Paine the Propagandist, and Burke the valuable political theorist?

 

 

The Age of Enlightenment was a self-conscious, idealistic movement which did away with groundless superstitions, and espoused the value of man’s faculty for rational thought[1]. It ended in the madness of the Terror in France during 1794. Men’s ‘reason’ was hard to maintain when confronted by the senseless killing which started in Paris, and with the Napoleonic wars, which engulfed Europe. Thomas Paine and Edmund Burke were two popular political writers who wrote before the Terror began. Both had strong views on the way Europe should react to the toppling of the monarchy in France. However, although Paine commanded more attention at the time, his ideas have been dismissed, whereas Burke is usually remembered as the more important political writer. This essay goes part of the way to describing why this state of affairs came about, and why Paine should be given more recognition as a political theorist.

 

First of all, the ‘Burke-Paine debate’ is a misnomer because there was never any dialogue between the two men. Burke published Reflections[2] in England in 1790 and Paine responded with Rights of Man[3] which appeared in two parts, in November 1791 (England) and February 1792 (written in France).

 

Paine’s work broke every existing publishing record, and may still hold that record[4]. Four or five hundred thousand copies of The Rights of Man (1791) sold in one year in the UK and Ireland. Given that literacy was not what it is today the figures are quite staggering. Burke sold 40,000 copies of his Reflections on the French Revolution which came out at that same time, and was funded and supported by the King. Reflections generated around 50 responses, one of which was The Rights of Man. In its turn The Rights of Man caused a larger stir of approximately 500 responses. The ideas were of interest to common men and officials alike. To put this in a local perspective the readership “certainly included Arthur Phillip and the governors that followed him” [5].

 

In relation to the potential he had to influence mass opinion, he attracted little attention from the mainstream academic press. The main reason for this is because he is considered a propagandist rather than a bona fide political theorist. He was a propagandist by self-admission, but this does not preclude his ideas from being of value. There are many reasons for his absence in the political science field, this is one of them. Some of them stem from Paine himself, and how he alienated himself towards the end of his life[6]. Recently, in the last twenty years, there has been a belated acknowledgement of Paine’s legacy, but it has been slow in coming, and still has a long way to go.

 

Burke’s commentators were much kinder, and he is commonly given as the next chapter of political thought after Hume. He did not sell as well as Paine, but his progressive utilitarian views and his more complicated language gave him credos with academics. Burke wrote for a more educated sector of society, evident from the text itself[7], which may have distinguished him from a ‘propagandist’. He also wrote for an audience which was justified in reading his views after the French Revolution went awry as he had predicted. His views are drawn upon by modern conservative thinkers, which has a stalwart following in present day ‘Thatcherites’[8].

 

In opposition to the positive attention Burke has received, Paine has mostly had two hundred years of negative press. Especially harmful to his long-term reputation has been the exclusion from serious works on political theory:

 

“A typical account from the 1930s devotes one paragraph of an 800 page study of the events of 1776 to Paine, dismisses Common Sense as ‘a useless study in monarchy’ and an ‘unpractical attempt to at laying down a system of government’ and concludes only grudgingly ‘whatever Paine’s lack of personal merit, it must be admitted he did a great service to his times’.”[9]

 

This suppression started as soon as Paine was jailed in 1794. It took root quickly in America (in England the book has been banned as soon as it was published and remained so), which should have been Paine’s most popular market,

 

“It must have been painful to the feelings of every honest man to think that the writing of Mr. Paine … should have been so near a total extinction as to be found no where for sale, but in clandestine manner and at an exorbitant price” (publisher’s preface to the 1817 edition of a collected works)[10]

 

Paine’s biographers preface their books and articles by the wrongs they must redress, even in the present day, 

 

“The bicentenary of the publication of Thomas Paine’s Right of Man (1791-2) has come and gone, silently and obscurely. No new monuments to Paine were unveiled (even the Post Office got into the spirit of things by refusing to issue a commemorative stamp) and conservative historians continued to poke at British radical traditions with evidence of ‘popular’ opposition to Paine’s politics” [11]

