., 1958), 48, Intro.
31 The passage
which follows. incidentally, derives from Aquinas (cf. ST I Ques. 106 art. 1
ad.1) who adopted it from the Pseudo-Areopagite (De Hierarchia Caelesti),
who in turn borrowed it from Plotinus (Enneads
5.1-11).
32 DNS 2.12.3
emphasis added
33 DNS
2.12.4
34 Specifically,
the choir of angels.
35 That St. John
was acutely aware of this burgeoning conflict is clearly reflected in certain
other passages, for example AMC 3.15.2
36 cf. AMC
2.24.2
37 cf. AMC
2.24.1
38 DNS
2.12.2
39 DNS 2.12.3
emphasis added
40 1 Jn.
3.2
41 DNS 2.20.5
(also cf. AMC 2.5.4+7; SC 11.6+7, 17.3, 27.2+3; LFL 2.30) emphasis
added.
42 DNS
2.20.6
43 1 Jn. 3.2
emphasis added
44 SC 11.6, also
cf. 18.4
45 DNS
2.17.2
46 DNS 2.17.3 (
cf. 2.17.6; AMC 1.3.3, 2.3.2-3.) This doctrine, incidentally, closely
corresponds to the Pauline conception that “Eye has not seen, nor has ear heard,
neither has it entered into the heart of man what God has prepared for those who
love him.” (1 Cor.2.9)
47 This forceful
line of reasoning has some rather interesting corollaries, not the least of
which concerns the phenomenon of miracles. If the reason for the uniformity of
the events we observe is not discoverable; that is, if we can perceive nothing
in the way of necessity linking putative causes to supposed effects --- and if,
therefore, the succession of observed events can always be otherwise than we
observe without implying contradiction, then while we have not answered
why miracles occur, we have nevertheless arrived at an explanation of how
miracles are able to occur. Miracles, by this reasoning, are not
understood to occur in violation of laws inherent in nature --- for there are in
effect no laws to be violated; only observed uniform events. From this
perspective, what we call miracles are no more than a reordering of an
anticipated sequence of events that were never necessary to begin with. And this
is simply another way of saying that in effecting a miracle God merely suspends
--- but does not violate --- what we connstrue to be laws at work in the
universe. If, moreover, the suspension of “laws” is attributable to God in the
occurrence of miracles --- and such miraculous events are (insofar as reason can
discover) at least as likely to occur as the effect we have come to anticipate
--- then what is to prevent us from ascrribing the uniform events that very
clearly occur to God as well, and simply because God wills them? It is, I
suggest, at least as cogent to argue that God is the cause of this uniformity as
to argue that there is no cause at all.
(Continued)
The Problem of Induction as
Pseudo-Problematic:
Mysticism as
Metalogical
Within the mystical
experience itself we can no more prescind from the problem associated with the
notion of causality than from any other state of human affairs. In other
words, mystical experience is no more exempt from logical problematics ---
simply because it deals with the individual in relation to the Absolute --- than
any other type of experience, and any epistemological attempt to render this
account coherent must sooner or later come to terms with the Problem of
Induction.
Let us first, however, be
clear about the problem before we begin to address it. The sequence of events
within which we are accustomed to discern any causal relation, such that
the effect perceived is construed to be in necessary relation to a
perceived cause --- which is
to say as invested with the same type of logical cogency that obtains between
premises and conclusions --- essentially result from what David Hume in his
Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding had called a “customary
conjunction”, a kind of psychological reflex conditioned by the perceived
regular succession of contiguous events. The implications of this type of
putative association are profound, and critical to our examination of the
concatenation of events we find occurring within the mystical experience.
Let us be more to the point. With no disconfirming instance occurring within our experience of any sequence of events that appear to instantiate a regular succession, we interpret what are essentially two separate and unrelated events --- or events related only through observation --- as causally conjoined and therefore necessarily related. A simple analogy will, I think, suffice. Suppose that each time I flip on the light in my study, a car is heard to backfire somewhere in the street. The coincidence at first strikes me as odd … but I find it recurring again and again, that is to say, without exception. Further suppose that, beginning to suspect some causal relation between these two otherwise completely unrelated events, I begin to consciously examine this phenomenon by turning the switch on and off at both regular and irregular intervals --- and each time, without failure, a car is heard to backfire. It is extremely likely at this point that I will posit what I interpret to be a causal connection to exist between the two, even though I find myself utterly unable to discover the nature of this apparent, but elusive, nexus between two otherwise discrete and unrelated events --- if indeed there is one to be discovered at all --- and we have no warrant, at least none served by logic, to believe that there is. Even one disconfirming instance will suffice to disabuse me of this notion, but none is foreseeably forthcoming. In other words, it is no less the case in ordinary states of affair, than it is in mysticism, that we cannot state a priori and therefore with apodictic certainty what course of events will follow those which precede them.1
The implications of this
assertion, together with the problematics inherent in it, have a direct and
significant bearing upon mystical epistemology. While we are unable to say, in
any event, what a particular experience will be, especially as it pertains to
union with the Uncreated Absolute--- whatever it can be, it cannot
be temporal, for this possibility has been categorically eliminated by the
via negativa as a condition to whatever type of experience
will ensue, although we cannot positively say what this type of
experience will be. One cannot, for example, experience participative
union with the Timeless and Eternal God without experiencing the
timelessness and eternity of God in that union which transcends time. And this
is to say that the negative logic of the via negativa
invests certain types of experiences subsequent to union with a negative
necessity. In a sense, while it cannot prescribe certain experiences,
it proscribes others. It informs the nature of subsequent experiences as
no positive principle can. As David Hume had correctly pointed out, our
experiences subsequent to a given event may indeed always be otherwise
--- but not when the conditions iinforming such experience, that is to
say, as prerequisite to the possibility of that experience, preclude some
clearly defined and distinguishable phenomena from it. In this sense, it is very
much analogous, from a purely negative perspective, to the argument that Kant
articulates in his attempt to answer essentially the same the question but
within a positive context: “How are a priori synthetic judgments
possible?”; a question to which he first formulates his answer in terms of the
Transcendental Aesthetic, the principal features of which are what he
calls the “two pure forms of sensible intuition serving as principles
of a priori knowledge, namely space and time.” 2 These Kant saw as necessary features of any possible
experience, and therefore could be posited a priori of every conceivable
experience. While we cannot explore Kant’s argument in depth, a brief aside may
prove helpful in illustrating our own point.
Mystical Transcendence and Transcendental
Aesthetics
For Kant, every possible
experience is necessarily invested with temporal and spatial aspects
which he describes as the two forms of sensible intuition that are the a
priori , the necessary, conditions of all appearances; time as universal to
every intuition, and space as relative to every outer intuition.
Every possible percept, every conceivable concept, Kant argues, is not just
invested, but necessarily invested with at least one of these two forms
of sensible intuition precisely because they are what he calls the “subjective
conditions” of sensibility: they are the only way that we can apprehend data
given our subjective constitution as such, in other words, given the inherent
epistemological apparatus with which we have been constitutionally endowed by
nature. In effect, the data delivered by sensibility acquire these
spatio-temporal aspects precisely because our subjective constitution invests
them with these features in order to make them available to us. As a result, we
can state a priori that all possible experiences will be spatio-temporal
in nature because space and time are the conditions under which alone
data may be received given our unique subjective apparatus which synthesizes
data through the forms of space and time through which alone they subsequently
become intelligible to us. In the words of Kant, they are the very “condition of
the possibility of appearances.” 3 And this, in effect, is how synthetic a priori
judgments are possible. Within the terms outlined by Kant in the
Transcendental Aesthetic, we can say, a priori (that is to say,
with certainty) that the nature of any possible experience --- even without
being able to say what that experience will be --- will at least be
temporal or spatial, or both.
The resulting problem ---
the penalty, if you will --- involved in acquiring this type of certitude of
course, is that we subsequently acquire knowledge of what are essentially
appearances, or phenomena, and not what Kant calls the nouemna,
the objective realities concealed behind the forms of space and time; forms, we
had seen, imposed upon the noumena of subjective necessity. For Kant,
then, whatever our experiences may not be, the matter is that Kant’s thesis, as
we can now see, is essentially diametric to that of St. John. But where Kant had
asked the question “how are a priori synthetic judgments possible?”, or
in other words, how does necessity --- and therefore, in light of the
trenchant objections of skepticism, certainty --- not simply
obtain relative to our experiences of the natural order, but
deductively follow from epistemological considerations deriving from
man’s subjective constitution as such --- St. John now asks, at least
implicitly, how are epistemological considerations necessarily related to
metaphysics in the mystical experience, such that the conclusions drawn by
mystics about states subsequently to be experienced, not just follow, but
deductively follow from previously defined mystical premises? In other
words, how are the mystic’s epistemological presuppositions necessarily
related to claims about metaphysical realities encountered in the mystical
experience --- so that the mystic’s purely negative claim, for example,
concerning the ineffability of this experience, is validated? In short, are
these claims merely analytical propositions that necessarily follow from
epistemological premises to which no metaphysical reality necessarily
corresponds--- or do these premises themselves derive of necessity from the
metaphysical features outlined by St. John? In a word, does, indeed,
deductive certainty obtain --- and if so, what does it say about the
nature of the mystical experience that St. John describes?
To begin to answer this
question, we must once again turn to the most fundamental epistemological
feature deriving from the via negativa itself, namely that, unlike a
positive or prescriptive principle which purports to eliminate an infinitude of
other possible features or elements in the act of positing one, the
via negativa does not dictate that certain types of experience
will follow --- to the exclusion of all other possible types of
experience --- but that certain clearly defined types of experience will
not follow --- and will not follow of necessity given the conditions
under which alone these experiences may occur; conditions themselves dictated by
the via negativa acting in conformity with the metaphysical parameters to
which it is applied. In other words, the via negativa, not merely as a
negative logical principle, but as a conditioning factor --- a presupposition
--- of certain types of experience, inveests each movement in the progress to
mystical union with a deductive necessity relative to the type of experience
that it will not be. We can apodictically assert that certain experiences
will not be of such and such a nature simply because these types of experience
are otherwise unavailable except through the via negativa which
not simply abolishes ontological incommensurability, but in so doing establishes
an epistemological correspondence grounded in the negativity of this
metaphysical logic such that statements concerning any subsequent experience
whatever will not simply be true, but be necessarily true. And this
necessity clearly does not derive merely from relations obtaining between
logical propositions, but from relations that obtain between ontological
realities. That two of the terms negated by this negative principle of
metaphysical logic, then, are precisely those terms which Kant posits as
necessary to our apprehension of natural phenomena (to which Kant alone confines
himself as the only legitimate province of reason) --- space and time --- is no
coincidence.
In this regard, it turns
out, St. John is in substantial agreement with Kant relative to the limitations
of reason. But St. John would continue on where Kant defaulted, by appealing to
knowledge not acquired through reason and relative to experiences that are not
sensuously endowed. By a continuation of this inexorable logic, the descriptive
utterances of the mystics are understood to deductively follow as so many
conclusions from --- if you will, consequences of --- premises contained within
the via negativa itself; for example, that certain experiences are
unavailable except under certain clearly specified conditions, and that these
conditions determine a priori and deductively that only such and such
experiences can possibly follow. And it is precisely this type of deductive
certainty relative to this unique type of experience which, I suggest, strongly
corroborates the authenticity of the mystic’s claim to a type of experience that
is, at the same time, also validated by the demonstrable coherence of what he
utters. Nor must we think that the type of certainty that obtains between the
mystic and his experiences in any way compromises the acknowledged autonomy of
God, for as we had seen, the via negativa does not necessitate
that a particular experience follow from the mystical protocol --- merely
that should an experience follow (solely contingent upon the will of
God), it will in fact be invested with certain negative features according to
the inexorable logic of mysticism.
The via negativa,
then, is not simply a practical propadeutic to, but in fact is the logic of
mysticism. But what are we to make of the via negativa itself? How
are we to establish the validity of this negative principle of applied logic ---
not merely in its negative, logical function which, as we had seen, is
essentially an existential application of the law of the excluded middle, or the
principle of non-contradiction---but relative to the metaphysical assumptions in
which we see it exercised by St. John in particular, and, for that matter,
mystics in general? And our answer to this, of course, involves the entire
metaphysical infrastructure of mysticism. While, from a purely phenomenological
perspective, the via negativa presupposes the existence of the Absolute,
the infinite, the eternal, etc., it is nevertheless a presupposition held to be
verified in the mystical experience --- which in turn validates the via
negativa as corresponding to, if not a metaphysical reality, then at least a
coherent claim to a perceived reality. In a word, there is an undeniable
correspondence between the metaphysics and the experience --- and while we may
argue from the premises implied in the metaphysics to conclusions drawn from
these premises --- that is to say, find the conclusions to be implied in the
premises and therefore deducible from them, we cannot argue from premises
to experiences. And the existence of this type of correspondence between the
premises implied in the metaphysics and the experience itself, I suggest,
strongly supports the authenticity of the mystic’s claim.
The reality which the
metaphysics purports to describe, and the reality actually encountered by the
mystic, correspond too exactly and too consistently to be considered less than
strongly evidential. And this, in turn, brings us to a clearly related issue
that will be examined in greater detail later on but which at the moment is
extremely pertinent to the present inquiry: if experience substantiates the
negative claims embodied in the via negativa, then this means that not
only are statements about certain types of mystical experience logically and
metaphysically consistent with the principles from which they purportedly
derive, but that such statements deriving from these principles are in fact
empirically substantiated in experience. The metaphysics of mysticism, then, is
at least logically consistent. But what is more, its strictly logical claims are
existentially instantiated in the mystical experience itself --- which is to say
that the principles correspond to realities. And unless this claim is
discredited, the mystic is able to offer the skeptic at least two complementary
credentials requisite to any science: correspondence with reason and
compatibility with fact. Of course, the skeptic will demand much more of the
mystic in the way of complete accountability, but, as we shall find, no more
than the mystic would require of the skeptic in the demand for equal
accountability.
Three arguments, then,
are essentially brought to bear upon the credibility of the mystical experience.
It is one thing to state from a metaphysics that some dimension of reality
exists qua rational; in other words, to conclude to some aspect of reality from
purely rational premises. It is quite another thing to say that such a dimension
has empirical reality. But what is more, it is something else altogether to find
that a clear, coherent, correspondence exists, is demonstrable, between what are
essentially rational premises and empirical conclusions. It is not merely to
say, as in the first case, that the rational is real, but in light of the latter
two cases, that the real is rational. In most sciences, for example, the
empirical verification of a rationally consistent hypothesis suffices to at
least conditionally validate the hypothesis as purporting to say
something authentic about reality, and inasmuch as it does, it is held to
have made a coherent claim upon reality. In other words, in light of the
confirmation of the hypothesis, warrant is derived to make certain statements
about, to predicate certain things of, reality in a way that is both rationally
and empirically consistent. In short, the correspondence between the hypothesis
and the empirical evidence is of such a nature as to be mutually corroborative,
and where this corroboration occurs we are generally agreed that sufficient
evidence exists to allow our claim of making a meaningful statement about some
aspect of what is real. But what is more, in many cases certain aspects of the
reality affirmed to exist by the physical sciences are characteristically
unavailable except through an extremely sophisticated procedural protocol
coupled with equally sophisticated technical apparatus. These aspects are not
only typically beyond normal empirical acquaintance, but cannot, moreover, be
apprehended unaided by artificial technology --- and even when so apprehended
exhibit such disproportion to ordinary perception as to appear to constitute
something altogether different. It is not that the reality itself has changed or
proven illusory --- it is that the level of perception has changed. And this is
to say that while the methods of attaining to certain ordinarily
undisclosed aspects of reality are quite different between the mystic and the
scientist, the results are strikingly similar. Too similar, in fact, to
be summarily dismissed.
The Model of Science: a Reluctant
Analogy
So let us carry the
argument further. The reality which science purports to disclose to us is, for
all practical purposes, intelligible, coherent, only to those who have submitted
themselves to exacting and rigorous programs in the physical sciences covering
an abstract spectrum ranging from integral calculus to quantum theory
propadeutic both to gaining access to, and to meaningfully interpreting, this
otherwise and ordinarily undisclosed dimension of physical reality. We may even
pursue the point further and say that these aspects of reality at which they
arrive are typically unavailable to the ordinary man inasmuch as he lacks the
basic aptitude requisite to the type of extremely abstract thought requisite to
these disciplines. This is not intellectual arrogance --- it is simply a candid
assessment that could be equally turned upon the point of artistic ability. Nor
am I persuaded that a specific aptitude is a democratic endowment that can be
cultivated through education and that, therefore, all men are latently
Heisenburgs or Pascals given the proper tutelage. But neither am I implying that
there is a mystical aptitude in the way that there are other clear aptitudes
within individuals for the arts or sciences. I am simply suggesting that certain
dimensions of reality are no more democratically accessible through science than
through mysticism. Our basic distrust of this argument, I think, stems from our
inclination to believe that, in the case of science, while we ourselves are
unable to enter into its mysteries, other men, better able than us, are, and
therefore can confirm the realities --- described by others --- which we
ourselves cannot.. But in the end this is either a restatement of the argument,
or a deferment of the conclusion. In any case, the layman by and large trusts to
the authenticity of the reality described by scientific specialists; specialists
who, as we have said, had undergone long, arduous years of training in order to
gain access to, and to coherently interpret, dimensions of reality available
exclusively through special equipment presumed to authentically disclose
elements of reality that in turn are interpretable only in terms of the most
abstruse and recondite hypotheses. There is much more to the objection of
science than this, but for the moment the analogy, I think, between mysticism
and science is fairly obvious. The realities, then, defined by Heisenburg and
St. John are in this respect equally opaque to the
uninitiated.
