Caplan, in his FAQ, attempts to rewrite anarchist history by trying to
claim that the individualist anarchists were forerunners of the
so-called "anarcho-capitalist" school. However, as is so often the case
with Caplan's FAQ, nothing could be further from the truth.
In section 5 (What major subdivisions may be made among anarchists?)
of his FAQ, Caplan writes that:
and quotes Carl Landauer's European Socialism: A History of Ideas
and Movements as evidence:
Caplan goes on to state that "the interesting point is that before the
emergence of modern anarcho-capitalism Landauer found it necessary to
distinguish two strands of anarchism, only one of which he considered to
be within the broad socialist tradition."
However, what Caplan seems to ignore is that both individualist and
social anarchists agree that there is a difference between the two
schools of anarchist thought! Some insight. Of course, Caplan tries
to suggest that Landauer's non-discussion of the individualist anarchists
is somehow "evidence" that their ideas are not socialistic. Firstly,
Landauer's book is about European Socialism. Individualist anarchism
was based within America and so hardly falls within the book's subject
area. Secondly, from the index Kropotkin is mentioned on two pages
(one of which a footnote). Does that mean Kropotkin was not a socialist?
Of course not. It seems likely, therefore, that Landauer is using a
common Marxian terminology of defining Marxism as Socialism, while calling
other parts of the wider socialist movement by their self-proclaimed
names of anarchism and syndicalism. Hardly surprising that Kropotkin is
hardly mentioned in a history of "Socialism" (i.e. Marxism).
Moreover, Kropotkin and Tucker both distinguished between two types of
anarchism as well as two types of socialism. Both of them considered
their ideas and movement to be part of the broader socialist tradition. As
evidence of the anti-socialist nature of individualist anarchism, Caplan's
interpretation of Landauer's words is fundamentally nonsense. If you look
at the writings of people like Tucker you will see that they called
themselves socialists and considered themselves part of the wider
socialist movement.
Interestingly, Landauer includes Proudhon in his history and states that
he was "the most profound thinker among pre-Marxian socialists." [p. 67]
Given that Caplan elsewhere in his FAQ tries to co-opt Proudhon into the
"anarcho"-capitalist school as well as Tucker, his citing of Landauer is
particularly dishonest. Landauer presents Proudhon's ideas in some
depth in his work within a chapter headed "The three Anticapitalistic
Movements." Indeed, he starts his discussion of Proudhon's ideas with
the words "In France, post-Utopian socialism begins with Peter Joseph
Proudhon." [p. 59]
Tucker and the other individualist anarchists considered themselves
as followers of Proudhon's ideas (as did Bakunin and Kropotkin). For
example, Tucker stated that his journal Liberty was "brought into
existence as a direct consequence of the teachings of Proudhon" and
"lives principally to spread them." [cited by Paul Avrich in his
"Introduction" to Proudhon and his "Bank of the People" by Charles A. Dana]
Obviously Landauer considered Proudhon a socalist and if individualist
anarchism follows Proudhon's ideas then it, too, must be socialist.
Unsurprisingly, then, Tucker also considered himself a socialist. To state
the obvious, Tucker and Bakunin both shared Proudhon's opposition to private
property (in the capitalist sense of the word), although Tucker confused
this opposition (and possibly the casual reader) by talking about possession
as "property."
So, it appears that Caplan is the one trying to rewrite history.
Perhaps the problem lies with Caplan's "definition" of socialism. In
section 7 (Is anarchism the same thing as socialism?) he states:
Which are hardly traditional definitions of socialism unless you are
ignorant of socialist ideas! By definition one, Bakunin and Kropotkin
are not socialists. As far as definition two goes, all anarchists
were opposed to private property and argued for its abolition and its
replacement with possession. The actual forms of possession differed
from between anarchist schools of thought, but the common aim to
end private property (capitalism) was still there. To quote Dana,
in a pamphlet called "a really intelligent, forceful, and sympathetic
account of mutual banking" by Tucker, individualist anarchists desire
to "destroy the tyranny of capital,- that is, of property." [Charles
A. Dana, Proudhon and his "Bank of the People", p. 46] by mutual credit.
Interestingly, this second definition of socialism brings to light a
contradiction in Caplan's account. Elsewhere in the FAQ he notes that
Proudhon had "ideas on the desirability of a modified form of private
property." In fact, Proudhon did desire to restrict private property to
that of possession, as Caplan himself seems aware. In other words,
even taking his own definitions we find that Proudhon would be considered
a socialist! Indeed, according to Proudhon, "all accumulated capital is
collective property, no one may be its exclusive owner." [Selected
Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Stewart Edwards (ed), p. 44] Thus
Jeremy Jennings' summary of the anarchist position on private property:
"The point to stress is that all anarchists [including Spooner and Tucker],
and not only those wedded to the predominant twentieth-century strain of anarchist communism have been critical of private property to the extent
that it was a source of hierarchy and privilege." ["Anarchism", Contemporary
Political Ideologies, Roger Eatwell and Anthony Wright (eds), p. 132]
He goes on to state that anarchists like Tucker and Spooner "agreed with the
proposition that property was legitimate only insofar as it embraced
no more than the total product of individual labour." [Ibib.]