 

Of course, to gain a place for Paine in the political theory books, it is necessary to show that he contributed new ideas. His place in the history books will eventually be secured by the uncontestable popularity of his work,  this does not necessarily mean that he will stand side by side, on an intellectual level, with men such as Hobbes and Locke. In the past Paine has been denied academic standing because of the conception that he was solely a propagandist. He probably considered himself as a ‘propagandist’, whose duty was to the men around him rather than to posterity. He wrote towards a tangible political end, there is no doubt. He issued cheap editions and re-invested his royalties in other publications. Just because he appealed to working people does not lead to a  conclusion that he was a mere ‘propagandist’, or that he did not put forward anything of theoretical significance.

 

The first negative blow may be dealt by calling Tom Paine a ‘second-hand Locke’;  that he was repeating and paraphrasing Lockean theory. This is backed up by the fact that Tom Paine said never read Locke[12],

 

 “I never read Locke, … and by what I have heard of it from Horne Tooke [a friend], I had no inducement to read it . It is a speculative, not a practical work, and the style of it is heavy and tedious.”

 

Instead he was influenced by second-hand sources,

 

“It is impossible to identify the influence which such men as Condorcet, Paine and Godwin mutually exerted upon one another. But the evidence points to a significant intellectual relationship among them, and to a common stock of ideas developing from Locke and the English Revolution…”[13]

 

Locke, like Paine, recognised the value of “reason” or “common sense” as opposed to blind faith. Locke said belief in God was not founded in reason, but he said that reason was not incompatible with belief, and that man should go ahead confident that empirical data would complement his faith rather than destroy it. The 1700s was to see the rise of popular, useful scientific culture, and Locke paved the way for scientists to work earnestly without worrying about reconciling empirical and theological matters. He created a convenient distance between God and the fields of scientific enquiry. In turn, Paine would advocate the division of the church from the state when he gave advice on the American constitution.

 

Locke still clung onto notions of ‘natural law’ and self-evident truths, which were taken up by Paine, but denied by Burke[14].

 

“The same spark of the divine nature and knowledge in man, which, making him a man, showed him the law he was under, as a man”.[15]

 

So Locke did not divorce himself from notions of the ‘divine’. Neither did Paine, although he did not use the word ‘divine’. He used words like ‘self-evident’. Such words highlighted that although Paine and Locke were progressive thinkers, they still refused to get rid of the safety valve which guaranteed fundamental rights, even though they might prove unprofitable for society . On the other hand, the utilitarian view, epitomised by Jeremy Bentham described any attempt to justify natural rights as “nonsense on stilts”[16].

 

Rousseau, a natural sceptic, was the first to attack natural law, albeit piecemeal,

 

“Rousseau attacked only one limited segment of the system of natural law, the artificiality of seeing society merely as an agent to secure individual goods … had Rousseau stood alone, the imposing system of natural law elaborated in a century and a half of philosophical development, would hardly have fallen…”[17]

 

Burke would draw very heavily on Rousseau’s development of ‘social contract’ theory, and also on his negative stand on innate human rights. Instrumental in bringing Rousseau’s sceptical ideas to fruition was David Hume’s 1749 essay, Treatise of Human Nature. He outlined three categories of knowledge: pure,  (eg. The extrapolation of mathematical axioms), empirical (eg. physics), and religious. The last two he said were grounded in subjectivity. Hume’s ground breaking piece classified the last category, faith in God and natural laws, as nothing but sentiment. Richard Carlyle called the idea “a flat thrashing-floor for logic, whereon all questions, from the doctrine of rent to the natural history of religion, are thrashed and sifted with the same mechanical impartiality”[18]. Hume completed the theory of shredding concepts of the ‘divine’ in favour of ‘utility’[19]. Burke was firmly in this utilitarian camp[20].