Considered from this
perspective, then, metaphysics is a statement about the ultimate nature of
reality much in the way that physics is a statement about the ultimate nature of
reality --- and these essentially are not so much competing statements as
complementary insights. It is not that there is a conflict about what
constitutes the nature of ultimate reality --- for this issue is entirely
outside the speculative interest and competence of physics --- as much as a
divergence concerning what is ultimate in the nature of reality, and we
arrive at divergent, even complementary, but not intrinsically conflicting
answers to this question precisely because the one, physics, delimits the scope
of its inquiry and establishes the limits of its competence relative to matter
considered as the ultimate constituent of physical reality --- a claim
with which the mystic would not quarrel within its recognized and legitimate
province --- where, on the other hand, metaphysics resumes where physics
leaves off and sees not the being of matter, but being as such, together with
the relations obtaining between modes of being, as the ultimate nature of
reality; a reality that clearly does not preclude physical being, but which is
nevertheless not constrained solely, or even principally to it. In a real sense,
the one appeals to that from which the other essentially prescinds inasmuch as
neither, in and of themselves, purport to provide a universal and exhaustive
schematic of reality in toto, but only a general understanding of the
principles underlying it. On the one hand, it would be both unproductive and
fatuous to argue that only what is sensible is real, for this would leave a good
deal more than pure mathematics and formal logic out in the cold. Or that
states-of-mind alone are real --- a statement neither entirely congenial to, nor
likely to be endorsed by, mystic and physicist alike. Nor yet as the Platonists
and Neoplatonists would contend that reality is quintessentially suprasensuous
and that our empirical acquaintances are either entirely illusory or at best
only impoverished representations of a sensibly inaccessible reality. St. John
no less than the physicist would find each of these three alternatives
unsatisfactory, and for reasons remarkably similar; reasons pointing to more
than a casual correspondence between theory and fact, metaphysics and reality,
which in turn strongly suggests that authenticity, in fact, is the copula
between the two.
Our question then becomes
this. If the logic and the metaphysics of mysticism rationally and consistently
explain the mechanics of the mystical experience and, in effect, account for
uniform and significant features of that experience --- which as such has an
empirical basis --- then on what grounds are we to reject the mystical
experience as non-veridical? The objections to which we have adverted --- its
characteristic unavailability to the majority of men, the unintelligibility of
its utterances to the uninitiated or to layman, the lengthy and rigorous
propadeutics required to have access to ordinarily undisclosed dimensions of
reality, its inability to be comprehended except by an apparently select few ---
without exception equally apply to science. And while it may be argued that one
scientist can confirm the observations of another, we may equally argue
on these very same terms that one mystic can confirm the experiences of
another. And this is to say that the notion of personal testimony is a
significant feature in both accounts. In short, it is very difficult to
understand how the mystical experience is to be rejected offhand without at once
rejecting not simply some extremely significant features of the scientific
protocol, but science itself as purporting to both veridically and meaningfully
convey the physical aspects of reality to us. And this really places us in a
skeptical posture that few of us would choose to assume.
This is not to say, of
course, that very clear differences do not exist between science and mysticism,
but it nevertheless remains that the notion of credibility as it pertains to
both accounts is too similar to be glossed over or simply ignored. And while we
may be inclined to see reason as superordinate to science as a more
comprehensive principle beneath which scientific theory is subsumed --- and
therefore more clearly evident within, and more confirmatory of, science than
mysticism --- some philosophical retrospect, I suggest, offers another and quite
different perspective on the matter. In fact, the notion of reason, or better
yet, specific features of the type of deductive reasoning from which a notion of
necessity follows are, I suggest, much more strongly supported by the mystical
account than by science, and for this simple reason: science is essentially
unable to extricate itself from the problem of induction. It cannot forge,
because it cannot discover, the vinculum that binds effects to putative causes.
It cannot argue with the type of certainty that is apodictic, or implies
necessity, that, for example, what so far has been the case relative to
specific observations, will in fact continue to be the case; that
given identical circumstances, the implementation of a specific hypothesis will
necessarily yield identical results: in short, that the future will conform to
the past.
Ex-Huming Hume
Let us assume that
B has always --- that is to say, historically --- followed, accompanied,
every observed instance of A. If we are then asked to justify our
expectation that the next occurrence of A will be accompanied by the
occurrence of B we will very likely say something like the following:
“every time, without exception, that I have observed A, it has been
accompanied by B, and I have never known of an instance of B that
was not preceded by the occurrence of A: therefore A and B
are so consistently, so uniformly conjoined that the occurrence of A is
understood not simply as antecedent to B but necessarily
antecedent to B. There is an observable sequence of uniform events to
which no disqualifying instance can be appealed, so A therefore is the
cause of B; there is, then, a necessary connection between A and
B that can therefore be scientifically legislated as a (physical) law
which admits of no exceptions.” And this, of course, is quite a subreptive leap
from a history of a uniform sequence of events, to the necessity
of the continuing uniformity of this sequence. And in the end, the justification
of this argument will always be circular: it will always appeal to experience
which will only disclose the sequence of observed events --- but not the
necessity presumed within them. In other words, there is no discoverable reason
why B, and not C or Y, should follow an instance of
A --- it is simply the case that B, in our experience, always has.
Now, of course we can argue, as indeed Russell has 4, that the discovery of uniformities alone, to which no
disqualifying instances have thus far been observed, suffices for the
rehabilitation of science through extreme probabilities that are quite nearly
tantamount to certainty, and that this is really the best that we can hope for
since nothing whatever in the way of necessity binds what we construe as effects
to events we interpret as causes.
Now, the implications of
this argument extend well beyond science and I think, relative to our own
position, it will be necessary to examine Russell’s objection more closely, for
it rather neatly summarizes the objection from skepticism in general. Russell
essentially argues
5 along with Hume that our belief in
causation results merely from the consistency, regularity, and uniformity of
observed events. This much, I think, we are fairly clear about. But the
interesting question relative to this line of reasoning is simply this: what are
Russell’s grounds for stating that uniform events cause our belief in
causation? Is it that hitherto uniform events have always caused our
belief in causes? And who is to say that tomorrow these same uniformities will
not cause our belief in causes, as they have in the past? To advert back
to experience is to reiterate the very argument which Hume and Russell have
discredited. And this is to say that if the premises upon which the argument is
constructed are not true, then neither is the conclusion. If we
consistently hold that we cannot argue from causes to effects except
inductively, then the grounds upon which we make this statement today --- our
experience of uniformity in events is the cause of our belief in causes --- may
not (do not necessarily) hold true for tomorrow. If nothing in the way of
necessity binds effects to causes, in either event the result is the same: the
discreditation of the notion of causality both as it applies to events observed
among phenomena, and as it pertains to the construction of the argument by which
the notion of causality has been discredited. If this argument is valid, then
Russell is correct in stating that we can achieve no more than probabilities.
But by the very argument itself Russell cannot argue to this conclusion
consistently from his premises. If, then, we have grounds for neither
necessity nor probability, we have no grounds for either claims to knowledge or
skepticism. Both are equally discredited.
If, on the other hand,
this argument is not valid, if this line of reasoning is not sound, then either
the premises or the conclusion, or both, are false. And I suggest that
the premises are false while the conclusion remains true for this reason:
Russell cannot explain the problem with believing in causes without appealing to
a cause (of the problem). In other words, he argues against causes by
using causes. And this really is to say that we cannot talk about
the problem without invoking causes --- and this would suggest that the
notion of causality is necessary to any discourse on causality. In other
words, even if, as Russell argues, we cannot discover it in events --- we cannot
dispense with it in discourse. And that with which we cannot dispense, we
understand to be necessary --- it is what we mean by necessary. The
relation, moreover, between my expectations and certain uniform events cannot
simply be a matter of inference: we do not infer that uniform events
cause our belief --- our belief is a direct result of, in other words is
causally related to, these events. It is not the case that we conform our
expectations to events; it is, rather, that our expectations arise from,
are caused by, these events --- whether or not this expectation in and of itself
is warranted.
There is, it turns out, a
necessary relation, not between the uniform occurrence of B subsequent to
A, but between my belief and the events that have caused my
belief. We should have no expectations at all, no belief whatever, apart from
the events which informed these expectations. Beliefs and expectations, then,
are necessarily related to uniform events. While there is no necessary reason
for the sun to rise tomorrow, there is a necessary reason for my
expectation that the sun will rise, and it is that I should have no such
expectation except for the observed uniformity of the sun having risen every
day. Nor can we argue that the conditions for our belief may not be the
same tomorrow; that is to say, that the conditions from which alone the
development of expectations derive may be different tomorrow from what
they have been today, or that tomorrow the uniformities we observe will no
longer cause any expectations regarding them whatsoever. For this would mean
that we can have no expectations. But we do have expectations. Whether or not
they are legitimate expectations --- which is quite beside the point --- is
another question entirely, but the expectations that we do in fact possess are
necessarily connected, arise out of, derive from, uniform sequences of events,
and are unintelligible apart from them as the necessary condition of the
formation of expectations. There is, in short, no other way that expectations
are formed; they are necessarily derived from consistent and uniform sequences
of events and cannot be understood apart from them.
Equally
important, I suggest, is that the argument --- essentially the Problem of
Induction itself--- is subreptive upon its own terms. It indicts what it holds
to be a circular argument upon circular terms. It arrives,
pseudo-syllogistically at a conclusion from, but in violation of, its own
premises. What do I mean by this? Quite simply this: to hold that we have no
logical warrant to posit a necessary connection between what
now appear to be two discrete and unrelated events (say the occurrence of
B invariably following each and every occurrence of A with no
disqualifying instance) because we have hitherto been unable to discover
such a connection --- is to make the subreptive leap to the very proposition
which the argument holds to be untenable: that the future will conform with the
past: in other words, because we have not been able to establish a
necessary connection up to this point in time, does not warrant the conclusion
that we will not be able to establish such a connection in the future. Yes,
nothing in the way of contradiction results if we hold that B will not
immediately follow the occurrence of A simply because it always and
without exception has. But by that same token, nothing in the way of
contradiction results if we affirm that what we have been unable to establish
today, we will be able to establish tomorrow. Upon what basis can we maintain
that the argument (to wit, against causality) which now holds today, will hold
tomorrow? Inevitably, ineluctably, we invoke the same premises, adduce the same
terms that the argument has already repudiated. In the end, we can make no
claims whatever, logical or otherwise, upon the terms invoked by the Problem of
Induction, not even the problematic posed by the pseudo-problem
itself.
It would appear that both
Russell and Hume have made something more in the way of a psychological
observation than an epistemological claim, and if this in fact is the case then
their argument is of little interest to us from a purely epistemological point
of view. Their argument essentially appears to be more along the lines of
operant conditioning than epistemological analysis: in effect, they appear to
be conflating two entirely separate issues: our conditioning to
observed uniformities, which is a psychological claim, with our inability to
discover necessity between expectations and the events that precipitate them, an
epistemological claim which in the end, I argue, is a mistaken claim. What they
really seem to be talking about is, fundamentally, the provenance of certain
types of belief. And this, in the end, is all that the skeptic is left
with if nothing whatever in the way of necessity obtains in our experiences. But
I am not persuaded that this is the case relative to all our experiences, and I
suggest that it very clearly is not the case relative to mysticism in
particular. The point from which we had departed in this rather
long, but I think necessary, aside is this: the pronouncements of science,
widely accepted as paradigms of reason, are ineluctably subverted by the problem
of induction, and as a result, the type of deductive certainty toward which it
strives, it cannot attain.
We had further argued
that as a consequence of this disability, reason of this deductive type finds a
more consistent paradigm in the metaphysics of mysticism than in the physics of
science, and essentially for this reason: within the phenomenology of mysticism,
there is no way of stating without contradiction that, for example, subsequent
to the negation of time, temporal experiences may nevertheless follow. To
presuppose the negation of time as the condition to a certain type of
experience is to be able to assert not simply with certainty, but with
deductive certainty that, whatever subsequent experience will be, it will
not be temporal. In other words, as metaphysical logic, the via negativa
binds it premises to its conclusions with a deductive certainty that is clearly
analytical in nature. As an existential principle --- a condition --- it also
connects certain types of experience mystical in nature, to certain other types
of experience negative in nature which the former presupposes. In either case
the conclusions are understood to be implied in the premises, and as such, to
deductively follow from them. The mystic, therefore, can appeal to the type of
certainty to which the physicist cannot --- but it is a certainty only
negatively descriptive in nature and will yield no knowledge whatever of what
subsequent experiences will be; only what they will not be. And
while the scope of this knowledge is confined to negative assertions, they are
at least deductively certain relative to the nature of future experiences --- an
assertion to which no law of physics can lay claim. And the deductive nature of
this certainty itself , I suggest, coupled with the testimony --- together with
the consistency, uniformity, and agreement with reason that we had examined
earlier --- puts the burden of proof not on the mystic, but the burden of
disproof on the skeptic.
There remain problems of
another type, however, which must be discussed before concluding our analysis;
problems relating to the authenticity of the mystical experience in light of
several of the more significant objections commonly brought to bear against it.
In attempting to substantiate the mystic’s claim upon reality, if we find that
the criteria to which we appeal is conceded to substantiate other types of
experience as genuine, and not illusory --- if this same criteria, in other
words, holds true for the mystic’s claim as well, then at the very least the
probable authenticity of the mystical experience must be conceded also. In the
following prolepsis, then, we will consider some of these objections which, if a
coherent epistemological account of mysticism is to be achieved, must ultimately
be answered.
1 This, of
course, is the Problem of Induction forcefully stated by the skeptic David Hume
in his Treatise of Human Nature (Bk. I, Part III, Sec.
1-6).
2 Immanuel Kant,
“Transcendental Doctrine of Elements, First Part, Transcendental
Aesthetic,” Critique Of Pure Reason, translated by Norman Kemp Smith
(New York, NY: St. Martin’s Press, 1965), 67 A 22.
3 op. cit. B
39
4 Bertrand
Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1978), pgs.
64-65
5
op.cit.
(continued
below)
Part III
Objections to the Mystical
Thesis
The Plight of the Mystic and the Occasion of
Animus
It is inevitable that the claims of the mystic, even within
the very ecclesiastical community through which his aspirations had been
nurtured, will often be met by reproach, disdain, and hostility. True sanctity
--- the most fundamental prerequisite too union with God conceived as Most Holy
--- has seldom been greeted by less. Andd if there is one unerring mark of the
authentic mystic, it is indubitable sanctity. The mystic is set apart. As
everything deemed holy, he is understood as set apart not merely for God --- but
by God. This simple observation alone, I think, suffices to explain a
good deal of the hostility with which the mystic has historically been greeted.
We are, by and large, indefeasibly democratic in nature, and when this sense of
democracy has been violated, our response, to a greater or lesser degree, has
been similar to that of Cain before God’s predilection for Abel, expressing
itself in hostility in having been disfranchised. We are indignant that
prerogative, access, has been accorded another, while it has been denied to us.
This appears to hold equally true for wealth, power, and knowledge --- in fact,
for the possession of anything from which we feel ourselves arbitrarily
excluded. Anything
whatever, exclusive in
nature, is repugnant to our ingrained democratic sensibilities. In a larger
sense, it is the same animosity, but on a much grander scale, encountered by the
Church in maintaining Herself to be the indispensable means to salvation. No one
likes being left out in the cold, understood either as outer darkness or
invincible ignorance --- especially when it is through no fault of their own.
The perspective enjoyed by the mystic --- or, for that matter, the physicist ---
from which one is excluded either by predilection or aptitude, is at least as
likely to arouse resentment as to stir admiration. The question, in the end,
inevitably becomes this: why this man and not another? Or more often than not,
why him, and not me? And this, I think, is simply a candid
assessment of human nature.
And then there is, of
course, the discredit, even disrepute, into which mysticism has occasionally
been brought by individuals uttering the most abhorrent and remarkable nonsense
that in one way or another had come to be mistakenly associated with mysticism,
but which really belong within the phenomenology of occultism, such as thought
transference, metempsychosis and the like. I think that the problem, in large
part, is due to the name which lends itself to such wide abuse, and for
this reason should probably be dropped entirely and replaced with something much
less general and altogether more specific. Too much in the way of undeserved but
nevertheless common association with altogether discreditable notions accompany
the term “mystic”, and I suggest that the term “infused contemplation”, which
St. John frequently uses (he seldom uses the word “mystic”, and never
“mysticism”) would be much more appropriate to the purpose. I think it entirely
likely that a mystic would blench at being called a mystic, and would more
probably consider himself a contemplative if he were forced to consider the
point.