In fact, a definition of socialism which socialists would agree with would
be one that stated that "the workers shall own the means of production."
Or, in Proudhon's words, "abolition of the proletariat." The common agreement
between all socialists was that capitalism was based upon wage slavery, that
workers did not have access to the means of production and so had to sell
themselves to the class that did. To use Tucker's own words:
"the fact that one class of men are dependent for their living upon
the sale of their labour, while another class of men are relieved of the
necessity of labour by being legally privileged to sell something that is
not labour. . . . And to such a state of things I am as much opposed as any
one. But the minute you remove privilege. . . every man will be a labourer
exchanging with fellow-labourers. . . What Anarchistic-Socialism aims to
abolish is usury. . . it wants to deprive capital of its reward" [Ben
Tucker, Instead of a Book, p. 404.]
By ending wage labour, anarchist socialism would ensure "The land to the
cultivator. The mine to the miner. The tool to the labourer." Wage labour,
and so capitalism, would be no more and "the product [would go] to the
producer." [from Tucker's essay "State Socialism and Anarchism" in Instead
of a Book] In other words, the "abolition of the proletariat."
Therefore, like all socialists, Tucker wanted workers to own and control
the means of production they used. He aimed to do this by reforming
capitalism away by creating mutual banks and other cooperatives. Here
is Kropotkin on Proudhon's reformist socialism:
"When he proclaimed in his first memoir on property that 'Property is theft',
he meant only property in its present, Roman-law, sense of 'right of use
and abuse'; in property-rights, on the other hand, understood in the limited
sense of possession, he saw the best protection against the encroachments of
the state. At the same time he did not want violently to dispossess the
present owners of land, dwelling-houses, mines, factories and so on. He
preferred to attain the same end by rendering capital incapable of earning
interest." [our emphasis]
In other words, like all anarchists, Proudhon desired to see a society
without capitalists and wage slaves ("the same end") but achieved by
different means. When Proudhon wrote to Karl Marx in 1846 he made the
same point:
"through Political Economy we must turn the theory of Property against
Property in such a way as to create what you German socialists call
community and which for the moment I will only go so far as calling
liberty or equality" [Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon,
p. 151]
In other words, he shared the common aim of all socialists (namely to
abolish capitalism) by disagreed with the means.
Caplan states that the "United States has been an even more fertile ground
for individualist anarchism: during the 19th-century, such figures as Josiah
Warren, Lysander Spooner, and Benjamin Tucker gained prominence for their
vision of an anarchism based upon freedom of contract and private property."
However, as indicated, Tucker and Spooner did not support private property
in the capitalist sense of the word and Kropotkin and Bakunin, no less
than Tucker and Spooner, supported free agreement between individuals and
groups. What does that prove? That Caplan seems more interested in the
words Tucker and Proudhon used rather than the meanings they attached
to them. Hardly convincing.
Perhaps Caplan should consider Proudhon's words on the subject of socialism:
"Modern Socialism was not founded as a sect or church; it has seen a number
of different schools." [Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon,
Stewart Edwards (ed), p. 177]
In section 8 (Who are the major anarchist thinkers?), Caplan tries his best
to claim that Proudhon was not really a socialist at all. He states that
"Pierre[-Joseph] Proudhon is also often included [as a "left anarchist"]
although his ideas on the desirability of a modified form of private property
would lead some to exclude him from the leftist camp altogether."
"Some" of which group? Other anarchists, like Bakunin and Kropotkin? Obviously
not - Bakunin claimed that "Proudhon was the master of us all." According
to George Woodcock Kropotkin was one of Proudhon's "confessed disciples."
Perhaps that makes Bakunin and Kropotkin proto-capitalists? Obviously not.
And, as we noted above, the socialist historian Carl Launder considered
Proudhon a socialist, as did the noted British socialist G.D.H. Cole in
his History of Socialist Thought (and in fact called him one of the "major
prophets of Socialism."). What about Marx and Engels, surely they would
be able to say if he was a socialist or not? According to Engels, Proudhon
was "the Socialist of the small peasant and master-craftsman."