 

So it is incorrect to paint Paine as the radical and Burke as the conservative. Historically they are so, but theoretically Burke took a more ‘enlightened’ stance, drawing on Hume and Rousseau. But Burke also refused to quote his sources, as Thomas Paine had done with Locke,

 

“I assure you I am not at singularity. I give you opinions which have been accepted among us, from very early times up to his moment , which a continued and general approbation, and which indeed are worked into my mind that I am unable to distinguish what I have learned from others from the results of my own meditation”.[21]

 

Which is a fancy way of saying he cannot be bothered crediting men with the ideas he has put forward. Paine too, had an arrogant streak in him,

 

“I rarely quote; the reason is, I always think”

 

and boasted that he,

 

“neither read books, nor studied other people’s opinions”[22]

 

This attitude is certainly no longer considered admirable, but served a political purpose. Gwyn Williams said that “His independence seemingly proved that the common man needed to political or intellectual theories to comprehend and challenge relations of power”[23]. However Paine may have been lying when he said that he had never published anything before Common Sense and that he never read books. Both these claims should be eyed with suspicion. From lesser known pamphlets and letters there is evidence that he was familiar with Locke, Montesquieu, Rousseau and Adam Smith [24]. To what extent he was versed in political theory is uncertain.

 

Burke was a good friend of Adam Smith[25], and used the term ‘social contract’, straight from the texts of Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau, who wrote a book on the subject. Burke was definitely an avid reader of the classics, and interested in politics because of his place in Parliament. Again, however it is impossible to nail down the specifics of his political education.

 

Paine and Burke’s ‘debate’ was heated because of they were arguing over the way the world should be shaped in a time when the future seemed imminently malleable. Burke had supported the American revolution, and he was a member of the Whig party (as opposed to the conservative party, the Tories). Burke surprised Paine when he wrote Reflections, because Paine thought Burke was a reformist. Lord Acton recognised Burke’s paradox:

 

“[Burke] not an entire liberal? How thoroughly he wished for liberty – of conscience – property, trade, slavery, etc. What stood against it? His notion of history. The claims of the past. The authority of time. The will of the dead. Continuity.”[26]

 

Reflections seemed out of place with Burke’s previous democratic sentiments. Maybe this is why the first few pages of Rights of Man are written in such a vehement tone, because Paine is chastising someone ‘who should have known better’.

 

The battle between the two documents revolves around how nations should respond to a their people when they want reform. Burke thought the traditional system of government was greater than the will people who lived under it, and Paine thought that all government’s power came from the collective’s self-evident right to determine their future, and thus could change it at any time. Burke saw government as a gradual progression through the ages, safe-guarding virtue and scientific advancement. He thought change in the system should come from above, organically, not in violent revolution. In Reflections there are strong arguments that are still relevant to conservative politics in the modern age[27]. He adopted the ‘social contract’ theory, which was popular with political theorists to justify keeping the status quo[28]. The populace and actual government of the day have a contract with the established system of government. Neither should emphasise their contemporary rights to topple the system. To change the structure of the community by emphasising individual rights was to descend into “madness, discord, vice, confusion and unavailing sorrow”[29].

 

This is similar to constitutional imperative Australia that the population does not have the right to revolution, and that we should pay reverence  to our evolved political systems that derived from the British system. Burke’s view is alive and well in schools and in the community because it is founded in conservatism and results in stability. If the Parliament were to put a prohibitive tax on food and people were starving then men and women might not be so complacent. Burke never outlined how the French should have acted under the absolute corruption of Louis XVI’s rule. He said rather cold-heartedly that revolution, even to overthrow corruption, is not justifiable,

 

“[the necessity = revolution in dire circumstances] This necessity is no exception to the rule [the rule of continuity]; because this necessity itself is a part too of that moral and physical disposition of things to which man must be obedient by consent or force; but if that which is only submission to necessity should be made the object of choice, the law is broken, nature is disobeyed, and the rebellious are outlawed, cast forth, exiled, from this world of reason, and order, and peace and virtue, and fruitful penitence into the antagonistic world of madness…etc…”[30]

 

and more,

 

“he should approach to the faults of the state as to the wounds of the father, with pious awe and trembling solicitude”[31]

 