What we are really
considering, then, is the larger problem of the broad and often indiscriminate
interpretation applied to what is essentially a clearly defined phenomena
concerning man’s relation to Absolute Being in the person of God. Nor is the
problem confined to those who have merely a superficial understanding of the
subject. William James, for example, includes in his understanding of mysticism
“voices and visions and leadings and missions,” 1 no less than the noted skeptic Bertrand Russell who
apparently includes in his own understanding of the subject, visions of angels
and saints.2 I suggest, however, that such visions and the like are
“mystical” in another and more ordinary sense, and really do not compel our
interest insofar as a coherent mystical epistemology is
concerned.
This regrettable
tendency, I think, results not simply from too broad an application of the term
which suggests a fundamental misconception about the nature of authentic
mystical experiences. It also appears to follow from an impulse to subsume too
disparate an array of mystical interpretations under a single rubric and one
general accounting. Mysticism --- at least of the Christian variety with which
we are dealing --- however, does not readily lend itself to this rather facile
subsumption. While most varieties of mystical experience undeniably share
certain common features --- which itself implicates something universal that in
turn suggests something authentic about this experience that cuts across
cultural and phenomenological lines --- the disparities within the several
accounts are often too metaphysically inconsistent, if not contradictory, to be
ignored. Quite obviously, certain of these accounts, for example, narcotically
induced states of so-called mystical awareness, demonstrate less logical and
metaphysical coherence than others; and the account which equates visions
invested with apparent corporeity with mystical experiences quite clearly
conflicts with another account of the type described by St. John which
explicitly suppresses such experiences as not pertaining by definition to the
nature of mystical experience at all.
It is, then, patently
impossible to ascribe equal validity to competing interpretations without at
once becoming involved in numerous logical contradictions. We cannot hold, for
example, that the mystical experience is sensuously embodied on the one hand,
and at the same time maintain that it is explicitly non-sensuous on the other.
Both assertions clearly cannot be true in any univocal sense. And as the
criteria to which we appeal in our effort to categorize these essentially
dissimilar experiences become increasingly general, they eventually reach the
point at which they become altogether meaningless. How, then, do we set about
distinguishing between authentic mystical experiences, and other experiences
which are held to share similar features but which derive from entirely
dissimilar sources, such as those observed in the dysperceptive reflexivity of
pathological psychosis, or narcotically-induced states of pseudo-mystical
awareness?
Before beginning to
answer this question, it is necessary to avoid some confusion at the outset by
agreeing upon a clear, if concise, definition of our understanding of mystical
union, and I think that the following will be adequate to our purposes while
remaining consistent with the text. By mystical union, St. John understands the
direct, immediate, and intuitive participation of the finite and created being
of the soul in the infinite and uncreated being of God. And while there are a
wide variety of objections to an equally wide variety of interpretations, some
more cogent than others, only those objections that have a direct bearing upon
our understanding of St. John’s mystical thesis will be considered. This
approach, I believe, will serve us in several ways: first and foremost it
provides us with a reasonably clear index of the types of objections to which
Christian mysticism is legitimately subject through a critical assessment of its
actual premises, and not those commonly but mistakenly associated with it
through its subreptive incorporation into essentially unrelated and incompatible
systems. And in so doing, it will at once provide the focus necessary to
systematically address problematic issues and legitimate criticisms specific to
St. John’s account without the need to contend with issues only incidental to
our strictly epistemological purview. Such an approach, at the same time,
equally serves to eliminate a surprising number of objections which more
properly address interpretations of experiences construed as mystical and which
deny, for example, the reality of space, time, matter, and personality --- a
denial in which St. John has no part.
Ite ad fontis
While the queue of
contemporary philosophers and epistemologists --- considered as either skeptical
or antagonistic to the mystical doctrine --- is long and distinguished, each
representative nevertheless appears, in one form or another, to
either further articulate or simply reformulate the
principle and most cogent objections to mysticism already embodied in the
writings of whom I consider to be the two greatest luminaries in this field:
Bertrand Russell and William James. Every other contemporary critic,
albeit providing valuable, if ancillary, insight, pales before the contribution
of these two exemplary thinkers. In scope, insight, perspicacity, and clarity,
their analyses to this day stand unrivalled.
The first type of
objection which we encounter is rather concisely, if sardonically, stated by
Bertrand Russell in the seventh chapter of his treatise on Religion and
Science. Here Russell argues the following:
“From a scientific point of view we can
make no distinction between the man who eats little and sees heaven, and the man
who drinks much and sees snakes. Each is an abnormal physical condition, and
therefore has abnormal perceptions.”
Let us look at this
argument a little more closely. Russell contends that what pass for mystical
experiences are directly induced (caused) by presumed physiochemical changes,
characteristically morbid in nature, that attend (result from, are incurred by)
specific forms of behavior, and that this experience, which is fundamentally
symptomatic, is particularly manifested through physical privation. By this
interpretation, then, mystical experience is essentially pathological in nature.
Consequently, we can dismiss the phenomena as a purely physiological issue as
quickly remedied by, as it is answerable in terms of, mere biochemistry or
psychophysics. The problem with this argument, however, is that it simply is not
the case, for example, that millions of people suffering involuntary privation
of this sort throughout the world, and greater privation still, overwhelm us
with reports of experiences of a mystical nature. I think it extremely unlikely
that there is any genuinely scientific data to substantiate the claim that
undernourished people are more likely to have ecstatic experiences as a result
of malnutrition, than people who are well-nourished, or that any statistical
analysis will prove it. Simply from the point of view of probability, the
preponderance of evidence suggests otherwise.
The argument, then, that
abnormal physical conditions cause abnormal perceptions, although not entirely
spurious in the most obvious sense, is nevertheless largely deceptive. If I have
a fever I may indeed hallucinate, but when the fever has subsided I recognize
the absurd nature of my perceptions; I do not set about attempting to construct
a metaphysics around this clearly recognized pathological experience. Fasting,
moreover --- and this is unmistakably the point to which Russell adverts --- is
neither held to be necessary to, nor is it an explicit protocol of, Christian
mysticism per se. Surely it is a discipline within the Church, and has been from
time immemorial, but most Christians under this obligation are, I suggest, more
likely to experience hunger than ecstasy. Nor is there any evidence to suggest
that St. John, or for that matter St. Teresa, Eckhart, Tauler, Suso or van
Ruysbroeck were anything but healthy, active, and productive individuals for the
greater part of their lives, experiencing as much or as little in the way of
abnormal conditions as any of their contemporaries, especially within the
religious communities themselves where the discipline was equally exercised. In
short, any statistical evidence, if indeed there is any, appealing to pathology
upon which a disqualification of mysticism is held to rest can be equally
applied to a given population at large and will subsequently yield quite
different and essentially contradictory results.
But more apropos of this
type of objection are statements to be found within the text itself Even a
cursory reading reveals St. John himself to be extremely skeptical about most
reports of mystical experience, and most especially as they relate to embodied
visions and the like. 3 But more importantly, we must recall that St. John insists
that the majority of those who have gone through the preliminary stages to
mystical union --- never in fact achieve it. 4 And the reason that they do not, we will remember, was
outlined by St. John earlier in his ascribing the cause of this experience to
God alone.
5 In other words, the type of
causality to which Russell appeals, and from which he elsewhere prescinds
entirely --- any irony in itself --- is signally absent. And more compelling
still, I think, is the fact that, with one or two very minor exceptions, the
privation and poverty of which St. John speaks as necessary to the state of
infused contemplation, are exclusively spiritual in nature. Nowhere do we
find emphasis upon the physical aspects of asceticism in the writings of
St. John who, at one point, tersely states that “all extremes are vicious”
6. The type of argument, then, that would attempt to
establish a causal relation between supposed pathological conditions and
mystical states is clearly inconsistent both with the evidence at large and the
premises of mysticism in particular.
If the mystical
experience cannot be adequately accounted for pathologically, then perhaps its
origin can be found elsewhere, specifically in a disordered state of the mind,
and there are indeed those who maintain that a similarity exists between certain
forms of delusional psychoses and mystical states of consciousness which
indicate a common psychological ground in reference to which, like psychoses,
mystical experiences are susceptible of explanation. This argument, of course,
is a somewhat more sophisticated variation of the first argument we examined if,
as some contemporary schools of thought maintain, psychological disorders are
physiochemical in nature. In either event the objection remains essentially the
same. Mystical experience and pathological psychoses are different in kind, but
similar in nature. Fairly representative of this line of thought is William
James who argues the following:
“... religious mysticism is only one half
of mysticism. The other half has no accumulated traditions except those which
the textbooks on insanity supply. Open any one of these and you will find
abundant cases in which mystical ideas are cited as characteristic symptoms of
enfeebled or deluded states of mind. In delusional insanity, paranoia, as they
sometimes call it, we may have a diabolical mysticism, a sort of religious
mysticism turned upside down. The same sense of ineffable importance in the
smallest events ... the same controlling by extraneous powers, only this time
the emotion is pessimistic: instead of consolations, we have desolations; the
meanings are dreadful, point of view of their psychological mechanism, that
classical mysticism, and these lower mysticisms spring from the same mental
level, from that great subliminal or transmarginal region of which science is
beginning to admit the existence, but of which so little is really known. That
religion contains every kind of matter: ‘seraph and snake’ abide there side by
side.” 7
Mysticism as Aberration. A Clinical
Objection
What are we to make of
this argument? First of all, it seems to me that it is not at all clear just
what James is arguing here. Is it that certain aspects of mysticism are
analogous to certain aspects of pathological psychoses? Certainly no analogy
obtains between the content of such experiences, for on this point he is
quite clear that the two are not just dissimilar, but essentially diametrical.
James, however, has failed to elaborate the point sufficiently, and it is
precisely on this elaboration that our contention rests. The one, we have seen,
is an experience of escalating unity, increasing coherence, within the universe
of perception; the other of amplified disunity, dyscontextuality, and
incoherence. For the contemplative, the universe of experiences gradually
unfolds itself, reveals itself, as a providentially ordered and harmonious
cosmos. Perfect ontological syntony, as it were, discloses itself among the
infinitude of existents; opposition yields to complementarity, plurality to
unicity --- in short, the universe unveils itself to the mystic as infinitely
coherent. On the other hand, within the solipsistic ambits of psychoses we find
quite the converse to be true: the involuted world of experience is apprehended
as incommensurable chaos; ordinarily lucid connections fail to obtain between
rhapsodic and isolated perceptions. Experience is characteristically
recalcitrant to order, syntony yields to opposition, coherence to incoherence.
And where the mystic’s experiences are interpretable in terms of movement toward
a coherent objective --- and are in fact seen to correspond with a systematic
and rational metaphysics --- there is no end, no goal, no objective toward which
the psychotic strives, or in light of which his behavior becomes subsequently
intelligible. There is no discernible purpose toward which these apparently
discrete or parenthetical states of mind are directed and in light of which his
experiences become susceptible of interpretation beyond the abbreviated
experience of the moment. Any meaningful notion of intentionality within a
context at large vanishes amid the pure spontaneity of apparently discontinuous
perceptions, and all correspondence to any coherent standard of what is
presumably real breaks down, disintegrates, in a reflexively constructed
dysreality.
Perhaps, then, in arguing
that mysticism and psychoses “spring from the same mental level”, James is
suggesting that they are analogous in that the two experiences share in
fundamentally identical categories? But neither is this the case, for we have
seen that the mystic’s experience is consistently --- and quite necessarily ---
outside the categories of space, time, and radical individuation. On the other
hand, whatever the psychotic perceives, however distorted and incoherent the
context, he necessarily perceives as invested with spatial and temporal
characteristics, and for this reason: the confusion encountered in this
apparently rhapsodic type of consciousness presupposes a clearly defined
chronology of erratically indexed perceptions. In other words, the confusion and
incoherence which psychology understands as diagnostic of psychosis could not
occur outside of a temporal matrix within which alone a sequence of disordered
perceptions is possible. However disorganized, there is a temporal priority of
one experience to another. Moreover, inasmuch as hallucinatory aspects of these
perceptions, ordered in time, are typically embodied as discrete forms, and so
are individuated one from another, such experiences are inescapably spatial in
nature. Were they not spatially individuated, there would be no discrete
perceptions for time to index, and consequently there would be no confusion. It
is not merely a matter of psychological, or even pathological interpretation of
experiences of a kind, as James suggests, for the categories involved in
the types of these experiences are radically dissimilar. And the point is
that they are dissimilar not from a psychological point of view
concerning the way that the mind organizes, or fails to coherently organize, the
data brought to bear upon it; still less from a pathological perspective as
causative --- but from a metaphysical perspective. It is not so much a
different subjective response to essentially identical data, but to data
altogether different; data which are outside the possibility of empirical or
psychological acquaintance simply because these acquaintances are universally
and necessarily defined in terms of time and space. In short, because an
individual is psychotic does not exempt him from the conditions governing
perceptions in general--- irrespective of whether these perceptions are
hallucinatory or not.
These rather general
observations, however, fail to make an assessment of perhaps the most
significant feature to be invoked in distinguishing between these essentially
dissimilar experiences: the notion of volition. In his argument, James
adverts to what he sees as “the controlling by extraneous powers” to which
mystic and psychotic are subject alike. But we must argue in turn that while it
is true that the mystic exercises no positive control over the mystical
experience --- a point upon which St. John is very clear --- in the sense that
he is unable to occasion, effect, this type of experience into which he is
cooperatively inducted, it is equally true that these experiences are, at any
moment of his choosing, negatively susceptible to his volition. That is to say,
by a simple act of will --- for the contemplative is never deprived of his
freedom --- a turning from God, the mystic may withdraw from the mystical state
and terminate the experience at will, although all evidence suggests that he
would be strongly disinclined to do so.
8
But disinclination and
inability are two quite different things. And this is to say that while mystical
consciousness is not voluntarily attained, neither is it involuntarily imposed.
The autonomy of the will is never subverted in ecstatic union. We may discern a
coincidence of wills --- the soul’s and God’s --- to such a degree that the will
of the soul is, as St. John had stated earlier, indistinguishable from the will
of God, but it nevertheless remains a freely appropriated correspondence
of wills. And this means that the experience, while not solely accessible
through the will alone, is an experience preeminently conditioned by will.
Psychotic states, on the other hand, are experiences over which the psychotic
exercises no control whatever, either positive or negative. He presumably
neither wills to induce them, nor to suspend them. He is not free to extricate,
to exempt himself from the conditions to which he finds himself subject. He may
not choose not to engage in these chaotic states of mind, or to resume at
will that integrated state of consciousness associated with a sound mind.
Nothing of the pathology of psychosis suggests that the condition lies even
marginally within the province of the will. Here indeed there is a “controlling”
of the sort that James describes, a controlling in the most rigorous sense
through biochemical factors that appear to effectively preclude the meaningful
exercise of the will relative to these states.
But let us consider this
objection further. Perhaps it may be argued that the sufferings which the
soul typically endures prior to union, and which, we had suggested
earlier, derive not from a lack of orientation to, but from the complete absence
of, every reference to the phenomenal world at large, are in fact similar to
those encountered in psychoses in that both are a suffering resulting from the
absence of ordinary frames of reference. In other words, these two experiences
are identical in certain respects specifically related to suffering and
perceptual orientation and therefore have at least a common psychological ground
inasmuch as the suffering is causally related to conditions of perceptual
reference. This objection, however, becomes decidedly less tenable when we
consider that for the mystic, the dark night of the soul, unlike the cognitive
chaos typical in psychosis, has a constant and coherent frame of reference: God.
However dark the night that eclipses sensibility and reason, together with every
ordinary frame of reference, the intentionality of the mystic remains
singularly intact. He is always cognitively oriented toward and intensely
focused upon a consistent and coherent end in the Person of God; an end first
acquired and subsequently maintained through what St. John calls the infused
theological virtue of faith. This coherent, almost teleological orientation
suggests that the mystical experience is too susceptible of purpose, accords too
closely, almost seamlessly with widely recognized theological canons, and
remains too much in the domain of the will, to allow for anything but the most
casual correspondence with psychotic states of the type to which James and
others would advert in dismissing the phenomenon. In addressing the problem of
suffering, we might better understand the apotheosized contemplative as, in a
sense, a victim of his own sacrifice, for in one of the typical paradoxes of
mysticism we find that in the prelude to ecstatic union the suffering of the
mystic is palliated by the very virtue through which it is embraced.
9
Given disparities of this
sort which cannot be objectively overlooked, it becomes increasingly difficult
to understand the analogy which James attempts to draw between two types of
experience that in fact become increasingly dissimilar the more closely we
examine them. If this type of argument concludes to an assertion of identity
(mysticism is form of psychosis) based upon the observation that the two
experiences simply appear to invest ordinary perception with certain
extraordinary features, albeit radically dissimilar in kind and nature, then the
analogy, I suggest, would appear to hold equally well between
narcotically-induced states of awareness and mysticism. But this analogy, in the
end, is simply a variation of Russell’s earlier argument; an argument in which
we had been unable to adduce any compelling evidence to substantiate precisely
this type of claim; a claim suggesting that psychological states causally
related to physical stimuli are equally explanatory of ecstatic union.