However, perhaps all these "leftists" are wrong. Perhaps they just did
not understand what socialism actually is (and as Proudhon stated "I am
socialist" this also applies to Proudhon himself!). So the question arises,
did Proudhon support private property in the capitalist sense of the
word? The answer is no. To quote George Woodcock summary of Proudhon's
ideas on this subject we find:
"He [Proudhon] was denouncing the property of a man who uses it to exploit
the labour of others, without an effort on his own part, property
distinguished by interest and rent, by the impositions of the non-producer
on the producer. Towards property regarded as 'possession,' the right
of a man to control his dwelling and the land and tools he needs to live,
Proudhon had no hostility; indeed he regarded it as the cornerstone of
liberty." ["On Proudhon's 'What is Property?'", The Raven No. 31,
pp. 208-9]
George Crowder makes the same point:
"The ownership he opposes is basically that which is unearned. . . including
such things as interest on loans and income from rent. This is contrasted
with ownership rights in those goods either produced by the work of the
owner or necessary for that work, for example his dwelling-house, land
and tools. Proudhon initially refers to legitimate rights of ownership
of these goods as 'possession,' and although in his latter work he calls
this 'property,' the conceptual distinction remains the same."
[Classical Anarchism, pp. 85-86]
Indeed, according to Proudhon himself, the "accumulation of capital and
instrument is what the capitalist owes to the producer, but he never pays
him for it. It is this fraudulent deprivation which causes the poverty of
the worker, the opulence of the idle and the inequality of their conditions.
And it is this, above all, which has so aptly been called the exploitation
of man by man." [Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Stewart
Edwards (ed), p. 43]
He called his ideas on possession a "third form of society, the synthesis
of communism and property" and calls it "liberty." [The Anarchist Reader,
p. 68]. He even goes so far as to say that property "by its despotism and
encroachment, soon proves itself oppressive and anti-social." [Op. Cit,
p. 67] Opposing private property he thought that "all accumulated capital
is collective property, no one may be its exclusive owner." Indeed, he
considered the aim of his economic reforms "was to rescue the working
masses from capitalist exploitation." [Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph
Proudhon, p. 44, p. 80]
In other words, Proudhon considered capitalist property to be the source
of exploitation and oppression and he opposed it. He explicitly constrasts
his ideas to that of capitalist property and rejects it as a means of
ensuring liberty.
Caplan goes on to claim that "[s]ome of Proudhon's other heterodoxies include
his defense of the right of inheritance and his emphasis on the genuine
antagonism between state power and property rights."
However, this is a common anarchist position. Anarchists are well aware that
possession is a source of independence within capitalism and so should be
supported. As Albert Meltzer puts it:
"All present systems of ownership mean that some are deprived of
the fruits of their labour. It is true that, in a competitive society, only
the possession of independent means enables one to be free of the economy
(that is what Proudhon meant when, addressing himself to the self-employed
artisan, he said 'property is liberty', which seems at first sight a
contradiction with his dictum that it was theft)" [Anarchism: Arguments
for and against]
Malatesta makes the same point:
"Our opponents. . . are in the habit of justifying the right to
private property by stating that property is the condition and guarantee
of liberty.
"And we agree with them. Do we not say repeatedly that poverty is
slavery?
"But then why do we oppose them?
"The reason is clear: in reality the property that they defend is capitalist
property. . . which therefore depends on the existence of a class of
the disinherited and dispossessed, forced to sell their labour to the
property owners for a wage below its real value. . . This means that
workers are subjected to a kind of slavery." [The Anarchist Revolution,
p. 113]
As does Kropotkin:
"the only guarantee not to be robbed of the fruits of your labour
is to possess the instruments of labour. . . man really produces most
when he works in freedom, when he has a certain choice in his
occupations, when he has no overseer to impede him, and lastly,
when he sees his work bringing profit to him and to others who
work like him, but bringing in little to idlers." [The Conquest
of Bread, p. 145]
Perhaps this makes these three well known anarcho-communists "really"
proto-"anarcho"-capitalists as well? Obviously not. Instead of wondering
if his ideas on what socialism is are wrong, he tries to rewrite history
to fit the anarchist movement into his capitalist ideas of what anarchism,
socialism and whatever are actually like.