This was unrealistic and Paine was ruthless in his counter-attack. He was a firm believe in natural rights, and the right to overthrow an unjust government. Burke had seeming cut off the “escape hatch” which theorists like Locke had always included – the right to resist if things got unbearable. Paine detested Burke’s notion that living men could be ruled over by the dead men who originally set up the system,

 

“There never did, nor never can exist a parliament,  or any description of men, or any generation of men, in any country, possessed of the right or the power of binding or controlling posterity to the ‘end of time’”[32]

 

Thomas Paine put this on grounds of natural rights,

 

“it is authority against authority all the way, till we come to the divine origin of the rights of man, at the creation… If  a dispute about the rights of man had arisen at the distance of an hundred years from the creation, it is to this source of authority they must have referred, and it is to the same source of authority that we must now refer.”[33]

 

He brought into play the notion of natural law, whereas Burke, taking the more ‘conservative’ stance, had dispensed with it altogether. Burke’s argument relied on Hume’s utilitarian justification, that a traditional system was best because it served its people best.

 

Paine never saw utilitarianism as an over-riding principle, but one which would always be put below the rights of individual citizens. Both the US Declaration of Independence 1776 and the more thorough French equivalent, The Rights of Man and The Citizen 1789, owe much to his thinking[34]. If we compare this to Hume’s utility principle, we can see that Paine has lapsed into an less ‘enlightened’ stance, even though the practical effect of his theories is more radical – to secure rights even when they are unprofitable for society as a whole. Because of this, Burke and Bentham were considered the natural successors in the anti-Lockean movement, rather than Paine, who was anachronistic (in the area of rights). It is understandable that many authors[35] chose the progression Hobbes, Locke, Hume, Burke, Bentham. Thomas Paine interrupted the flow, and it was convenient to side-line him.

 

In many cases it is ignored that Burke sometimes lapsed into horribly sentimental arguments, many of which did not make sense. Reflections  is more emotional than Rights of Man. For instance about Marie-Antoinette he wrote,

 

“I thought ten thousand men must have leaped from their scabbards to avenge a even a look that threatened her with insult. – But the age of chivalry is gone – that of sophisters, oeconomists, and calculators have succeeded. etc…etc…” [36]

And so forth, glorifying the Queen of France for a full page. Another piece that stands out is,


“The anodyne draught of oblivion, thus drugged, is well calculated to preserve a galling wakefulness, and to feed the living ulcer of a corroding memory. Thus to administer the opiate potion of amnesty, powdered with all the ingredients of scorn and contempt, is to hold to his lips, instead of the ‘balm of hurt minds’, the cup of human misery to the brim, and to force him to drink it to the dregs.”

 

Burke is moved by the momentous upheaval of the French Revolution, who felt its force as much as Paine. Both their works intended to influence popular opinion. The only difference is that Paine used a simpler language so that all men could understand him. The only sources he assumed his audience had knowledge of was the Bible and the Book of Common Prayer[37]. He renounced an elitist approach and this reflected in his wider readership. Paine used rhetoric but he used his old ruse of ‘common-sense’, a commoner’s truth readily understandable to a fellow commoner[38]. Rights of Man used “rhetoric to hide rhetoric”[39].

 

Apart from the high-flown language, Burke’s manuscript is also jumbled, having no structure or shape[40]. Even more damning are his contradictory statements. He is passionate about keeping the constitutional monarchy in England, but cannot help being the progressive thinker who supported the American Revolution’s rejection of the monarchy. This leads to unclear thought,

 

“There is something manic, even schizoid, in Burke’s endless shifts of moods and positions. Just at the very moment when one thinks one has located him, Burke slips away and reappears somewhere else – the effect being that ‘where Burke is, you cannot be’, or that game of ‘scissors, paper, stone’, where each discrete element either caps or is capped by one of the others”. [41]

 

The same could not be said about Paine, whose Rights of Man is structured to deal with Burke on a point-by-point basis. In fact Rights of Man set readily understandable principles which were fitted in neatly with each other. Its propaganda value was thus ensured.