Ironically, the more appropriate analogy may in fact be between this type of
narcotically-induced consciousness and psychosis of the sort adduced by James.
For here we find a strikingly similar inventory of evidence in the way of
altered consciousness and disrupted cognitive processes, the re-composition of
space and time accompanied by perceptual disorientation and the complete
interpretive restructuring which James mistakenly sees as typifying both
mystical and psychotic experiences. But unlike the relationship between
psychosis and mystical experience, here a common ground is clearly
distinguishable, and widely recognized, between psychotic states of mind and
narcotically altered consciousness inasmuch as both are seen as resulting from,
and are therefore explicable in terms of, biochemistry; the one disorder
apparently spontaneous in nature, the other narcotically induced. In either
event the cause and the effect are held to be identical in both cases. No such
observable nexus, however, links the mystic to his experiences. And this brings
us to what I think is an extremely interesting question relative to this entire
line of reasoning, and it is simply this: why, relative to a discussion on
mysticism, was the analogy from psychosis chosen over an analogy from narcosis,
when the latter would appear to have served the purpose equally
well?
The answer to this
question, I think, is particularly illuminating. In the former analogy James
could at least plausibly argue that the mystical experience is essentially
explainable solely in terms of biophysics and without reference to anything
extrinsic; a biological isolation within which alone his interpretation
will hold, and which effectively excludes any other principle of causation. Any
appeal to Divine causation, then, becomes not superfluous, but entirely
unnecessary. Using the analogy from psychosis is clearly more congenial to
James’s purposes: the mystical experience is more readily dismissed, together
with God, if it can be shown that no appeal to a cause outside of man is
necessary in order to explain it, and this is perfectly true --- but the problem
is that James’s argument does not offer this proof. He has not demonstrated that
these experiences derive from a common source, merely that they are
superficially related through the fact that ordinary perceptions sometimes
acquire extraordinary features, which is clearly as answerable in terms of
narcotics as clinical psychosis. James’s type of argument in a nutshell
is this: change the biochemistry and you change the perceptions. But arguments
of this type adduce no evidence whatever of biological alteration diagnosable in
mystics. Moreover, were such evidence produced; even were it proven that the
biochemical makeup of mystics is similar or even identical to that of
psychotics, this still would not prove the point, for it still fails to account
for the radical dissimilarities between these two experiences and the still
coherent orientation of the mystic toward an objective as clearly maintained to
exist within the experience itself as outside of
it.
Mysticism as Constitutive
The type of argument
exemplified by James might well be called a theory of psycho-mystical immanence,
for James essentially attempts to understand the mystical experience as somehow
immanent, albeit latent, within consciousness itself. Given the necessary
protocols, the types of experiences associated with mystical states can be
induced: ecstasy is elicitable within consciousness. If we ascribe to this
theory, however, we confront several significant problems at once. An adequate
understanding of the concepts, especially the metaphysical presuppositions
involved in Christian mysticism, make this extremely problematic for those
ascribing to this theory. First of all, it must be demonstrated that the mind
contains certain data in the form of a priori intuitions that are
very specific to this to this type of experience, particularly those relating to
the transcendence of time, space, and finitude; intuitions which could not, in
any event, be empirically derived from experience since all experience
necessarily presumes them. But what the mind possesses a priori is
necessarily understood in formal and not empirical terms: we speak of them as
rational concepts, not empirical percepts. But mysticism, we have seen, if
nothing else, is fundamentally an experience, an intuition; and while we
can meaningfully argue for the a priority of certain rational
concepts, we cannot without contradiction argue for the a priority of
empirical percepts, for to do so is to argue that we possess certain experiences
prior to experience, which is absurd. Any theory, in a larger sense, that would
hold certain experiences to be immanent or innate, awaiting, as it were, the
proper conditions to actualize them or to stimulate them from latency, has
failed to grasp the immediacy of experience as such. It is unintelligible,
because it is contradictory, to argue that we are innately possessed of certain
experiences which are not immediately experienced, for in what sense is
an experience one that is not experienced? I can argue that I possess the
recollection of the experience of “hot”, but I cannot argue that I
possess the experience “hot” even though I do not presently experience it. To
further contend that under the proper stimulus I would reacquire this experience
which is latent within me is to have missed the point of the immediacy of
experience altogether. The only stimulus adequate to this immediacy is a renewal
of the experience itself.
Let us take a different
tack, and for the moment hold the entire question of the provenance of such data
in consciousness in a kind of methodological suspension. Let us merely assume
the point as proven. What would follow from it? What are the logical
implications? Well, to begin with (and prescinding entirely from the question of
what legitimately constitutes data per se) the data must, first of all,
exist prior to experience: since such data are absolutely incommensurable with
experience, they cannot derive from it. Such data, then, must be innate. But
they are not innate in the way that, say, Plato held our acquaintance with forms
to be innate, such that our empirical acquaintance with particularized instances
of this form stimulates a recollection of the true form, epistemologically
latent, of which the particular is recognized to be only an impoverished
representation, a form, in Plato’s case, that we possess and had acquired, say,
through an ante-natal existence. And while the critique of mysticism that we are
presently examining would appear to explain mystical experiences much in the way
that Plato endeavored to explain our acquaintance with forms --- by maintaining
them to be innate --- the similarity between the two accounts is too superficial
to be exploited. The fact of the matter is that the data we encounter within the
mystical experience are entirely unique: they are not mere concepts much as
Descartes famous chiliagon;10 still less the formal protocols of reason we find in the
canons of logic. They are, rather, irreducible experiences; sheer intuitions
with which the mystic is immediately acquainted. The question, then, remaining
to be answered, is this: in what possible sense can an experience be
understood to be innate or implicit?
As we had argued earlier,
to speak of becoming conscious of an experience is absurd. An experience
is a conscious perception. To put it another way, if we understand
experiences to be coterminous with consciousness, such that the notion of an
unconscious experience is essentially unintelligible and meaningless, how can we
hold ourselves to possess experiences of which we are not simultaneously
conscious? It would appear to be equally clear that we do not experience
the laws of logic; we comprehend them. Nor do we, in any Cartesian sense,
experience a chiliagon; we conceptualize it. But these mystical data, we have
argued, are neither logical functions nor capable of conceptualization: they are
experiences, like any other kind of experience, mystical or not, to which
we cannot ascribe the notion of a priority without contradiction. James’s
type of argument in one respect, and Russell’s in another, draw illegitimate
conclusions from basically defective premises; premises which I suggest are
based upon a subreptive association between fundamentally dissimilar
experiences. Both, in the end, are too quick to explain the phenomenon of
mysticism by an appeal to superficialities.
The Real Contributions of Russell and
James
While the types of
arguments exemplified by Russell and James fall short of their purpose, it would
be an error, I believe, to dismiss their general perspective altogether. And
while I am not prepared to grant an inherent disposition on the part of the soul
to certain states of quasi-mystical awareness --- certainly not within the terms
outlined by either --- I do not think it is entirely unprofitable to consider
some states of awareness to be suggestive of, and in a sense an empirical
testimony to, the inherent limitations of reason, and more importantly, to the
possibility of alternative modes of cognition. One paradigm which readily comes
to mind concerns that state of consciousness we call dreaming. To wit, in
dreams it is not uncommon to find ourselves quite suddenly and forcefully
illuminated to some obscure connection between the most remote and
erstwhile unrelated
events, such that we are likely to say with the most profound conviction born of
a truth that has suddenly been thrust upon us, “Aha, so that is the
nature of such and such!”, or “So that is the connection!” And while the
wording, obviously, may be different, the sense remains the same. A single
object or concept, or perhaps the relation between several, suddenly assumes
manifold aspects; a previously unknown dimension, a newly revealed facet,
emerges in light of which the relation we perceive is changed instantly and
dramatically, unfolding before us as something invincibly true. Connections
become marvelously translucent and strike us with the inexorable force of
revelation in light of which our previous understanding
palls.
These connections,
however, these insights, gradually evanesce as we recede from this state of
subliminal intuition and as reason gradually, inexorably reasserts itself in
waking consciousness. The more that reason becomes explicit, operative---the
more it supplants intuition --- the less able we are to grasp these erstwhile
lucid connections until at last they disappear entirely and reason is left with
the awkward conjunction of apparently incongruous, irrelevant, or irreconcilable
ideas. Yet often, despite the verdict of reason which pronounces these relations
absurd, we are left with an unmistakable feeling of an experience of certitude
often more compelling than reason ever delivered us. We are left, momentarily,
with a firm conviction in the unity of reality; with the impression that there
are not so much alternative, as complementary categories to be discerned within
reality. And in a larger sense I think that our perception of reality is
enriched by these dreams: we are persuaded that a real and fundamental stratum
of unity is at least possible beneath the equally real surface phenomena
of plurality and distinction which reason critically divides and apportions to
us. That somehow, perhaps, these connections are not entirely chimerical, were
we to discover a cognitive faculty superior to reason and through which this
iridescent reticulation of perceptions would once again become accessible to
us.
However appealing such an
alternate might be to consider and while, much like Russell and James, we might
be initially persuaded to follow this tenuous skein of evidence to the end of
the strand at which point it passes completely through our grasp to no good end,
we must, in our pursuit of coherence, be ingenuous enough to come to frank terms
with the phenomena from the outset. Dream states are, with few exceptions,
characteristically lacking in overall contextuality: in most dreams, no
perduring frame of reference consistently orients the dreamer throughout his
dream-experiences---indeed, were this not the case, it would be impossible to
distinguish between ordinary and somnolent states of consciousness. And it is
precisely this incoherence which essentially has no analogue in mysticism. While
it is true, as we have already said, that the sufferings which the soul endures
throughout the dark night prior to union effectively stem from the absence of
ordinary frames of reference, it nevertheless remains equally true, despite this
fact, that such experiences are not experiences of incoherence, but of
negation. The dark night prior to mystical union is not an incoherence
among experiences, but an absence of specific types of experience.
Indeed, subsequent to union, these experiences, we find, are transformed into
experiences of a markedly coherent and unified nature.
Dreams, unlike mystical
states, moreover, are not characteristically ineffable. The difficulty
encountered in describing some dreams --- by far not all dreams ---
derives not from any intrinsic incommensurability between the perceived
experience and waking reality, but rather, from the attempt to impose contextual
coherence upon essentially incoherent experiences. It is, I think, equally clear
that dreams invariably contain, instantiate, simply the elements of ordinarily
experienced perceptions, however bizarrely arranged, superimposed, and
synthetized. Dreams, in other words, are not perceptions of an extraordinary or
transcendent reality, but of ordinary reality reflexively projected in
unsystematic consciousness; a somnolent consciousness upon which reason
exercises only marginal influence. Lastly, of course, but perhaps most apropos
of the point, dreams, however extraordinary, are, one and all, perceptions
invested with spatio-temporal features. The similarities, then, which we might
otherwise impulsively seize upon to prove a relationship between these
essentially unlike experiences, are, as their predecessors were in the arguments
of Russell and James, at best superficial only. They do, however, suggest
something valuable no less: that reason may in fact not be the exclusive arbiter
of every type of experience.
Metaphysical Objections
Another and more serious
objection yet remains to be considered from an entirely different perspective
which, unlike the objections we have previously addressed, questions not the
psychology, but the metaphysics itself upon which the mystical thesis stands.
And because it is a metaphysical objection to a fundamentally metaphysical
issue, it is on this account by far the more potentially discrediting, for in
questioning certain ontological features of the mystical experience, it calls
into question the very credibility of the metaphysics of mysticism itself. The
argument may be formulated as follows:
Given not the relative,
but the absolute ontological otherness of this purported mystical
dimension, how can such a reality not simply relate to experience in general,
but be held to structure experiences with which it is understood to be
totally incommensurate? In other words, given the acknowledged categorical
opposition in ontology, how is it possible for these not merely apparent, but
real, contradictions to be sublated in a mystical and metaphysical
unity?
The essentially monistic
aspect of mysticism is clearly problematic by this account, for mystical
experiences are invariably experiences of unity; a unity, as we had seen, in
which opposition is not so much abolished as reconciled, and in which dogmatic
individuation yields to the attenuated distinction implied in the notion of
participation. The difficulty arises when the principle of reconciliation, the
unifying, structuring element in this experience, is not only incommensurable
with, but in fact is held to be in ontological opposition to, its counterpart in
ordinary experience. In short, it is totally other. What can the nature
of this principle possibly be such that it structures and unifies that of which
it is essentially the antithesis? If indeed it can structure the universe
of experience, then it must in some way be related to the world at large. But as
St. John has forcefully argued, it is not related to the world, neither
formally nor materially.11 How, then, are we to answer this?
To begin with, it is, I
suggest, equally clear that despite this apparent contradiction there is
a connection --- for the two dimensions are in fact experienced as
structured and unified in the mystical experience; an experience, moreover, that
has shown itself to be extremely recalcitrant to being proved illusory. This
point was well illustrated in the case of explanations that would summarily
dismiss the authenticity of the mystical experience through theories of
psycho-mystical immanence. In fact, the psychological models we explored failed
to adequately account for the most significant features of the mystical
experience precisely because they mistakenly interpreted the phenomenon in terms
of immanence; an immanence which could make no account, not merely of an
implied disproportion among specific types of experience, but of a clearly
perceived and experienced incommensurability between them. And this
contradiction--- which is central to the problem --- is, I suggest, only capable
of being resolved if a principle, not of immanence, but of transcendence
is assumed in the account. And the whole point is that this is precisely the
case with regard to Christian mysticism which posits God as a principle
ontologically assumed which not only comprehends the exhaustive plenitude of
reality, but is held to be the ground of its existence. 12
Given this universal
ontological presupposition --- that God is not merely the cause of every being,
but ontologically necessary to every being as such --- there is, despite
contrariety in nature and categorical polarity in essence, a necessary and
fundamental connection between the phenomenal world at large and the ens
realissimum of God which is encountered in mysticism. To put it in other
terms, there is a transcendent metaphysical nexus between God
13 and every aspect of reality (creation) --- which cannot
possibly obtain between man and reality. While we cannot argue for the
unqualified reconciliation of ontological opposites, 14 it nevertheless remains incontestable that the relation of
the one to the other is fundamentally and necessarily ontological if God is
posited as the ground of existence.15 And this ontic relation, we had seen in an earlier context,
derives from the notion of being-as-such: the primal, unqualified, and
unpredicated ontic state which is only commensurate with God as Being
Itself, in its being-only --- and not its being such-and-such.
However, once formal predicates are attached to this being-only, subsequent to
which it becomes informed as a being-such-and-such, then all commensurability
vanishes, for every ascribable predicate will be necessarily finite and stand in
opposition to the Infinite (God).
Even so, inasmuch as all
existents are primally possessed of being-only, some residual commensurability
remains, however remote, and an ontological connection is in fact discernible in
the account; the one, in other words, is understood to be coherently related to
the other. But while we have succeeded in establishing relation, we are still
left with the problem of incommensurability and opposition between
predicated-being --- the being-such-and-such understood in every existent beyond
its being-only --- and the infinite Being-in-Itself which is God. To complicate
matters further, we have argued that this opposition cannot be ontologically
reconciled --- but indeed, it need not be reconciled, for while these
experiences pertain to ontological categories reciprocally and necessarily
remote through opposition, they are at the same time experiences
transcendentally unified through what is essentially apotheosized consciousness;
the consciousness acquired in ecstatic union. It is a transcendental structuring
which does not alter, or encroach upon, the respective ontologies, but in which
infinite or apotheosized cognition is brought to bear upon finite existents. It
is a structuring that does not violate what is finite in ontology, but which
elicits infinite epistemological dimensions from it. And it does so, I suggest,
in the following way: while it remains a perception of a manifold in existence,
it is at the same time a perception of the transcendental unity of relations
that obtain between the manifold existents. And this is simply to restate what
we had suggested earlier: that the experience of the mystic is that of a
manifold not ontologically, but transcendentally unified. One in which the
apparent ontological isolation of each entity is not abolished, but transcended
through the epistemological disclosure of infinite relations obtaining between
--- and consequently unifying --- otherwwise isolated finite existents in a
mutually implicative manifold in which the perception of the part entails a
simultaneous perception of the whole to which it pertains. This perceived
relation then, since it cannot be predicated of any being in isolation, but
which obtains only between being, is, then, a transcendental relation
deriving its unity not from the manifold in which it is discerned, but from an
apotheosized apprehension of that manifold.
