Rationally Speaking
A monthly e-column
by Massimo Pigliucci
Department of Botany,
University of Tennessee
N. 4, November 2000 - "Intelligent Design - the Classical
Argument"
"In crossing
a heath, suppose I pitched my foot against a stone and were asked
how the stone came to be there, I might possibly answer that for anything
I knew to the contrary it had lain there forever.... But suppose I
had found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the
watch happened to be in that place, I should hardly think of the answer
which I had before given, that for anything I knew the watch might
have always been there."
These famous words were written in 1831 by the Reverend
William Paley (in Natural Theology: or, Evidences of the Existence
and Attributes of the Deity, Collected from the Appearances of Nature)
and constitute the best-known rendition of the classical argument
from design for the existence of god. Essentially, Paley said that
nobody would necessarily invoke a supernatural designer in order to
account for the existence of simple rocks, but complex and marvelously
functional objects such as eyes beg for an explanation that transcends
natural laws. If there is a watch, there was a watchmaker; ergo, if
there is an eye, there must have been an intelligent designer of that
eye.
Unfortunately
for Paley, the famous skeptic philosopher David Hume had already refuted
his argument, more than 50 years before Paley's formulation. In his
Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Hume left it to his
legendary character, Philo, to concisely explain what is wrong with
the argument from design:
"The world plainly
resembles more an animal or a vegetable than it does a watch or knitting-loom.
Its cause, therefore, it is more probable, resembles the cause of
the former. The cause of the former is generation or vegetation."
It is interesting
that the argument from design is still the most popularly cited reason
for why people believe in god according to a survey by Michael Shermer
published in How We Believe (2000). It is therefore important
for us to examine more closely the structure of Hume's critique and
understand where exactly the intelligent design argument falls flat.
In the exposition below I will add my commentary and examples to clarify
each point, given that Hume's language is at times obscure and obviously
not up to date on our current knowledge of the physical universe.
One can discern
six objections to the argument from intelligent design in a complete
reading of Hume's Dialogue:
1.
1 - The analogy between the universe and human artifacts is
not convincing.
In the quotation above, Hume does not think that the universe resembles
a complex machine at all. While the regularity of the laws of nature
may superficially inspire the analogy, human artifacts are always
clearly designed for a function. It often takes quite a bit of imagination
to see what the purpose of some aspects of the universe really is.
Biologist J.B.S. Haldane once answered a reporter who asked what his
study of genetics told him about God: "He must have an inordinate
fondness for beetles," referring to the hundreds of thousands of species
of these insects existing for no apparent purpose other than their
own reproduction.
2.
2 - Intelligence is only one of the active causes in the world.
Many natural
phenomena obviously do not require intelligence to occur. Tides, for
example, would hardly make a good choice for Paley, since their explanation
in terms of simple gravitational interactions does not require any
intelligent design.
3.
3 - Even if intelligence is everywhere operative now, it does
not follow that we can ascribe to it the origins of the universe.
This is logically true, and can be illustrated in modern terms if
we imagine that somebody one day demonstrates that life on Earth was
seeded by a race of extremely intelligent extraterrestrials. This,
of course, would not make them gods, and would not provide an explanation
for the origin of the extraterrestrials, nor for the universe as a
whole. In fact, humans may someday do something of the sort, without
because of this being elevated to divine status (other than perhaps
by the simple-minded results of our own experiments).
4.
4 - The origin of the universe is a single unique case and
so analogies are pointless.
This is a subtle but very good point: while we have plenty of natural
objects, organisms and human artifacts, we only have one universe.
Science can derive meaningful analogies by comparing populations
of objects or entities. While we may compare and contrast the attributes
of rocks, eyes, tides and watches, to what shall we compare the universe?
Anything we might think of would be comparing a part of the whole
to the whole itself, and we are unable to find another self-contained
whole for comparison. We may conceive of an omnipresent god as an
analogy for the universe, but unfortunately the analogy offers no
insights of scientific value. It is also unlikely that the analogy
would help theology. Is god spherical or doughnut-shaped? Will god
expand forever from an explosive beginning, or does god alternate
through phases of expansion and contraction?
5.
5 - The analogy between human and divine mind is clearly anthropomorphic.
Nature resembles a mindless organism rather than a purposeful and
intelligent one.
This is another way to put objection #1, this time by highlighting
the parochialism of a theology that would pretend to understand the
mind of god simply as a version of the human mind writ large.
6.
6 - The fruit of anthropomorphic thinking is a finite God.
Here Hume goes on the counter-attack by showing that if the argument
from design is taken seriously, one has to conclude that the god acting
in the universe is very different from the Christian variety. Since
there is no independent argument for the perfection of the designer,
we have to judge its ability and character from what we see of the
universe. And to paraphrase Bertrand Russell, if I had millions of
years of time and infinite power and had come up with the universe
as we know it, I should be ashamed of myself.
Hume
was a skeptic, but not a fool. He published his Dialogues on religion
posthumously, in 1779. They are still one of the most lucid critiques
of the most commonly used argument in favor of theism. And that, my
friends, is true immortality.
Next
Month: "Intelligent Design, the Modern Argument"
© by Massimo Pigliucci, 2000