 

Paine’s originality is a hard subject to discuss, because as discussed above, he did not cite other’s opinions. Historians with must sort out what is original by looking at the ideas and comparing them with previous literature. John Keane has said that Paine’s divergences from old authority are today “so obvious that their originality is often over-looked”[42].

 

Paine was the first man to look at how power relationships at a national level affect the family as a basic unit of society[43],

 

“[Paine] emphasised how despotic states foster the power of men over women and children within households. Despotic states presuppose despotic households, in which the arbitrary exercise of power fathers – who, for instance, bequeath property to their firstborn sons – reinforces what Paine called ‘family tyranny and injustice’”[44].

 

Today the catchword in feminist studies is ‘patriarchy’, and Paine goes unrecognised. Also highly original is his link of despotic governments to their penchant for war. Previous thinkers had regarded war as a ‘sad necessity’. Rights of Man was the first to describe this relationship properly.[45]  

 

Paine also advocated a system of welfare. Paine wanted to reduce the role of government as much as possible, to make it ‘cheap, efficient’, but saw that people needed security if there was to be ultimate peace between citizens and nation states[46]. Paine regarded care of the elderly, widowed, single mothers, the unemployed, “not of the nature of a charity, but of a right”[47]. He considered this the best policy, because citizens with rights to a certain level of comfort would never choose to go to war, thus securing peace from the bottom up[48]  . This argument shows that Paine was a utilitarian, but one who came at the problem from a different angle[49]. He came closer to Rousseau’s ideal state than anybody previously:

 

“a form of association which will defend and protect with the whole common force the person and goods of each associate and in which each, whilst uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone and be as free as before”[50].

 

The cutting question was put by a modern human-rights advocate,

 

“Is it possible that the claims of human rights may be incompatible with the good of social utility? … can the doctrine of human rights be more coherently and plausibly formulated by the theory of utilitarianism?”[51]

 

This question is absolutely crucial if human rights are to be recognised by the international community. Paine had already alluded to a compatible state where rights and utility would ultimately be the same thing – the maximum utility would arise out of honouring people’s dignity as human beings.

 

Paine’s theory that there would be an absence of war in a true democracy that safe-guarded its citizens’ welfare leads into Paine’s internationalist ideas. Internationalism became unpopular during the War (1796-1815) and afterwards with the rise of strong nationalistic movements in the 19th century. Now that trend may be reversing. Ian Dyck sees the European Union as greatly in debt to Paine, who was committed to free trade between the countries in a capitalist system[52]. Furthermore it seems like the United Nations was also foreshadowed by Paine,

 

“Paine was certain that democratic republican states, guided by civil societies held together by reciprocal interests and mutual affection,  would make for a new global order free from the curse of war”[53]

 

Dyck says that the refusal of the EU to recognise Paine is due to “fear that the enquiry will rattle some skeletons in our ideological closets”[54]. This is easy to see what these skeletons might be when one looks at Paine’s sweeping idealism:

 

“The true idea of a great nation, is that which extends and promotes the principles of a universal society, whose mind rises above the atmosphere of local thoughts, and considers mankind, of whatever nation or profession they may be, as the work of one Creator.”[55]

 

Paine’s world view is a bit too idealistic (communist?) to be endorsed by New York or Brussels. In fact it is Burke who has seen a renewed interest in his writings after the collapse of the Berlin Wall and the rise of economic rationalism[56]. One commentator thinks this is because Burke can be used to justify a wide-range of policies, but sees reference to him as an indictment of the referee,

 

“Seeking support from Burke today, is the very act of launching what seems to be a most thrusting indictment of government policies: “To tell people that they are relieved by the dilapidation of their public estate, is a cruel and insolent imposition” [Burke] one trips over some under pronouncement equally supportive of those policies: “To provide for us in our necessities is not the power of government … The labouring people are poor because they are numerous’ [Burke]”[57]

 

It is clear that Paine should have his place in the books as a bona fide political theorist alongside his contemporary, Burke. One of the major problems is that there is not much political benefit in promoting Thomas Paine, either from a left-wing, right-wing or a religious standpoint. He is incompatible with all the major ideologies. Another is that he once he started to be ignored, he tended to be ignored in the present out of deference to the text-book writers of the past. That trend is being reversed slowly, but the account has not yet been settled, and probably will not be settled for years to come.