Extraordinary as this
state of affairs may be, it is not without its analogue in ordinary human
perception which is capable of eliciting limited, or finite, epistemological
relations from, and in so doing effectively unifying, otherwise discrete and
isolated ontological and conceptual elements. One conspicuous difference
remains, however: in mysticism, ontology is already totalized in
apotheosized consciousness through being transcendentally unified in an
intuitional noesis. The entire ontological spectrum is already apprehended, not
as unified ontologically, but as totalized epistemologically. And in point of
fact, most of the errors involved in the misinterpretation of the mystical
experience originate in a fundamental misunderstanding regarding this very
point. What is actually a transcendental unity experienced in mysticism is
mistakenly interpreted as ontological unity. It is not, however, the
ontological aspect of reality that is transformed --- such that the
perception of individuation and distinction perceived in the phenomenal order is
ultimately revealed to be illusory --- it is rather the cognitive faculty itself
that has been transformed, and through this transformation has been enabled to
simultaneously perceive the multiplicity of relations that obtain between, and
therefore mutually implicate, every instance of being, both created and
Uncreated, finite and infinite, temporal and eternal. It is, in a word, to
possess the mind of God. 16 It is, consequently, cognitive and perceptual
limitation which is transcended and abolished --- not real distinctions in
ontology. It is not the case that being is one, monistic, and ultimately,
essentially, unified; but rather that the sum of being, and being in every
instance, is capable of being totalized in a cognitive
apotheosis.
But this is merely one of
two levels of unity discernible within the mystical experience. As finite
and temporally-conditioned beings we are, of course. limited in our perception
of any given item in experience. Reason, on the one hand, constrained by time,
cannot simultaneously entertain the vast multiplicity of relations that
enter into any single object falling under its purview, while perception, on the
other hand, constrained by space, cannot simultaneously apprehend
the multiple facets circumscribing and defining any object acquired through
sensibility. And this means that the multidimensionality of being is never
simultaneously disclosed to us. In a sense, our access to being, to any being,
is dimensionally limited in the way that the geometer is limited to a plane. And
the consequence of this limitation is a certain opacity to being finitely
considered: from one standpoint certain relations and dimensions obtain which
are not accessible from another and as a result, our perception, our knowledge,
our understanding of being is characteristically and necessarily
incomplete.
The Cubist and the Mystic: a Common Agendum on
Limitation
Within the mystical
experience, on the other hand, finitude and limitation are transcended and
cognition is no longer subject to these limitations, for it is no longer
constrained by time and space. Our best analogy, I think, comes from art, and is
that offered by certain Cubists who had the perspicacity to recognize these
fundamentally spatial constraints inherent in perception and the artistic
ingenuity to redefine them. Our first impression upon viewing the cubist’s
rendering of his subject is that of formal chaos. The subject presented to our
consideration is unlike anything that our ordinary perception would be likely to
encounter in the world around us, the parameters of which are defined in terms
of time and space. But this, for the cubist, is entirely superficial. Beneath
what sense can only perceive as chaos, inasmuch as it appropriates data within
the limitations of time and space, is the ingenious rendering --- and unity ---
of the subject in terms appropriable only through the intellect. The Cubist,
recognizing the totality of his subject, is not satisfied with the single facet,
the one perspective, to which perception is limited by time and space --- one
given particular spatial perspective among a multiplicity of possible alternate
perspectives permitted in one particular point in time. Realizing that we cannot
attain to the totality and unity of the subject aspectually, facet by facet ---
as it were, by a process of addition, attempting to arrive at a sum from the
parts --- he strives, rather, to grasp, to render, the subject in its entirety,
from all perspectives and simultaneously. And because he does so at the cost of
the organization of space and time --- by superimposing perspective upon
perspective as so many temporal overlays upon his subject--- the product is
formally recalcitrant to perspective and strikes us as odd, even grotesque.
Prescinding from a presumed aesthetic value, the rendering is perspicuous to the
intellect only. In a similar manner, in the mystical experience the multifaceted
dimensions of being, of any being and all being, become totalized in an
intuitional noesis, and through this totalization become susceptible of being
cognized simultaneously. It is a perception of erstwhile unrealized dimensions
and relations in being --- dimensions and relations latent in ontology and
capable of being elicited only through the soul’s virtual participation in the
Divine Mind, the absolutely illimitable cognition of God. And it is precisely
for this reason that mysticism purports to convey to us an unqualified,
veridical perception of reality, for it is reality simultaneously and
exhaustively considered in all its luminescent dimensions and
relations.
Objections from Orthodoxy: Indwelling
Unknown
The types of objections
that we have been considering until now have largely come from perspectives
outside the tradition to which St. John belongs and apart from which his
metaphysics are incapable of being understood. The scientific perspective, while
not in and of itself intrinsically inimical to mysticism, is nevertheless more
often than not critically, if unsuccessfully, invoked in attempts to discredit
the mystical experience, while the skeptic, to whom Christian metaphysics in
general is not simply insufficient but abhorrent, is openly hostile toward it.
In a greater sense we may have anticipated these objections beforehand, for
while they are clearly brought to bear against mysticism in particular as
epitomizing the religious impulse, we may equally anticipate their critical
inquiry into any aspect of religion in general, especially when claims are made
about religious experiences, for any experience as such would appear to bring at
least certain aspects of putative religious phenomena within the competence, and
therefore under the legitimate purview, of science. In any event, a long and
often unnecessarily antagonistic association has existed between science and
religion which leads us to expect, as a matter of course, at least a critical
commentary on topics religious from science in general. This is no especial
handicap to mysticism, as we have seen. But there are other types of objections,
more critical still, brought against mysticism from the very tradition upon
which it is nurtured; criticisms which have sometimes resulted in an internecine
conflict between dogmatic elements embodied in orthodox doctrine, and a
perceived incompatibility with, if not an outright repudiation of, acknowledged
dogma in the sometimes rarefied metaphysics of mysticism. This tension, more
often than not, has essentially resulted from either a misunderstanding, or too
rigorous an understanding of the sometimes fluid metaphysics subtending the
mystical experience. This, coupled with the limitations inherent in language ---
and not occasionally by concepts carelessly constructed or poorly thought
through --- had, until St. John of the Cross, combined to create an atmosphere
not altogether congenial between Dogmatics and Mysticism.
Nor was St. John himself,
as we had seen, exempt from the lingering odor of heresy inasmuch as his own
doctrines were called before --- although subsequently exonerated by --- the
Holy Office. 17 Historically this has not always been the case. The Holy
Office had good reason, and ample evidence of justification, for its vigilant
skepticism. A point in fact, among many others that could be invoked, involves
no less a well known and influential mystic than Johann Eckhart who, to his
credit, and as an enduring testimony to his humility, retracted several
controversial positions before the scrutiny of a panel assembled against him by
the archbishop of Cologne in 1326, subsequent to which some twenty-eight of his
propositions were formally condemned, seventeen among them being pronounced no
less than heretical. St. John, on the other hand, so brilliantly and
meticulously synthesized dogma and mystical doctrine, that he earned the title
Doctor of the Church Universal by proclamation of Pope Pius XI in 1926 --- some
335 years after his death. That is to say, subsequent to 335 years of close
doctrinal investigation and the unremitting dogmatic analysis of his work. This
is no small achievement, and speaks, I think, extremely well of the mind of this
inimitable, if diminutive, Spanish mystic. Even in his most ecstatic utterances,
St. John has ground his doctrine firmly in the elements of dogmatic theology.
This is not to say, of course, that misunderstandings will not inevitably occur
given the often abstruse metaphysics upon which his doctrines rest, and for this
reason it appears to me entirely worthwhile to consider some of these
misunderstandings in light of a brief Scriptural exegesis from which dogma
ultimately derives its own doctrine.
One of the more cogent
objections that we encounter involves the doctrine of the resurrection, and the
argument may be stated as follows: If the perfection of man, or the consummation
of his being, consists in the beatific vision of God, 18 which the Christian understands to be heaven; and if such a
vision is, according to mystical doctrine, inaccessible to man in his created
and finite nature, then how is this to be understood as compatible with the
divine eschatology in which the separated soul is held to be rejoined with the
body in the general resurrection when the bodies and souls of the just
will be assumed into heaven --- that is to say, brought before the beatific
vision? For indeed, Job himself in the midst of his afflictions
utters:
“This I know: my Avenger lives, and he, the
Last, will take his stand on earth. After my awaking, he will set me close to
him, and from my flesh I shall look on God.” 19
This is equally affirmed
by the Apostle Paul in his epistle to the Thessalonians:
“... those who have died in Christ will be
the first to rise, and then those of us who are still alive will be taken up in
the clouds, together with them, to meet the Lord ...” 20
Moreover, the Apostle
John in the Book of Revelation reports seeing:
“... a huge number, impossible to count, of
people from every nation, race, tribe and language; they were standing in front
of the throne and in front of the Lamb, dressed in white robes and holding palms
in their hands.” 21
And again, from the same
source, the Evangelist states that:
“They will never hunger or thirst again;
... because the Lamb who is at the throne will ... lead them to springs of
living water; and God will wipe away all tears from their
eyes.” 22
Given such passages, from
unimpeachable sources, it would seem that we shall indeed see God in our created
nature, for it is clearly the body, and not the soul, which is possessed of
hands, and in need of raiment (Rev. 7.9); which alone has eyes, and requires
food (Rev. 7.17). It would then appear that the mystical doctrine which
maintains that the beatific vision of God is accessible to man only through the
negation of that created nature with which he is providentially endowed, is
incompatible with Scripture. But is it really? Consider the following statement
by St. Paul in his letter to the Corinthians:
“... flesh and blood cannot inherit the
kingdom of God: and the perishable cannot inherit what lasts forever. I will
tell you something that has been secret: that we are not all going to die, but
we shall all be changed. This will be instantaneous, in the twinkling of an eye,
when the last trumpet sounds. It will sound, and the dead will be raised,
imperishable, and we shall be changed as well, because our perishable nature
must put on imperishability and this mortal nature must put on
immortality.” 23
And
earlier:
“ [ In the] resurrection of the dead... the
thing that is sown is contemptible but what is raised is glorious... when it is
sown it embodies the soul, when it is raised it embodies the spirit”
24
And yet
again:
“... the Lord Jesus Christ ... will
transfigure these wretched bodies of ours into copies of his glorious
body.” 25
And finally, the
Evangelist John affirms this eschatological doctrine in stating
that:
“... we are already the children of God
but what we are to be in the future has not yet been revealed; all we know is,
when it is revealed we shall be like him because we shall see him as he really
is.” 26
While the historical
development of doctrine pertaining to eschatology, especially as it unfolds
within the canon of Scripture, is obviously another study altogether, it
nevertheless remains pertinent to our understanding that from St. John’s point
of view, it is not the case that the latter four citations are simply more
compatible or more readily accord with his own mystical doctrine --- and that
therefore Scripture is somehow vindicated or validated by his own
metaphysical insight. This would be to misunderstand St. John entirely. For St.
John, it is rather the case that his mystical doctrine is in agreement with
Scripture --- and that therefore his metaphysical analysis is effectively
validated in divine revelation. Nor is this relationship to be understood as
coincidental in the least since St. John’s metaphysics is profoundly based upon
Scripture --- a fact amply attested to by his constant appeal to Sacred
Scripture in elaborating his doctrine. Now certainly it was not the intent, and
clearly aside from the purpose, of both St. Paul and the Apostle John to
proclaim a metaphysical evangel --- but the latent metaphysical
implications upon which St. John of the Cross drew are nevertheless
conspicuously present within that divinely inspired kerygma. The obvious
question, then, remains as to how the four previously cited passages are to be
understood in light of the latter four statements. First of all, I think it is
important to understand that the use of symbolism and metaphors, which is
largely a feature of apocalyptic literature in general, is a type of mystical
signature in all eschatological accounts; and they are so precisely
because these accounts are characteristically eschatological, being
narrated either at the margin of, or in fact within, supernatural experience
itself. In a very real sense they share in the unique mystical problematic of
language: the attempt to communicate what is experienced as essentially
ineffable. And as is often the case in mystical experience, only analogies,
similes and metaphors can suffice where descriptive language either proves
altogether inadequate or completely fails. The canonical books of Ezekiel and
Daniel, to say nothing of the Apocalypse, are eminent examples of this type of
encounter with linguistic limitations. Here we find a tremendous literal effort
to introduce some measure of commensurability into the account of an experience
that is commensurable with no other: hence the proliferation of symbols,
metaphors, and similes, valuable in themselves only insofar as they
intelligibly, albeit remotely, proximate or convey some sense of experiences
inherently recalcitrant to the descriptive utility of language. St. Paul’s own
mystical experience, to which we had briefly adverted earlier, is a good case in
point. In his second epistle to the Corinthians, St. Paul, speaking of himself,
says:
“I know a man in Christ who, fourteen years
ago, was caught up --- whether still in the body or out of the body, I do not
know; God knows --- right into the third heaven. I do know, however, that
this same person --- whether in the body or out of the body, I do not
know; God knows --- was caught up into paradise and heard things which must not
and can not be put into human language.”
27
It is, I suggest,
precisely in light of this type of apparent incommensurability that we must
endeavor to understand apocalyptic and eschatological symbolism. It is not the
case that one part of Scripture is true from a mystical point of view and
another part not true --- it is essentially the manner in which that truth is
communicated. One clear example at hand of the hermeneutic tension likely to
result from this type of recurrent symbolism is to be found in the sense in
which the Lamb (Christ) is understood to “feed” the souls of just as we had seen
described in Revelation 7.17, and in the first Gospel where Christ
says:
“Man does not live on bread alone, but on
every word that comes from the mouth of God.” 28
And in the Book of
Revelation:
“... to those who prove victorious I will
give the hidden manna...”
29
How are we to understand
this symbolism? What, for example, is this “hidden manna”? It is nothing less
than a share in the life of Christ as is evident from the fourth Gospel where
Christ declares:
“I am the bread of life. Your fathers ate
the manna in the desert and they are dead; but this is the bread that comes down
from heaven, so that a man may eat it and not die. I am the living bread which
has come down from heaven. Anyone who eats this bread will live forever; and the
bread that I shall give is my flesh, for the life of the world ... He who eats
my flesh ... lives in me and I live in him.” 30
Such passages, then, much
as we had found in Revelation 7.17 and the three citations subsequent to it,
cannot, in and of themselves, be literally interpreted and therefore construed
as disconfirming the mystical thesis. Much as we had found in our previous
examples, the literal meaning --- presented to us in terms that would
appear to imply actual corporeity --- inadvertently obscures, if not effectively
corrupts, the authentic significance latent within the text itself. And I think
that we must see this not as a literary device to conceal doctrine beneath
ambiguities --- but merely as the result of a certain default in language
characteristically encountered before certain types of experience. And this, I
think, is particularly true of those references we find to the body. It is
virtually certain, in light of the sorts of statements made by the Apostles
which we had just considered, that we must indeed assume a radically different
kind of body than we now possess in order to accommodate ourselves to that
vision of God in which perfect beatitude is held to consist; a body no longer
possessed of the limitations to which it is presently subject; in the words of
St. Paul, a spiritual body, one in which presently experienced
limitations are transcended, overcome, abolished. And this, of course, is an
essential element in mystical doctrine: the restoration of commensurability
through the transcendence of limitation. And while this mystical contention that
man in the state of nature --- and by the state of nature we always mean
prescinding from grace which is a share in the life of God ---
cannot attain to the beatific vision, is implied elsewhere in Scripture,
31 the whole point which
St. John endeavors to develop is that it is of the essence of the mystical
dialogue that we cannot prescind from grace and arrive at a coherent
explanation of the mystical experience. St. John, we have insisted from the
outset, is writing within a very clearly defined tradition to which an adequate
notion of grace is indispensable. And what we understand by grace ---
essentially, participation in the life of God--- is the crucial key to the most
central, and at once most enigmatic, paradox of mysticism: the union of
incommensurables. And here we enter into the mystery of the
Incarnation.
A Two-Fold Doctrine: Mysticism and The
Incarnation
In order to understand
how it is possible for man as a finite, created being to come to union with the
Infinite, Uncreated Being of God --- a union to which, of himself, he cannot
possibly attain given an acknowledged ontological contrariety that can be
neither breached nor reconciled --- we must first understand how it is
possible for the Infinite, Uncreated Being of God to come to union with the
finite, created being of man; in other words, our answer must be formulated in
terms of the Christian dogma of the Incarnation. Briefly summarized, this
profound dogma is defined as the hypostatic union of the human with the divine
nature in the one divine person, Jesus Christ, in whom, therefore, two distinct
natures are held to subsist --- the unique ontological integrity of each
remaining equally intact --- and which are understood to be substantially united
and so constitute one substance in the one person. Simply put, the Divine and
the human, God and man, the Infinite and the finite, the Eternal and the
temporal, are united in the one person of Jesus Christ --- arguably the most
fundamental doctrine of Christianity.
Now, quite obviously, it
cannot be our argument that the Incarnation is an inverse paradigm of the
mystic’s relation to God. The mystic does not partake of the divine
nature in the way that Christ assumed our humanity. It is, for that reason,
called a mystical union --- and not a hypostatic union. The human nature
of the mystic does not become one substance with the divine nature of God. In
fact, were this understood to be the case, he would be no different from Christ.
