PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS WITH
MORAL RELATIVISM
by Francis J. Beckwith
Summary
In moral debate in the United States today, many people resort to moral relativism. They
argue that there are no objective moral values which help us to determine what is right or
wrong. They claim "everything is relative." In order to defend this position,
the relativist puts forth two arguments: (1) Since people and cultures disagree about
morality, there are no objective moral values; (2) Moral relativism leads to tolerance of
practices we may find different or odd. These two arguments are seriously flawed. In
addition, the moral relativist has a difficult time explaining moral progress, moral
reformation, and clear-cut cases of moral saints and moral devils.
Ethical, moral, and social issues are beginning to dominate the headlines of major
newspapers and the front covers of leading magazines. Unfortunately many today seem to
assume that rationality and logic have no place in discussions of moral issues, and that
there is no way such questions can be answered. Many assume that we are simply stuck with
our opinions, and that all opinions are relative having
no basis in any objective or unchanging moral values. Should all values and opinions be
accorded equal moral weight?
The purpose of this article is to critically address the problem of moral relativism,
which I believe impedes our ability as a people to critically and rationally discuss
issues of great moral and ethical importance.
MORAL RELATIVISM
In his influential work, The Closing of the American Mind, Professor Allan Bloom
makes the observation that "there is one thing a professor can be absolutely certain
of: almost every student entering the university believes, or says he believes, that truth
is relative...The students, of course, cannot defend their opinion. It is something with
which they have been indoctrinated."1
By dogmatically asserting that there is no truth, people have become close-minded to the
possibility of knowing truth, if in fact it does exist. Consequently, lurking behind most
of the moral rhetoric in America today is moral relativism, the belief that there are no
objective moral values that transcend culture or the individual. This is why many people
begin or end their moral judgments with qualifying phrases such as, "It is only my
personal opinion," "Of course I am not judging anyone's behavior," or
"If you think it is all right, that is okay, but I'm personally against it."
Although such assertions have their place, we often use them inappropriately. Let us
consider a few examples of how moral relativism affects the way many people approach
public moral issues.
The Abortion Debate
Some abortion-rights advocates, in response to pro-life arguments, emote such
bumper-sticker slogans as: "Pro-choice, but personally opposed," "Don't
like abortion, don't have one," or "Abortion is against my beliefs, but I would
never dream of imposing my beliefs on others." These slogans attempt to articulate in
a simple way a common avenue taken by politicians and others who want to avoid the slings
and arrows that naturally follow a firm position on abortion. It is an attempt to find
"a compromise" or "a middle ground"; it's a way to avoid being labeled
"an extremist" of either camp.
During the 1984 presidential campaign when questions of
Geraldine Ferraro's Catholicism and its apparent conflict with her abortion-rights stance
were prominent in the media New York Governor Mario
Cuomo, in a lecture delivered at the University of Notre Dame, attempted to give this
"middle ground" intellectual respectability. He tried to provide a philosophical
foundation for his friend's position, but failed miserably. For one cannot appeal to the
fact that we live in a pluralistic society (characterized by moral pluralism/relativism)
when the very question of who is part of that society (that is, whether it includes
unborn children) is itself the point under dispute. Cuomo begged the question and lost the
argument.
The pro-abortionist's unargued assumption of moral relativism to solve the abortion debate
reveals a tremendous ignorance of the pro-life position. For the fact is that if one
believes that the unborn are fully human (persons), then the unborn carried in the wombs
of pro-choice women are just as human as those carried in the wombs of pro-life women. For
the pro-lifer, an unborn child is no less a human person simply because the child happens
to be living inside Whoopi Goldberg or Cybil Shepherd. Ideology does not change identity.
Pro-choicers ought to put at least some effort into understanding the pro-life
position. When they tell pro-lifers (as they often do) that they have a right to believe
what they want to believe, they are unwittingly promoting the radical tactics of Operation
Rescue (OR). Think about it. If you believed that a class of persons were being
murdered by methods that include dismemberment, suffocation, and burning resulting in excruciating pain in many cases
wouldn't you be perplexed if someone tried to ease your outrage by telling you that you
didn't have to participate in the murders if you didn't want to? That is exactly what
pro-lifers hear when abortion-rights supporters tell them, "Don't like abortion,
don't have one," or "I'm pro-choice, but personally opposed." In the mind
of the pro-lifer, this is like telling an abolitionist, "Don't like slavery, don't
own one," or telling Dietrich Bonhoffer, "Don't like the holocaust, don't kill a
Jew." Consequently, to request that pro-lifers "shouldn't force their pro-life
belief on others" while at the same time claiming that "they have a right to
believe what they want to believe" is to reveal an incredible ignorance of their
position.