 

 



[1] Peter Hulme and Ludmilla Jordanova, The Enlightenment and Its Shadows, ed. Hulme, Jordanova, Routledge, London, 1990, p.1

[2] The full title being Reflections on the Revolution in France and on the Proceedings in Certain Societies in London Relative to That Event in a Letter Intended to Have Been Sent to a Gentleman in Paris, 1790

[3] This title came from a popular song about a miner who had been treated badly by his landlord,

 

“Ye landlords vile whose man’s peace mar,

come levy rents here if you can;

Your stewards and lawyers I defy,

And live with the Rights of Man”

 

See John Keane,  “Thomas Paine: A Political Life”, Bloomsbury, London, 1995, p. 306

[4] “the most widely read book of all time in any language” – John Keane, p. 307. (Keane must mean  non-state, or non-organisational funded literature by this comment ie. The bible, Mao’s Little Red Book).

[5] Marion Aveling, “Imagining New South Wales as a Gendered Society 1783-1821”, Australian Historical Studies, 1992 (25), p.5

[6] For instance, publication of the Age of Reason, an anti-religious, but strongly spiritual text. Also his open letter to the newspapers blaming Washington for his imprisonment. This essay doesn’t go into biographical detail, but Paine did not help his cause by alienating himself from his fellow Americans (who adored Washington, and often had religious beliefs).

[7] Long quotes in Latin, references to Cicero, etc…

[8] Margaret Thatcher was a Tory PM who opposed to Britain entering the EU, and also cut welfare programmes. See JD Fair and JA Hutcheson Jr  “British Conservatism in the Twentieth Century: An Emerging Ideological Tradition”, Albion, 1987 19(4), p.1.

[9] Gregory Claeys, “Thomas Paine”, Unwin, US, 1989, p. 3

[10] The edition funded by Richard Carlyle, See George Spater, “The Legacy of Paine”, Citizen of the World, ed. Ian Dyck, Helm Books, London, 1987, p. 24,  p.145

[11] Ian Dyck, “Local Attachments, National Identities and World Citizenship in the Thought of Thomas Paine.”, History Workshop Journal  (UK), 1993 (35) p.117

[12] See George Spater “American Revolutionary 1774-1789”, Citizen of the World, ed. Ian Dyck, Helm Books, London, 1987, p. 24.

[13] Ian Dyck, op cit, p.56.

[14] Burke’s writings are unclear, as Burke admitted this himself. When reading Burke there are some passages which allude to the natural law, but he is not using them in the natural law sense. Burke’s Reflections is a confusing document if read from cover to cover.

[15] RW Harris, Reason and Nature in the 18th Century, Blanford Press, London, 1968, p.76

[16] Jeremy Bentham, “Anarchical Fallacies; being an examination of the Declaration of Rights issues during the French Revolution”, in Jeremy Waldon, Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man, Methuen, US, 1987, p.69

[17] GH Sabine, A History of Political Theory, 1941, Harraps, p. 597

[18] G.H. Sabine op cit, p.606

[19] GH Sabine, ibid. Hume, Burke and Bentham were the foremost propounders of utility.

[20] Burke’s references to “God” are purely rhetorical, because Burke is trying to appeal to many segments of the community as possible. Any study of the underlying structure of his theories will confirm that Burke relegated God to the church, not to the political system.

[21] Edmund Burke, Reflections op cit p. 87

[22] See Gregory Claeys, “Thomas Paine”, Unwin, US, 1989, p. 85

[23] ibid.

[24] Gregory Claeys, op cit.  p. 86

[25] JA Pocock, in his introduction to Reflections on The Revolution in France, Hackett Pub., US, 1987, p.xlvii

[26] Lord Acton, quoted in JD Fair and JA Hutcheson Jr’s article “British Conservatism in the Twentieth Century: An Emerging Ideological Tradition”, Albion, 1987 19(4), p.1.