But the point I wish to make in the way of explaining the divine paradox
embodied in mysticism is that the doctrine of the Incarnation effectively
establishes the ability of God --- to whom nothing is held to be impossible
32 ---to reconcile in His own person two otherwise mutually
exclusive and incompatible ontological categories without conflating the two or
diminishing the integrity of either. In other words, the reconciliation of
otherwise incompatible categories that is impossible for man --- is possible for
God; and the whole point that is key to our understanding of mysticism is that
it is possible only within His own person; the hypostasis, if you will,
with whom the mystic is united through infused contemplation. Let us attempt to
sort this out a bit.
Because the human and the
divine can coexist without contradiction in Christ, the humanity of the mystic
through his sacramental incorporation into the sacred humanity of the Christ, is
susceptible of being united with God through the divinity of Christ. The
participation of the mystic in God --- beyond what is only latent in his
created ontology as image of the Absolute in terms of his being-only---is only
possible through the assumption of humanity by Christ, which is to say, by the
Incarnation. Apart from Christ, the mystic has no ontological recourse to God,
for his nature is one, created, and finite. He does not embody the terms of
commensurability necessary to the union of ontological opposites. But Christ, as
the Son of God, does. The mystic’s union with God, then, is (only possible)
through God’s union with man in the person of His Son. Christ is the point of
union between God and man, the created and the Uncreated, the finite and the
Infinite, the temporal and the Eternal. This is the first point. The union of
incommensurables is established in Christ. The second point is perhaps best
introduced through the Johannine Prologue:
“... though the Law was
given through Moses, grace and truth have come through Jesus Christ.”
33
There are essentially two
vertical movements, then, to be found in St. John’s mystical account. The first,
as we had seen above, involves the descent of God to man and the union of
ontological opposites in the person of Christ through the Incarnation. And while
this remains a profound mystery accepted on faith and not susceptible of proof,
it nevertheless effectively establishes the basis for the possibility of
the union of opposites in the created nature of the soul vis-à-vis the Uncreated
nature of God --- a possibility so radicated in, as to be inconceivable apart,
from the Incarnation. The second movement, then, is of course the ascent of man
to God through mystical union. And this is uniquely achieved through
Christ --- who, in the sublime poetry of St. John of the Cross, is the
Spouse, the Beloved, the Bridegroom, with whom the
contemplative ultimately attains to union. Christ alone, as true man,
comprehends within himself the created nature of man reconciled with divine
nature of God, and as True God the divine nature of God reconciled with the
human nature of man. And it is of the essence of our argument that the mystic is
only enabled to participate in both through his union with Christ in whom
alone these otherwise irreconcilable natures, while yet remaining distinct, are
united in one substance in one person. And this means that mystical union is not
only unintelligible, but unattainable apart from Christ --- who himself said
that no one comes to Father except through him 34 who, in his divinity, is one with the Father.
35
While me may have
acquired some insight into certain aspects of the mechanics involved in the
movement to union through the via negativa, together with some of the
metaphysical principles underlying it, the impelling force itself behind this
movement is ultimately grace; not simply actual grace as the mystic’s subjective
response to the invitation, but sanctifying grace through which the mystic
already shares in the life of God Himself through his incorporation into the
Mystical body of Christ. And this is to say that aside from the purely
ontological relationship to God that is understood in terms of mans being-only,
which, in the strictest sense, is possessed of an ontic dignity no greater than,
and essentially no different from, anything else of which being-only may also be
predicated through its participation in the Being-Absolute---a relationship, in
any event, which we do not understand as constituting ontological union
because of real metaphysical contrarieties in nature --- or yet even in the more
articulated ontological presupposition that is rooted in man’s being understood
as a being-the-image-of-the Absolute, of God, which presumes to its being, the
Imaged of which, and in virtue of which alone, it is an image --- beyond all
these relations which only metaphysically obtain, there is a far greater, a more
binding and commensurable relationship that obtains through
grace.
Ontology merely defines
the terms of the relation legislated in nature. Within it we discern the
metaphysical relation, but also the insuperable contrariety that metaphysics
alone cannot reconcile. Grace, however, ever building upon nature, redefines the
terms in the person of Christ, and specifically through the mystery of the
Incarnation. The infusion of the divine, the infinite, the eternal, into the
human, the finite, and the temporal, binds, with neither contradiction nor
conflation, two erstwhile irreconcilable categories into one
substance in the one person in a way analogous to that in which the mystic
attains to union with God in Christ. The difficulty that we have, I think, in
coming to terms with this notion is our tendency to confuse union with
identity. Christ, in assuming human nature, did not make it divine such
that it was no longer a human nature, but was transformed into, and therefore
identical with, his divine nature. The Incarnation did not abolish his human
nature. It brought it into substantive union with his divine nature. In other
words, the notion of union, as we had pointed out earlier, presupposes two
distinct terms attaining to a unity of those terms, and not a reciprocal
transformation of those terms. And this is precisely the manner in which the
mystic comes to union with God, while not becoming God. Where the mystic attains
to this union through participation, God, in Christ, achieved an
infinitely more profound union through the Incarnation --- the
Incarnation, subsequent to which, and through which alone, the participation of
man in God is made possible because God first deigned to come to union with
man.
This really brings us to
what I feel is by far the most serious objection to mysticism; one that is
occasioned by a misunderstanding of the most fundamental mystical doctrine that
man not simply can participate in God, but effectively, be
God-by-participation. This conclusion is so obviously fraught with possibilities
of misunderstanding and so readily lends itself to misinterpretation, it is
little wonder that historically it has consistently been the subject of
ecclesiastical censure; and for very good reason. >From the outset, as far
back as Plotinus and Porphry, the third century antagonists to the
philosophically naive Christians--- and themselves the metaphysical precursors
to Christianized mysticism --- this doctrine has, in one way or another, either
acquired or been tainted with the odor of heresy. This regrettable consequence
had resulted largely from heretical conclusions that necessarily, or
systematically followed from basically defective metaphysical premises; premises
to which the Christian mystic had inadvertently committed himself in good faith,
but from which he could not extricate himself without repudiating his own
metaphysical doctrine. It is, I think, not so much a case of a lack of critical
assessment as a lapse in critical judgment. The conclusions may well follow
deductively from the premises, but the premises, and, a fortiori,
the conclusions, are in some essential aspect defective, resulting in
consequences unacceptable either to reason or orthodox doctrine, or more often
than not, to both.
The great thirteenth
century mystic Johann Eckhart, for example, in his celebrated Opus
Tripartitum 36, maintained that man, already possessed of an
“uncreated” scintilla (vünkelin) as the essence of his soul, is capable
of total transformation into God, and that this transformation, because
it is total, essentially requires the annihilation of his created nature. John
Tauler, another acclaimed thirteenth century mystic, appears to suggest that
mystical union is achieved only at the cost of man’s unique identity, as well as
his own distinctive consciousness, apart from God. In the following century we
find the equally renowned mystic, Jan Ruysbroeck, in the third chapter of his
De Ornatu Spiritalium Nuptiarum 37, describing the union of the soul with God in terms which
do not clearly admit of any recognizable distinction, or, for that matter,
individuation, from God. Eckhart, it is important to note, submitted to the
censure his writings provoked and had subsequently retracted these statements
and publicly recanted his position, while Suso --- despite his error--- was
nevertheless beatified by the Church in 1831. Those who like to see these early
Dominican mystics as proto-antagonists to the institutional Church will be
disappointed to find in their humility not a formal, but an earnest submission
to what they recognized as the magisterium of the Church. These men, in other
words, were by and large faithful sons of the Church, even holy men, consumed
with a love of God that sometimes led to impulsive, rather than closely
reasoned, speculation on the nature of their mystical
experiences.
It is against this
background that we must begin to explore the objections to the fundamental
mystical doctrine that man is capable of becoming God-by-participation, and in
the process endeavor to understand how St. John avoided the errors that dogged
his predecessors within the same tradition. Let us first be clear about the
problem, especially as it is viewed from the perspective of dogmatic theology.
That God’s nature is absolutely unique and essentially apart from every other
nature is fundamental to some of the most ancient canons of Scripture beginning
with the first proscription of the Decalogue 38 where God effectively establishes his unique transcendence
beyond, not simply man, but everything that has a claim to man’s reverence
through its transcendence, such that the prophet Isaiah simply
states:
“To whom could you liken God? What image
could you contrive of him?” 39
Indeed, God Himself
speaking through this same prophet, asks:
“To whom can you compare me, equate me, to
whom claim I am similar, or comparable? 40 ... I am God unrivaled, God who has no
like ... 41
The Odor of Heresy: God-by-Participation
How, then, can St. John
--- indeed, any mystic --- claim that thhrough ecstatic union the soul becomes
“God-by-participation” through this God “who has no like”; this God to whom
nothing can be equated? But indeed, this has been the starting point of the
mystic from the beginning, the very metaphysical realization that is both the
focal point and whole purpose of the via negativa. What we find here,
then, is essentially a restatement of the mystical problematic; not a
contradiction, but an affirmation of the problem which mysticism takes to itself
from the outset: given the absolute incommensurability, the categorical
contrariety, that is perceived between man and God, how is it possible for man
to attain to union with Him? Nor is the question merely speculative in the way
of an attempt to define a relationship in terms of possibility only --- it is a
genuine, an earnest inquiry arising out of actual experiences, equally real
experiences of contrariety and unity, that in turn demand coherence, a coherence
which the mystic clearly perceives but toward which he must strive through the
limitations and liabilities of language and in the context of dogmatic
parameters with which his doctrine must accord. Nor are these parameters, at
least for St. John, perceived as constraints upon the mystical impulse; to the
contrary, as we had explained earlier they are understood as constituting an
indispensable index of irrefragable truth in the form of dogmatic certainties
derived from no less an unimpeachable source than divine revelation itself to
which the mystic subsequently appeals both as a means of verifying the
authenticity of his experiences, and in avoiding the impediment of error --- the
twofold source of which, we will remember, is human and diabolical --- that
would otherwise frustrate his journey to union. Dogma, in other words, is not
something simply subsidiary to the mystical experience for St. John; it is
requisite to achieving it.
If we succeed in
understanding St. John’s mystical doctrine in its clear relationship to dogma,
we immediately grasp the context in which his claim that the mystic does indeed
become, in a carefully nuanced sense, “God-by-participation”, for the
possibility of man’s participating in God ultimately derives, as we had seen,
from man’s ontological status as essentially being-the-image-of-God, and
Scriptural references to this effect are numerous. 42 At its most basic level, we have understood this
participation to relate to man’s being-only, or
being-contingent-upon-the-Being-Absolute of God. And in this sense, man’s being
necessarily, but only remotely --- in the most minimal sense that unpredicated
being-only implies --- participates in the being of God, in Whom, unlike man,
being and essence coincide. Beyond this merely ontological relation that man
shares with virtually every other created existent, a greater dignity obtains in
man through the further articulation of his being-only into
being-the-image-of-God which conveys a good deal more in the way of proximity
than is implied in the remote concept of being-only.
The question then
naturally arises, in what does this image consist? And St. John --- unlike
Aquinas and Eckhart before him, both of whom had understood this to consist in
the intellect --- answered, as we had seen earlier, that it principally consists
in the faculty of love, which for St. John is the only proximate means to union
with a God Who is Love. And while we tend to see this as an essentially
affective faculty capable of embracing the totality of man’s being in the
impulse to union with the Beloved --- compellingly and beautifully illustrated
in the poetry of St. John --- love is essentially more than merely affective, at
least as we are inclined to understand it in contemporary terms: indeed, a close
analysis reveals that it fundamentally pertains to the will in its relationship
to the good. In its essence, love simply consists in willing every possible good
and no evil. And this, of course, is what we preeminently understand of God. It
is not Divinity conceived in terms of power, or being, or intellect, that
invincibly compels our affinity to God; it is his goodness, and the
divine, the absolute and unqualified love that is the enactment of this goodness
--- the clearest expression of which, foor the Christian mystic, became Incarnate
in His Only Begotten Son. Reason, the intellect, only affords us an
analogy --- not a likeness between the soul and God. Love, on the other hand,
is, for St. John, the impress of God upon the soul, the impress of likeness. But
we have found that even this impress alone, that is to say, in and of itself, is
insufficient to union --- a union that can only be effected, not through
nature, but through grace which alone is accessible through the
Son, even as we had seen earlier in our discussion on the Incarnation. Man
indeed can become God-by-participation --- because God in His Son had
first become man through the Incarnation.
The mind of St. John,
then, is unequivocally the mind of the Church. But the genius of St. John, even
beyond his inimitable, even sublime, poetic creativity, lies in his ability not
simply to elicit, but to reconcile, a complex multiplicity of metaphysical and
ontological antinomies, to submit them to the demands of reason and to the
equally exacting demands of doctrine, and to arrive at a coherent synthesis
that, without compromising either, is consonant with both. It lies in his
capacity to discover not merely plausible but cogent relations between the
formal articles of faith and the empirical deliverances of experience, between
the cerebral austerity of metaphysics and the resolute passion of dogmatics,
between the abstracted Absolute and the virtual real --- in a word, between God
and man. To view his achievement in terms less than this; to see it merely as
the successful conclusion to an endeavor defined from the outset by a
preconceived effort to conform doctrine to dogma --- a success that his
predecessors within the same tradition did not enjoy, and which in large part
rightfully earned him the title of Doctor of the Church --- is nevertheless to
miss the point of St. John’s contribution altogether.
It is not the case that
St. John modified or scaled down his doctrine as a theological expedience to
conform to --- in a greater sense, to comply with --- the orthodox demands of
dogma, and in the process sacrificed the authenticity of his account; much less
that he exercised what amounts to duplicity in offering one doctrine while
secretly subscribing to another. There is no evidence whatever suggestive of
this in any of the Juanistic writings. His genius quite simply consists in his
ability to coherently elicit from experience what dogma presents to faith. It
is, in a sense, experience infused with theological
reciprocity.
From a doctrinal
standpoint there is essentially little difference between the Apostle Peter
stating that “... you will be able to share the divine nature
...43, and St. John maintaining that the mystic in ecstatic union
becomes “God-by-participation”. And this, of course, is no mere coincidence. St.
John was renowned for his profound knowledge of Sacred Scripture, which he
deftly quotes, often analogically, to illustrate a point in his own mystical
doctrine, and while his writings are free of the scholastic encumbrances of many
of his contemporaries --- and are for this very reason accessible, as they were
meant to be, to the average reader --- the tradition within which he writes is
unmistakable. One does not find a multiplicity of references outside of Sacred
Scripture in the works of St. John, and the appeal to authority in establishing
an argument (“... for according to the philosopher ...”) which had become
somewhat of a hallmark in a good deal of scholastic philosophy, is conspicuously
and refreshingly absent in the writings of St. John --- but the scholastic stamp
itself remains indelible. In any event, any question concerning the tension
between St. John’s mysticism and orthodox doctrine was definitively settled, at
least within the Church, upon St. John’s beatification in 1675, and his
subsequent canonization in 1726. And despite the animus that motivates much of
the criticism of the Church, her scholars, in their critical examination of the
mystical doctrines of St. John, have, by and large, been men and women whose
reason has been as profound as their faith.
Rewarding as such an
analysis of St. John’s works has been, it is not unaccompanied by a certain
sense of incompleteness. His intuitive grasp of Sacred Scripture, his uncanny
and unerring insight into human nature, and, above all, his poetry, have been
barely touched upon --- the latter most regrettably of all. It is difficult to
try to summarize even a few of the many profound dimensions in the thought of
perhaps the greatest figure in the Western tradition of mysticism, and it is
extremely doubtful that any commentary, however comprehensive, will completely
succeed in plumbing their depths or exhausting their amplitude. But this, after
all, is St. John’s own particular charism, both as philosopher and mystic. It
is, in the end, a fitting testimony to the depth of one man’s being, whose being
became inseparably bound to God’s.
1 Varieties
of Religious Experience, lecture 17
2
Religion and
Science, Chapter
7
3 AMC 2.11-12;
2.16ff; 2.19ff; & 3.2ff
4
AMC 1.1.5; DNS
1.9.9
5 AMC 1.1.4-5;
DNS 1.1.1 & 1.9.7
6
DNS
1.6.2
7 The
Varieties of Religious Experience, Lecture 7.
8
The freedom
implied in this possibility, incidentally, was apparently overlooked by the
Illuminists mentioned in an earlier connection. Freedom is generally conceded to
be a perfection in man; hence, the Illuminists, while holding man to be
essentially impeccable in the state of union, inadvertently deprived man of this
perfection. And this, of course, is incompatible with the notion of union with
God as constituting man’s highest perfection. In other words, the highest, or
consummate, perfection cannot be achieved through a privation of that very
perfection.
9 i.e., faith
(cf. AMC, 2.4.2 ff.)
10 The
thousand-sided figure that we can conceive but not apprehend. Meditation
VI
11 AMC 1.4.4,
1.5.4, etc.