Interestingly, one of Proudhon's "other heterodoxies" he does not mention
is his belief that "property" was required not only to defend people against
the state, but also capitalism. He saw society dividing into "two classes,
one of employed workers, the other of property-owners, capitalists,
entrepreneurs." He thus recognised that capitalism was just as oppressive
as the state and that it assured "the victory of the strong over the weak,
of those who property over those who own nothing." [On the Political Capacity of the Working Classes, p. 141]
Indeed, he considered that "companies of capitalists" were the "exploiters of the bodies and souls of their wage earners" and
an outrage on "human dignity and personality." Instead of wage labour
he thought that the
"industry to be operated, the work to be done, are the common and
indivisible property of all the participant workers." In other
words, self-management and workers control. In this way there would
be "no more government of man by man, by means of accumulation of
capital" and the "social republic" established. Hence his support for
cooperatives:
"The importance of their work lies not in their petty union interests,
but in their denial of the rule of capitalists, usurers, and governments,
which the first [French] revolution left undisturbed. Afterwards, when
they have conquered the political lie. . . the groups of workers should
take over the great departments of industry which are their natural
inheritance." [cited in Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, E. Hymans, pp. 190-1,
and Anarchism, George Woodcock, p. 110, 112]
In other words, a socialist society as workers would no longer be
separated from the means of production and they would control their
own work (the "abolition of the proletariat," to use Proudhon's
expression). This would mean recognising that "the right to products
is exclusive - jus in re; the right to means is common - jus ad rem"
[cited by Woodcock, Anarchism, p. 96] which would lead to
self-management:
"In democratizing us, revolution has launched us on the path of
industrial democracy." [Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon,
Stewart Edwards (ed), p. 63]
As Woodcock points out, in Proudhon's "picture of the ideal society of the
ideal society it is this predominance of the small proprietor, the peasant
or artisan, that immediately impresses one" with "the creation of
cooperative associations for the running of factories and railways."
["On Proudhon's 'What is Property?'", Op. Cit, p. 209, p. 210]
To summarise, Proudhon was a socialist and Caplan's attempts to rewrite
anarchist and socialist history fails. Proudhon was the fountainhead
for both wings of the anarchist movement and What is Property? "embraces
the core of nineteenth century anarchism. . . [bar support for revolution]
all the rest of later anarchism is there, spoken or implied: the
conception of a free society united by association, of workers controlling
the means of production. . . [this book] remains the foundation on which
the whole edifice of nineteenth century anarchist theory was to be
constructed." [Op. Cit., p. 210]
Little wonder Bakunin stated that his ideas were Proudhonism "widely
developed and pushed to these, its final consequences."
That Tucker called himself a socialist is quickly seen from Instead of
A Book which means that either Caplan has not looked at it (with obvious
implications for the accuracy of his FAQ) or he decided to ignore
these facts in favour of his own ideologically tainted version of
history (again with obvious implications for the accuracy of his FAQ).
Caplan, in an attempt to deny the obvious, quotes Tucker from 1887 as
follows In section 14 (What are the major debates between anarchists?
What are the recurring arguments?):
You will instantly notice that Proudhon does not mean by property "the
possession of the labourer of his products." However, Proudhon did include
in his definition of property the possession of the capital to steal profits
from the work of the labourers. As is clear from the quote, Tucker and
Proudhon was opposed to capitalist property ("the power of usury"). From
Caplan's own evidence he proves that Tucker was not a capitalist!
But lets quote Tucker on what he meant by "usury":
"There are three forms of usury, interest on money, rent on land and houses,
and profit in exchange. Whoever is in receipt of any of these is a usurer."
[cited in Men against the State by James J. Martin, p. 208]
Which can hardly be claimed as being the words of a person who supports
capitalism!
And, we may add, since when was socialism identical to communism? Perhaps
Caplan should actually read Proudhon and the anarchist critique of private
property before writing such nonsense? We have indicated Proudhon's
ideas above and will not repeat ourselves. However, it is interesting
that this passes as "evidence" of "anti-socialism" for Caplan, indicating
that he does not know what socialism or anarchism actually is.
So this, his one attempt to prove that Tucker, Spooner and even Proudhon were
really capitalists by quoting the actual people involved is a failure.
He asserts that for any claim that "anarcho"-capitalism is not anarchist
is wrong because "the factual supporting arguments are often incorrect. For
example, despite a popular claim that socialism and anarchism have been
inextricably linked since the inception of the anarchist movement, many
19th-century anarchists, not only Americans such as Tucker and Spooner, but
even Europeans like Proudhon, were ardently in favor of private property
(merely believing that some existing sorts of property were illegitimate,
without opposing private property as such)."