[27] See JD Fair and JA Hutcheson Jr’s “British Conservatism in the Twentieth Century: An Emerging Ideological Tradition”, ibid.

[28] Ian Hampsher-Monk, Modern Political Thought, 1992, Blackwell Publishers, UK, p.5.

[29] Edmund Burke, quoted by David Musselwhite, op cit. p.152

[30] Edmund Burke, Reflections on The Revolution in France, Hackett Press, US, 1987,  p.85

[31] Edmund Burke, op cit,  p.84.

[32] Thomas Paine, “The Rights of Man”, Basic writings of Thomas Paine : Common Sense. Rights of Man. Age of Reason, ed. N.Y., Willey, US, 1942 (Each vol. has separate pagination) p. 4

[33] Thomas Paine, op cit., p.34

[34] The extent of influence is unclear. He influenced Jefferson personally with his Common Sense papers, and was in contact with La Fayette’s circle of framers by mail. For many years he was thought to have written the Declaration of Independence, and a minority of historians still cling to the view that he co-authored it.  See John Keane, p.560n.70,  George Slater “European Revolutionary 1789-1809”,  Citizen of the World, ed. Ian Dyck, Helm Books, London, 1987, p. 53.

[35] For instance GH Sabine, and Iain Hampsher-Monk, two staple texts used over decades at Oxford and University of Sydney. The 1943 edition of Sabine omits Paine entirely.

[36] David Musselwhite, “Reflections on Burke’s Reflections”, The Enlightenment and its Shadows, ed. P. Hulme and L. Jordanova, Routledge, London, p.149

[37] John Keane, op cit. p. 296

[38] “It is illuminating that he [Paine] should not have taken issue with Burke’s description of the English people as a people of great ‘simplicity’, ‘untaught feelings’, ‘old prejudices’ and ‘native plainess’ – the reason being that Paine agreed with this caricature”, See Ian Dyck, op cit p.127

[39] ibid.

[40] “which perhaps the ‘letter’ format is designed to excuse”, Hampsher-Monk, op cit. p. 263

[41] David Musselwhite, op cit. p.143

[42] John Keane, op cit. p.298

[43] These kind of statements led into Mary Wollstonecrafts’ more specialised piece, Vindication of the Rights of Women. 1792. She was a supporter of the revolution.

[44]  From The Rights of Man, paraphrased by John Keane, op cit, p.297.

[45] Which is now popularly attributed to Marx and Engels. See John Keane, op cit., p. 298.

[46] John Keane, p.303.

[47] The Jacobin version Rights of Man and The Citizen  (passed 23 June 1793) incorporated these services as rights. Also the UN Declaration on Human Rights, Art.25. See Michael Freeman, “Human Rights and The Corruption of Governments”, The Enlightenment and its Shadows, ed. P. Hulme and L. Jordanova, Routledge, London, p.177

[48] John Keane, op cit. p.304

[49] Bentham realised that there is no definition of ‘utility’. It is in itself a rather subjective concept, even when described in terms of ‘Pain’ and ‘Pleasure’. It is probably best seen as an approach, rather than a science. See Douglas Long, Bentham On Liberty: Jeremy Bentham’s idea of liberty in relation to his utilitarianism, Canada, University of Toronto Press, 1977

[50] Jean Jacques Rousseau, in Iain Hampsher-Monk, op cit. , p. 157.

[51] Michael Freeman, “Human Rights and the Corruption of Governments 1789-1989”, The Enlightenment and its Shadows, ed. P. Hulme and L. Jordanova, Routledge, London, p.169.

[52] Ian Dyck,, op cit, p.118

[53] John Kean, op cit. p.304. This idea manifested itself first in Paine’s Letter to Abbé Raynal, as early as 1782, Ian Dyck points out (op cit p. 122).

[54] Ian Dyck, op cit. p.118.

[55] Ian Dyck ibid.

[56] Hampsher-Monk, op cit. p.261

[57] David Musselwhite op cit, p.142-143

1