12 Ex.3.14; Jn.
1.3, 8.58; Col. 1.16-17; Rev. 1.8 Also cf. ST I.3 Ques. 44
Art.1-4
13 And, eo
ipso, man understood as participating in God.
14 Such an
argument, were it successful, would in effect demonstrate this opposition to be,
not real, but apparent only, and the ineluctable consequence of this line of
reasoning would be a pantheistic interpretation of the universe; an
interpretation which, beside being clearly outside the pale of Christianity,
entails myriad contradictions within its own terms.
15 While we
cannot offer proof of this assertion within the limited scope of our present
inquiry, this presupposition constitutes the first principle apart from which
nothing further intelligible in the mystical account may follow. God, in
a word, simply must be taken as the sine qua non of Christian
mysticism.
16 In the words
of St. Paul, arguably the first mystic in the Christian tradition: “Nos autem
sensum Christi habemus.” 1 Cor. 2.16
17 cf. page
191
18 cf. DNS
2.20.5; 1 Cor. 13.12; 1 Jn. 3.2; Aquinas, Sum. Cont. Gent. 4.1.1;
Augustine, De Civit. Dei 22.24
19 Job
19.25-26
20 1 Thess.
4.16-7
21 Rev.
7.9
22 Rev.
7.17
23 1 Cor.
15.50-53
24 1 Cor.
15.42-44
25 Phlp.
3.21
26 1 Jn.
3.2
27 2 Cor.
12.2-4
28 Mat.
4.4
29 Rev.
2.17
30 Jn.6.48-56,
emphasis added
31 Ex. 33.20;
Deut 18.16 (also cf. Gen. 32.30; Dt. 5.25 + 18.16; Jg. 6.22-23; Is.
6.5)
32 Mat.
19.26
33 Jn.
1.17
34 Jn
14.6
35 Jn.10.30
36 Work in Three
Parts
37 Adornment of
the Spiritual Marriage
38
Ex.20.1-5
39 Is. 40.18
(also cf. Dt. 3.24; Ps.86.8, 89.8, 113.5; Jer. 10.6)
40 Is.
46.5
41 Is.
46.9
42 Gen.1.26-27;
Ps. 17.15; Rom. 8.29; 1 Cor. 11.7, 15.49; 2 Cor. 3.8; Col. 3.10; Jas.
3.9
43 2 Pt.
1.4
(Continued below)
As a final note, something further must be said about the permutations of being as they touch upon our attempt to arrive at some kind of epistemological synthesis. In the writings of St. John of the Cross, any attempt to seize upon a coherent notion of being immediately brings us to the ineluctable realization that for St. John the ontological is deeply radicated in the eschatological. Being in its utter immediacy is possessed of identity, and therefore history. The historical nature of being, embracing, as it does, all the antecedents that culminate in present being, being not merely verging upon, but enacted within the telos of becoming, is, within the mystical context, without terminus; it is eternally enacted because God is eternal. Ultimately, beyond the eschatological chrysalis, being is epiphanous, a perpetual epiphany in perpetually becoming. What I mean by this is that God's autonomous perpetuity is in Being. Man's heteronymous perpetuity is in becoming. Let us take another approach..
Becoming, I at least suggest, is the created articulation of the
uncreated eternal. There is no terminus to becoming vis-à-vis the Absolute, the
Infinite, the Eternal, and in this sense it is perpetually parallel to it and only in virtue of it. Even while we may
speculate that at any given point of becoming, the soul (in eternity) subsumes
as present all the
permutations of its being, in all
that has been and to this extent
incorporates being even in the
indesinence of becoming; that is to
say, if we presume that the soul incorporates as present all that has been up to any given point in the
continuum of becoming, we still have not arrived at the soul as being --- only as a being-such-that-is-perpetually-a-becoming-of. From this perspective, the soul is
indeed the imago Dei inasmuch as it
embraces as eternally present all
that it has been … .
up to this point in its becoming;
however, what lies before it is not yet present, nor can the soul
incorporate what it is not yet, into
what it has been, into what it is,
has enacted, up to this point of its
becoming. The soul may in fact be understood to exist in a quasi-eternal
present ---
but it is a present that has not yet, and never will, culminate in a
terminus of its becoming such that it is a being whose being has been totally
and completely enacted and can become no more than it is. But to attain to
nothing more, to culminate in nothing more, to become no more than what the soul
is, is to understand the soul not simply as having attained to being, but having
become distinguishable from it. It would be a being whose essence has culminated
in being. But only God’s Being is His essence, and only God’s Essence is His
Being. Rather than having understood the soul as having spuriously assumed
unqualified being, we see the soul as the speculum of this Esse Ipsum, this Being Itself, as the
finite image of what is absolute --- understanding at the same time that the
Infinite and Absolute as imaged
eternally exceed the boundaries of the finite image. However clear and
authentic the image, it is only an image in part, an incomplete instantiation,
not only of the Absolute, but of its very own being
which is perpetually becoming, and is not yet what it will be, and when
it is what it will be, it will still
not yet be what it will be, for it remains to be more, to become more than it
is, to perpetually verge on the Infinite and the Absolute but never embrace it
in its totality. Since human nature can never attain to the ontological status
of Being Itself inasmuch as it can
never assume the divine nature (even while participating in it), the perpetuity of
its becoming-that-always-verges-on-being
remains an inviolable aspect of its created nature (or its nature qua created) --- and therefore remains
unchanged even in eternity. And that is the splendor and the happiness, the
felicity enjoyed by the soul in conspectu
Dei, that is to say, in the beatific vision. Becoming is
inexhaustible --- because Being Itself is inexhaustible in God;
becoming, as such, it is a tangent to, because it is enacted in,
eternity.
A Biography of St. John of the
Cross
While it might appear odd to append a biographical sketch as
a postscript, I have done so deliberately. In an effort to isolate the logical
and metaphysical elements in St. John’s mystical account from any biographical
overview whatever, I have attempted to subject his doctrine to a philosophic
inquiry specifically upon its own terms. In approaching the works of St. John as
a purely epistemological enterprise, our primary focus has been a rigorous
examination of the internal consistency of the doctrines that evolve from
a close and critical reading of the text. A doctrine, however, which simply
evidences no inconsistency among the terms through which it is articulated,
while persuading us of its cogency, or even its consonance with reason, leaves
us with something not so much epistemic, as doxastic in nature. Specifically,
the quantum leap from the hypothetical if to the existential is
--- in other words, from the conditioonal to the existential, from
<P.... to $x, is nothing less than
a leap from the qualified hypothetical to the unqualified ontological. However
splendid the architectonic that we observe in the metaphysical edifice,
the predication of being remains another matter altogether, often
attaining to something merely speculative, tentative or altogether elusive. To
complicate matters further, the canons to which we appeal in our attempts to
qualify or disqualify such phenomena as authentically ontic in nature are
themselves notoriously fluid. In this sense, philosophy is a propadeutic to
something beyond itself. It brings us to the brink of the chasm dividing the
hypothetical from the ontological, but is not itself the bridge over
which we pass. Yet if we
hope to attain to something more cogent, more compelling, than mere speculations
delivered ex hypothesi, we must earnestly acknowledge, take into account,
and attempt to respond to, some very rigorous criticisms of the epistemological
credentials we have presumed to proffer, especially philosophical critiques that
emerge outside the tradition of which the mystical doctrine of St. John has
subsequently become part. We find in the end that we have arrived at neither a
contention, nor an accommodation, so much as a confluence of ideas that
contribute to an understanding of that sublime phenomena we have come to know as
mysticism. Whether these have crystallized into something coherent I leave to
the judgment of the reader. The point I now wish to emphasize is that in making
every effort to allow St. John’s account to stand upon the integrity of its own
arguments --- and apart from the personality behind the mind that forged this
remarkable doctrine, I have sought to bring impartial and objective focus to the
consistency of the doctrine --- independent of the undisputed sanctity of
the man. I think that this is quite necessary. Holy men do not
necessarily make sound doctrine, as clearly was the case with Blessed Henry
Suso. There is no binding vinculum between sanctity and perspicacity, because in
large part the latter is unessential, and in the end ultimately superfluous to
the former.
Let me take another tack:
the culmination of every Christian life is the attainment of holiness, and if
erudition attends this achievement it is admirable but largely beside the point.
I am a great admirer of Russell; his perspicacity and often trenchant, critical,
insight are refreshing both in their candor and clarity; but I decidedly esteem
Mother Teresa of Calcutta, or for that matter, Blaise Pascal, as having arrived
at something more estimable through, rather than having merely articulated
sterile abstractions in, the pursuit of truth.
Perspicacity, in a word,
is engaging --- but sanctity is compelling. And this really brings me to the
point of this preface. Sanctity, I think, is often so compelling that we are
loath to subject it to any association with error. We are inclined, in effect,
to extrapolate from sanctity to inerrancy, as the though a defect in the latter
vitiates the former, which is not at all the case. Christ’s stinging rebuke to
Peter is a sober reminder of this. 1 But the fact remains that it is likely in some to attenuate
the genuine and unsparing critical impulse necessary to the objective analysis
of a Saint’s work --- and as a consequence to forfeit truth; a defection no less
antagonistic to good philosophy than to religion. Truth itself, it has been
suggested, must be esteemed as holy --- and any defection from it a defection
from the very holiness toward which we strive. And this is simply another way of
saying that we cannot hope to attain to a consistent end through inconsistent
means. And while we must be careful of a susceptibility to this type of critical
latitude in dealing with the Saints, we must, on the other hand, and quite
obviously, recognize that sanctity and critical acumen, while not allied of
necessity, have quite often found common ground in the lives of the Saints. Even
the most cursory perusal of the voluminous Patrolgiae Latinae Cursus
Completus or the Patrologiae Graecae --- to mention nothing of the
great multiplicity of philosophical and theological works within the Church that
extends to the present day --- clearly attests to this. And this is simply to
say, on the other hand, that sanctity no more precludes critical acumen that
critical insight precludes sanctity. Nevertheless, it remains a common, even a
persistent misconception that a Saint’s commitment to doctrine --- which, from
the Catholic perspective, is at least an integral aspect of the imputation of
sanctity --- precludes, or at least impedes, hampers, confines, even compromises
the disinterested dedication to truth. But the fact of the matter is that the
sanctions incorporated into that very body of doctrine are more far-reaching,
and far more stringent, relative to a commitment to truth than those which are
selectively and subjectively appropriated outside of it according to the
individual inclination of the skeptic. This is not to disparage the moral
integrity of the skeptic, but merely to place it within existential perspective.
The historical and often heroic commitment to truth on the part of many Catholic
philosophers is, I suggest, exemplified in a way seldom encountered by their
skeptical counterparts in a given culture--- whether we consider the ancient
martyrology beginning with the early Christian philosopher St. Justin Martyr
who, rather than equivocate the truth, was scourged and beheaded in 165 AD; or
in our own times, and within the great Carmelite tradition itself, in the case
of St. Teresa Benedicta of the Cross, who as Edith Stein, the German
philosopher and colleague of the twentieth century phenomenologist Husserl,
perished at the Nazi death camp at Auschwitz in 1942, both as a Jew and a Nun,
renouncing neither and suffering for both --- despised by the Nazis as a Jew and
forsaken by her family as a Catholic Nun. Both, I maintain, are paradigms in the
sense that each had clear existential alternatives, the extreme consequences of
which turned exclusively upon their uncompromising relation to truth. These, and
the many examples to which we can appeal, evidence a commitment to truth often
supremely enacted; and that commitment, I suggest, which does not blench before
the prospect of death is much less likely to be compromised in matters decidedly
less final in nature.
Of course, such
commitment can be, and frequently is, dismissed, or worse yet, trivialized as
‘fanaticism’, but I think, by and large, that this explanation is much too
convenient, for we invariably see little of this trait, and much more in the way
of balanced reason evidenced in the lives of the Saints. And this essentially
brings us to the second reason that I have chosen to append St. John’s
bibliography in the way of a postscript. Bibliographies, especially within the
twentieth century, are seldom read without a good deal of psychological
conjecture, and a parallel, often narrative form, conceived in terms of the
doctrine with which we are first acquainted, accompanies and superimposes itself
upon our assessment not simply of the personality behind the doctrine, but more
importantly, of the doctrine itself which is then held to be, by extension, an
interpretation of the personality. As a result, we frequently do not allow the
doctrine, the philosophy, to be interpreted solely, objectively, in terms of its
own consistency, but rather in light of bibliographical features presumed as
contributing to, often in a psychological way, the development of the doctrine;
features which are then seized upon as an explanatory of it. We are all familiar
with one account or another in which the personality, or more specifically,
perceived defects in the personality, are held to be explanatory of the
doctrine. Interpreted psychologically in terms of a symptomatic, rather
than philosophically in terms of its intrinsic coherence, the focus
shifts altogether from philosophy (the doctrine as logical) to pathology (the
doctrine as pathological). At times this would appear to be explanatory of at
least some aspects of a given doctrine --- but seldom the entire
doctrine. Nietzsche, I think stands as one example of this, and so does
Schopenauer. But one will be hard pressed to detail this type of psychological
association between St. John of the Cross and his doctrine; in effect, to see
his doctrine emerging from his personality, and not out of his experiences.
Those who would seek such an explanatory are bound to be disappointed in the
life of St. John.
Beginnings
Born Juan de Yepes y
Alvarez on what is likely the 24th of June 1542 in Fontiveros, Spain,
St. John of the Cross was the youngest of three sons born to Gonzalo de Yepes
and Catalina Alvarez. John’s father, from a proud Toledo family which had
accumulated some considerable wealth, had a bright future before him in the silk
trade from which the family fortune had been amassed, but his marriage to
Catalina, who was of humble origin, was considered by his family an unpardonable
misalliance, and Gonzalo was effectively disowned and subsequently disinherited
by his family, leaving Gonzalo with his wife and three children in great
hardship. The callous disregard of Gonzalo and his family, now reduced to
poverty, is stunning, especially in light of the untimely death of Gonzalo in
1543, two short years after the birth of John, subsequent to which the family
turned a resolutely deaf ear to the pleas of the now destitute widow on behalf
of her small children, one of whom, the second eldest, died within a few years
of Gonzalo, leaving Catalina with John and his eldest brother Francisco. The
poverty that John was later to embrace as a religious, was cruelly thrust upon
him in childhood. Catalina’s meager earnings from silk-weaving were not enough
to feed and clothe her children who in large measure, and out of necessity,
relied upon the beneficence of a catechetical orphanage in Medina del Campo to
provide not simply the education, but the substance as well necessary to her
children. During this period, John had acquired some instruction, but no great
proficiency, in several trades with an eye toward some practical vocation, but
it was really in his youthful office as acolyte at the Convent of Augustinian
Nuns, where he served in the sacristy each morning, and not infrequently
elsewhere among other duties in the afternoon, that John’s lifelong love of the
Church very likely began. The often long and solitary hours spent in obligations
within the sacristy undoubtedly imbued the young John with a keen sense of the
sacred and an early formative acquaintance with an atmosphere of introspective
contemplation.
The Divine Summons
At sixteen, and now
working at the nearby Plague Hospital de la Concepcion, he had matriculated at
the Jesuit College at Medino del Campo where after four years of a liberal arts
education, he entered the Novitiate of the Carmelite Order in 1563 and, as was
the custom, assumed a new name, that of Juan de Santo Matia, or John of St.
Matthias. Upon professing solemn vows he undertook further study at the
Carmelite College at San Andrés which, rather auspiciously, was located at
Salamanca. Here Fray John had the opportunity to study under some of the finest
minds of late medieval Europe at the great University of Salamanca whose
reputation as a center of learning equaled, and in some respects surpassed, the
renowned medieval Universities of Paris and Oxford. Both at the College of San
Andrés and at the University of Salamanca, John had acquired an apparently
outstanding grasp of both Scholastic philosophy and theology, and in general
excelled in his studies to such a remarkable extent that, while yet a student,
he was appointed to the post of Prefect of Studies at San Andrés. In 1567 Fray
Juan de la Cruz took Holy Orders and entered the priesthood. On the auspicious
occasion of the celebration of his first Mass, which brought him to back his
hometown of Medina del Campo, he met Madre Teresa de Jesus --- better known as
St. Teresa of Avila.
This acquaintance --- not
entirely fortuitous, for St. Teresa had sought out the young priest who had been
recommended to her as a likely candidate to assist her in her efforts to reform
the Carmelite Order at large, friars as well as nuns --- evolved into a lifelong
friendship and alliance, and was to prove momentous to both the 52 year old
Carmelite Nun, and the young 25 year old priest whose deepening spirituality and
strong sense of interiority had compelled him at this point to consider
transferring from the Carmelites to the more austere and reclusive Carthusians.
But St. Teresa in short order succeeded in persuading the diminutive but intense
young friar that his vocation lay in the white mantle that presently stood upon
his shoulders, and not elsewhere; the Order of Our Lady, she insisted, must not
be abandoned, but reformed. And she had quite definite plans for effecting the
reform which the Mitigated Rule stood in such desperate need of, and John would
be instrumental in restoring the venerable Order to its Primitive Rule among the
friars in the way that St. Teresa had tirelessly labored to effect it among her
nuns at Valladolid. In 1568, in the company of three other Carmelite friars, St.