The facts supporting the claim of anarchists being socialists, however,
are not "incorrect." Proudhon was reknown as the leading French Socialist
theorist when he was alive. His ideas were widely known in the socialist
movement and in many ways his economic theories were similar to the ideas of
such well known early socialists as Robert Owen and William Thompson. As
Kropotkin notes:
"It is worth noticing that French mutualism had its precursor in England, in
William Thompson, who began by mutualism before he became a communist, and
in his followers John Gray (A Lecture on Human Happiness, 1825; The Social
System, 1831) and J. F. Bray (Labour's Wrongs and Labour's Remedy, 1839)."
Perhaps Caplan will now claim Robert Owen and William Thompson as capitalists?
Tucker called himself a socialist on many different occasions and stated
that there were "two schools of Socialistic thought . . . State Socialism
and Anarchism." And stated in very clear terms that:
"liberty insists on Socialism. . . - true Socialism, Anarchistic Socialism:
the prevalance on earth of Liberty, Equality, and Solidarity." [Instead of
a Book, p. 363]
And like all socialists, he opposed capitalism (i.e. wage slavery) and wished
that "there should be no more proletaires." [see the essay "State
Socialism and Anarchism" in Instead of a Book]
Caplan, of course, is well aware of Tucker's opinions on the subject
of capitalism and private property. In section 13. (What moral justifications
have been offered for anarchism?) he writes:
What did Tucker consider as a government-imposed monopoly? Private
property, particularly in land! As he states "Anarchism undertakes to
protect no titles except such as are based upon actual occupancy and
use" and that anarchism "means the abolition of landlordism and the
annihilation of rent." [Instead of a Book, p. 61, p. 300] In other
words, Tucker considered capitalism as the product of statism while
socialism (libertarian of course) would be the product of anarchy.
So, Caplan's historical argument to support his notion that anarchism
is simply anti-government fails. Anarchism, in all its many forms, have
distinct economic as well as political ideas and these cannot be parted
without loosing what makes anarchism unique. In particular, Caplan's
attempt to protray Proudhon as an example of a "pure" anti-government
anarchism also fails, and so his attempt to co-opt Tucker and Spooner
also fails. If Proudhon was a socialist, then his self-proclaimed followers
will also be socialists - and, unsuprisingly, Tucker called himself a
socialist and considered anarchism as part of the wider socialist
movement.
For more on Tucker's ideas see section G of the FAQ.
1 - Individualist Anarchists and the socialist movement.
"A large segment of left-anarchists is extremely skeptical about
the anarchist credentials of anarcho-capitalists, arguing that
the anarchist movement has historically been clearly leftist. In
my own view, it is necessary to re-write a great deal of history
to maintain this claim."
"To be sure, there is a difference between
individualistic anarchism and collectivistic or
communistic anarchism; Bakunin called himself a
communist anarchist. But the communist anarchists also
do not acknowledge any right to society to force the
individual. They differ from the anarchistic
individualists in their belief that men, if freed from
coercion, will enter into voluntary associations of a
communistic type, while the other wing believes that
the free person will prefer a high degree of isolation.
The communist anarchists repudiate the right of private
property which is maintained through the power of the
state. The individualist anarchists are inclined to
maintain private property as a necessary condition of
individual independence, without fully answering the
question of how property could be maintained without
courts and police."
2 - Why is Caplan's definition of socialism wrong?
"If we accept one traditional definition of socialism -- 'advocacy
of government ownership of the means of production' -- it seems
that anarchists are not socialists by definition. But if by
socialism we mean something more inclusive, such as 'advocacy of
the strong restriction or abolition of private property,' then
the question becomes more complex."
3 - Was Proudhon a socialist or a capitalist?
4 - Tucker on Property, Communism and Socialism.
"It will probably surprise many who know nothing of Proudhon save
his declaration that 'property is robbery' to learn that he was
perhaps the most vigorous hater of Communism that ever lived
on this planet. But the apparent inconsistency vanishes when
you read his book and find that by property he means simply
legally privileged wealth or the power of usury, and not at
all the possession by the labourer of his products."
"Still other anarchists, such as Lysander Spooner and Benjamin
Tucker as well as Proudhon, have argued that anarchism would
abolish the exploitation inherent in interest and rent simply by
means of free competition. In their view, only labour income is
legitimate, and an important piece of the case for anarchism is
that without government-imposed monopolies, non-labour income
would be driven to zero by market forces. It is unclear, however,
if they regard this as merely a desirable side effect, or if they
would reject anarchism if they learned that the predicted
economic effect thereof would not actually occur."