John changed his name at Duruelo from Juan de Santo Matia to Juan de la Cruz ---
and effectively entered upon the reform of the Order. The mutual vision and
reciprocal commitment, coupled with the deep and holy affection that bound the
younger John to the older Teresa, would sustain this collaborative effort for
many years and through much hardship.
It was not long before
the exemplary lives of the small community of reformed friars and nuns that had
gathered around St. John and St. Teresa respectively began attracting vocations,
and with the burgeoning reform, in which St. Teresa had been indefatigable, it
was inevitable that the friars and nuns of the Mitigated Rule who wished to
retain the individual latitude to which they had grown accustomed should respond
sometimes acrimoniously, even violently, to the vigorous threat which the zeal
of the reform had posed. From a larger perspective, however, the ensuing turmoil
--- and it was considerable --- cannot bbe laid entirely at the feet of St.
Teresa and St. John, though neither were loath to come to terms with the
consequences of their zeal, for the call to a general reform of all
Religious Orders had been issued by the Council of Trent a year earlier in 1568,
and was already in the process of being implemented by King Philip II in that
same year --- a reform, we must remember, itself precipitated by the
Counter-Reformation which had begun a mere 8 years earlier in 1560 under the
Papacy of Pius IV.
Reformatio in Capite et in Membris: The Counter-Reformation
Some brief overview of
this period is necessary, I think, to understanding the historical context from
which the reform efforts of both Saints took their impetus. The lax and
reproachable state of affairs, especially concerning discipline and morals, into
which highly profiled segments of the Church had fallen, had, of course,
precipitated the Reformation some years earlier, and what had been experienced
by the Church on a much larger scale had no less been the occasion of the lapse
in discipline in the religious orders in Spain as well. The formation and
training of the clergy at large had been seriously neglected in favor of the
decidedly more immediate and provincial interests of higher ecclesiastical
dignitaries and this regrettable state of affairs was often not unaccompanied by
moral turpitude. Members of the Papal Curia, no less than local bishops and
abbots, had come to understand and so exercise their authority in increasingly
secular terms, to the neglect and detriment of the primary spiritual offices
with which they were entrusted; offices which, at least as often as not, were as
instrumental to augmenting their income as to their acquiring the perquisites of
secular power. Entire cathedral chapters, whose ecclesiastics were beneficed
through endowments established to maintain the clergy, would often spuriously
combine prebends --- salaries intended to be distributed among the clergy
attached to the Cathedral --- within one individual, increasing his leverage in
both power and wealth. And conditions, regrettably, fared no better with the
Religious Orders themselves. Not infrequently, monasteries of religious women
were largely congregations of the unmarried daughters of the nobility, and for
many Orders, the original charism upon which the community had been founded, and
which had provided its raison d‘être, had been entirely lost in this
lapse of orientation, or the rule so seriously mitigated as to be
unrecognizable. A recognition of the impendence of this sorry state of affairs
had existed for some time and in fact dated at least as far back as the
14th century where the call pro reformatio in capite et in membris
2 had begun slowly gathering the initial momentum that would
culminate in the Counter-Reformation in 1560. St. John and St. Teresa, while
confining their efforts at reform to the Carmelite order in particular, may in
fact be seen not simply as the product of the Counter-Reformation, but as two of
the most brilliant, articulate, energetic and successful figures that the
Counter-Reformation had produced. The influence of their efforts extended well
beyond the cloisters of Carmel; indeed, well beyond the border of Spain and
continues to exert itself to the present day within the whole of Catholicism at
large. In any event, the reform which the two Saints had collaborated in
effecting resulted in some particularly bitter consequences for St. John who,
taken captive by the Calced Carmelites --- the friars of the mitigated rule,
who, unlike the newly reformed Discalced Carmelites, wore sandals, the latter
going barefooted, or discalced --- and refusing to renounce the reform, was
subsequently imprisoned at the Carmelite Priory in Toledo in 1577 for the better
part of a year. The room --- a closet actually --- that served as his cell, was
a meager 6 foot by 10 foot area, unheated, unventilated, and effectively
unilluminated except for a small crevice in one wall well above the head of the
spare and diminutive friar who, standing erectly, barely attained to five feet.
Subsisting only on bread and water and an occasional sardine, he was routinely
scourged, not by one, but by every present member of the Calced community
following their evening refection and returned to the darkness and cold --- or
stifling heat --- of his cell. Having nothing but the tattered clothes on his
wounded and unhealing back, no breviary, and probably most painfully, nothing
with which to confect the species through which he could celebrate Mass, St.
John was left with the outer darkness --- and the gathering inner light, a
combination which crystallized in the sublime poetry that has made the works of
St. John of the Cross not just classic in Spanish literature, but among the most
beautiful poetic works ever written.
Chronology of St. John’s Writings
After
six months closely confined and in great privation, St. John was providentially
assigned a new jailer, Fray Juan de Santa Maria, who was much more kindly
disposed toward the gentle St. than his previous incarcerator. He appears to
have allowed him oil and a lamp, and more importantly, paper and ink upon which
to write, and in general seems to have made every effort to alleviate the
condition of the straitened friar as much as was within his power to do so,
despite the severe sanctions, under provisions of the Order’s constitution, that
would have been applied against him, and with the same severity and exactitude
with which St. John himself had become intimately acquainted. At this time, St.
John composed the first thirty-one verses of his magnificent Spiritual
Canticle, and several less well-known poems. Two months later, in August of
1578, and under circumstances deemed by some to have been miraculous, St. John
managed to escape his captors and found refuge in Toledo with the reformed
Carmelite nuns who sheltered him from his pursuers, bringing him south to the
greater safety of El Calvario in Andalusia where he began composing the Dark
Night of the Soul and the Ascent of Mount Carmel upon which he worked
sporadically until their completion in 1585.
St.
John’s poetry, the magnificent and inimitable style of which contrasts so
sharply with his dense and often redundant
literary treatises, is widely considered among the most beautiful and
preeminent in all of Spanish literature to date. In fact, it is among the most
beautiful, most evocative of poetic literature in any language. As Fr. Kieran
Kavanaugh, O.C.D. correctly observes,
“St. John of
the Cross has received the title, “the loftiest poet of Spain”, not on account
of his books of poetry, but with some ten or twelve compositions. These
compositions, however, display such variety that it can almost be affirmed that
each of them represents a completely distinct poetic vision and technique, a
singular accomplishment in Spanish literature.”3
There are ten poems of
indubitable authenticity, all composed within a 14 year period preceding St.
John’s death in 1591. Regrettably, none of the original copies are extant. The
copies which do exist are incorporated into what is known as the Codex of
Sanlucar, which, while not in the hand of the Saint himself, were
nevertheless unquestionably reviewed and revised by St. John as attested to by
glosses and additions to the text which appear in the handwriting of St. John.
The authenticity of four other poems is also very likely. It is, I find, an
extreme irony --- even a paradox --- that one is more likely to arrive at a much
clearer intuition (not understanding) of something verging upon
the experience of unio mystica through any of these 14 poems, than
through all the protracted, carefully nuanced, and often involuted explications
which St. John offers us through the treatises we have examined in this work.
Here we have attained to consistency. In his poetry we attain to sublimity. The
poems of unquestionable authenticity are as follows:
·
The Spiritual
Canticle (Cantico
Espiritual)
·
The Dark Night
(Noche Oscura)
·
The Living Flame of
Love (Llama De Amor
Via)
·
I Entered in
Unknowing (Yo No Supe Dόnde
Entraba)
·
I Live, but Not in
Myself (Vivo sin Vivir en
Mi)
·
I Went Out Seeking
Love (Tras de un Amoroso
Lance)
·
A Lone Young
Shepherd (Un Pastorcico Solo Esta Penado)
·
For I Know Well the
Spring (Que Bien Sé Yo la
Fuente)
·
The
Romances (Romances
1-9)
·
On the Psalm: “By the
Waters of Babylon” (Romance Que Va Por
“Super flumina Babylonis” (Ps.
136)
The remaining four poems,
the authenticity of which cannot be definitively established but which very
likely were composed by St. John are:
·
Without Support and With
Support (Sin Arrimo y con
Arrimo)
·
Not for All of
Beauty (Por Toda la
Hermosura)
·
Del Verbo
Divino (Del Verbo
Divino)
·
The Sum of
Perfection (Suma De
Perfeccion)
These poems are
faithfully reproduced in Spanish and meticulously translated into English by Fr.
Kieran Kavanaugh O.C.D. and Fr. Otilio Rodriguez, O.C.D. in “The Collected
Works of St. John of the Cross” 4, which I highly recommend.
Death and Canonization
St. John, in the years
ensuing, was extremely active within the newly reformed order, holding a variety
of positions as confessor, vicar, Prior, Second Definitor, Vicar-Provincial,
Definitor and Consiliario, and Deputy-Vicar General --- to say nothing of the
great administrational skill he demonstrated as founder and rector of the
Carmelite College for the students of the Reform at Baeza. This activity,
however, was balanced by the contemplation he had patiently and diligently
acquired through spending long hours in prayer. As is often the case with great
saints no less than great men, the end of his life would find him persecuted by
the very cause for which he gave of himself entirely, patiently enduring the
spite of lesser men resentful of his irrepressible sanctity. Deprived, for his
conviction, of every office within the Reform, and in failing health, he
repaired to La Peñuela in 1591 only to learn that efforts were already under way
to expel the holy friar from the Reform itself which he had founded, and for
whose sake he had willingly suffered so much. This must have been a bitter
disappointment to St. John --- not to find himself despised and put to naught;
indeed, it was his wish to die alone, without title, and in obscurity --- but to
find his brothers in Christ at such a great distance from the heart of God, the
mind of Christ, in their enmity not just to him --- but to any man. It has
indeed been well put that in the Church where the lights are brightest, the
shadows are also deepest. St. Teresa, who had died some nine years earlier in
1582 would probably have come closest to understanding the heart of St. John at
this crucial and final point in his life, but was providentially spared the pain
of this ignominy. John, whose health continued to decline, and still under the
vow of obedience, was ordered to seek medical assistance which was available
both at Baez and Ubeda, and when presented with the choice opted for Ubeda
where, he felt, he was unknown and would be accorded no more consideration than
any other friar in failing health. But even in Ubeda, St. John’s reputation
preceded him, and despite his ill health, those both envious and suspicious of
his sanctity received him coldly, brusquely assigning him the poorest cell
available while taking pains to make clear to him the inconvenience and expense
incurred of necessity by his stay at the monastery. This must have troubled St.
John as much as the festering ulcerations that had by now progressed from his
legs to his back, and before long it became apparent that the small friar in the
most dismal cell was dying. Without reproach, and in the most earnest humility,
he begged pardon of those to whom he had become such an unwelcome burden, and
parting his lips finally, uttered the words of Christ on the Cross: “Lord, into
your hands I commend my spirit”, and with this, died. He was forty-nine. Within
eighty-four years of his death on December 14, 1591 St. John of the Cross was
beatified by Pope Clement X on January 25, 1675, subsequently canonized by Pope
Benedict XIII on December 26, 1726, and finally declared a Doctor of the Church
Universal by Pope Pius XI on August 24, 1926.
Something more must be
said of this great luminary, something vitally important to any adequate
assessment of the life of St. John. And it may be summed up simply in this: St.
John was a good man. For all the austerity to which he subjected himself
willingly and without murmur, his heart was singularly inaustere. Embracing
poverty, and the son of poverty from his earliest childhood, he was nevertheless
pained by the poverty he saw in others, even in the sometimes desperately poor
nuns of the Reformed and Primitive Rule for whom he himself would beg alms as a
father for his children. Knowing the needs of others, he never humiliated those
in want, but anticipating their need, set about to secure what was necessary for
them, knowing that they would never ask it for themselves. His concern, it is
important to note, did not extend simply to the spiritual welfare of
those with whom he came in contact: he saw the whole man, the entire woman, not
just the imago Dei sequestered behind the ephemerality of the flesh, but
the Sacred Humanity of Christ which ennobled the humanity of every person. His
eyes, St. Teresa tells us, were large and dark, and in St. John they were not
merely the portals to his own soul, but the lamps of compassion that burned with
a love that seemed to embrace the totality of the person who stood before him.
The hunger that gnawed at the stomachs of his penitents was just as real as the
cancer of sin he sought to excise from their souls in the holy tribunal of
penance. The illness that racked the bodies of men and women was every bit as
real as the spiritual sickness that plagued their souls, and he sought to remedy
both as much as it was in his power to do so. His life, in short, was conformed
to the life of Christ who not simply forgave sins, but healed the sinner, and
who, in the succinct words of the Apostle Peter, went about doing
good.5 St. John, in a word, was the faithful steward whose will
was to do the will of the Master. And these who gathered around him, Carmelite
and lay, would in the end be called home through the same night to the same
House by the same Father, in the one same unquenchable light that, consuming all
else in a holocaust of love, ultimately reveals the face of
God.
1
Mk.
8.33
2 literally, a
reform of the head and the members.
3
The Collected
Works of St. John of the Cross, p.709,
Kieran Kavanaugh, O.C.D. and Otilio Rodriguez, O.C.D., ICS Publications,
Institute of Carmelite Studies, Washington, D.C., 1979
4 op.
cit.
5 Acts
10.38
(Continued below)
EPILOGUE
In the end, something vital remains to be said about the
enduring phenomenon of mystical experience itself. It has little to do
with epistemology or metaphysics --- which at best are only so many superficial
tangents to the sublime experience which, we have seen, remains impenetrable to
reason. We are, I think, mistakenly inclined to see this deeply personal and
profoundly religious experience as somehow confined to the lives of a few
remarkable individuals who by and large have been saints in a strictly canonical
sense. We are intimidated by what we perceive to be the austerity of the lives
they had lived, and tend to see them as persons quite apart from ourselves ---
and quite fortunately so. Very likely we are acquainted with one narrative or
another detailing the severity of the lives they had lived --- accounts
sometimes embellished, as all hagiography to some extent is --- with the great
trials and hardships they endured in an adamantine faith that appears quite
impossible to most of us. They are figures who loom largely in unforgettable but
nevertheless dusty tomes from an age of faith as distant from us as the
alchemist’s art.
As a consequence, we tend
to consign the experience that shaped and ultimately defined their lives to the
same reliquary to which we reverently, but no less resolutely, shelf these
abstruse speculative systems together with the devout biographies that accompany
them --- for it no longer seems viable in our age or even possible in our lives.
In short, the great mystical enterprise; indeed, the mystical phenomenon itself,
tends to be perceived
essentially as an
historical phenomenon. This, I think, is due in large part to the
emphasis placed upon the medieval mystics who, not surprisingly, had flourished
in an age of faith, an age in which the Church predominated and whose every
institution to some extent understood itself in relation to God. It was,
moreover, the medieval mystics who had succeeded in systematically formulating
this ancient doctrine into a viable Christian synthesis around which, at least
implicitly, entire contemplative communities were subsequently formed. The goal,
after all, of every contemplative is contemplation --- and perfect contemplation
culminates in union. These most conspicuous figures in the history of mysticism,
confined to a fixed and distant era, seem --- with few notable exceptions since
--- to have formed the terminus of a traadition whose impulse had somehow
withered with the dawn of the Renaissance. But this, of course, is not true. The
many Discalced Carmelite monasteries throughout the world --- which have not
merely survived, but have flourished --- are extraordinary testimonies to the
vibrant continuity of this tradition. They, and other contemplative orders ---
to say nothing of the lives of many individuals living contemplatively within
the world at large --- are reminders in this postmodern era that the ancient
mystical impulse is indomitable, incessant, irrepressible --- even
eternal.
In the end, I think that
the invitation to union is far more common than we suppose. I further think that
the basic intuition underlying the experience of this invitation is, however
indistinctly --- and however reluctant we are to concede it --- perceived as
God. I am equally persuaded, however, that it is a perception we are likely to
distort, resist, or even arrogantly dismiss. The reasons for this, to be sure,
are many and varied. But I also think that this invitation leaves an indelible
impression. However successful we are in explaining it away, this unmistakable
invitation, I am convinced, is etched into the heart by God Himself, and
continues to beckon us, despite the disdain, even the reproach of reason, to
something beyond ourselves, something infinitely greater than our selves. And
our reluctance to respond to this invitation seems, in the end, to be rooted in
fear; the fear that, in the words of Archbishop Fulton Sheen, “if we give Him
our finger, He will take our whole hand.” In an age that blenches before any
absolute commitment whatever, many of us simply are not prepared to make a
commitment as absolute as the invitation requires. For ultimately, we realize,
it entails far more than our hand, or even our heart, embracing, as it does, the
totality of our being in the totality of His love.
~ END ~
The Author
The author studied
philosophy in the Bachelor’s, Master’s, and Doctoral programs at Boston
University. The Metaphysics received the Imprimatur and Nihil
Obstat from the Censor Librorum of the Archdiocese of Boston in an
earlier redaction.