Contrary to popular belief, the so-called "pro-choice" position is not neutral.
The abortion-rights activist's claim that women should have the "right to
choose" to kill their unborn fetuses amounts to denying the pro-life position that
the unborn are worthy of protection. And the pro-lifer's affirmation that the unborn are
fully human with a "right to life" amounts to denying the abortion-rights
position that women have a fundamental right to terminate their pregnancies, since such a
termination would result in a homicide. It seems, then, that appealing to moral relativism
(or moral pluralism ala Mario Cuomo) to "solve" the abortion debate is an
intellectual impossibility and solves nothing.
Censorship and the Public Good
Another example of how ethical relativism affects the way many people approach public
moral issues can be seen in the arguments concerning the right to boycott products
advertised on television programs which certain groups believe are psychologically and
morally harmful. The usual argument in response to these groups is, "If you don't
like a particular program, you don't have to watch it. You can always change the
channel." But is this response really compelling? One must point out that these
groups are not only saying that they personally find these programs
offensive, but rather are arguing that the programs themselves convey messages and create
a moral climate that will affect others especially
children in a way they believe is adverse to the public
good. Hence, what bothers these groups is that you and your children will
not change the channel.
I believe that as long as these groups do not advocate state censorship, but merely apply
social and economic pressure to private corporations (which civil rights and feminist
groups have been doing for some time now), a balance of freedoms is achieved. Both are
free to pursue their interests within the confines of constitutional protection, although
both must be willing to accept the social and economic consequences of their actions. This
seems to best serve the public good. Notice that this position does not resort to ethical
relativism, but takes seriously the values of freedom, the public good, and individual
rights and attempts to uphold these values in a way that
is consistent and fair.
ARGUMENTS FOR MORAL RELATIVISM
There are several arguments people have put forth to defend moral relativism. Of these,
two are especially popular, surfacing again and again in our culture under different
forms. The remainder of this article will be devoted to examining these arguments.
The Argument from Diversity in Moral Practice
Argument no. 1 states: Since cultures and individuals differ in certain moral
practices, there are no objective moral values. Several objections can be made to this
argument. First, the fact that people disagree about something does not mean there is no
objective truth. If you and I disagree about whether or not the earth is round, for
example, this is not proof that the earth has no shape. In moral discussion, the
fact that a skinhead (a type of young Neo-Nazi) and I may disagree about whether we should
treat people equally and fairly is not sufficient evidence to say that equality and
fairness have no objective value. Even if individuals and cultures held no values in
common, it does not follow from this that nobody is right or wrong about the correct
values. That is, there could be a morally erring individual or culture, such as Adolf
Hitler and Nazi Germany.
Another problem with this argument is that it does not follow from the fact that cultures
and individuals differ in moral practices that they do not share common values.
For example, the fact that some female islanders who live in the South Seas do not cover
their breasts and British women do doesn't mean that the former do not value modesty. Due
to the climate, environmental conditions, and certain religious beliefs, the people of the
South Seas have developed certain practices by which to manifest the transcultural value
of modesty. Although cultures may differ about how they manifest such values as honesty,
courage, and the preserving of life, they do not promote dishonesty, cowardice, or
arbitrary killing.
Second, sometimes apparent moral differences are not moral differences at all but factual
differences. For example, many people who live in India do not eat cows because they
believe in reincarnation that these cows may possess the
souls of deceased human beings. In the United States we do not believe cows have human
souls. For this reason, we eat cows but we do not eat
Grandma. It appears on the surface, therefore, that there is a fundamental value
difference between Indians and Americans. This is a hasty conclusion, however, for both
cultures do believe it is wrong to eat Grandma; the Indians, however, believe the cow may
be Grandma. Thus it is a factual and not a value difference that divides our culinary
habits.
Other examples can be produced to show why this first argument for moral relativism is
inadequate.2 It should be noted, however, that the fact there are some
common values among peoples and cultures does not mean all cultures share all the
same values. Obviously certain peoples and cultures may have developed some values that
others have not. Hence, the discovering of a unique value in a particular society does not
in any way take away from my central thesis that there are certain values to which all
societies either implicitly or explicitly hold.
Third, the argument from differing practices puts an undue emphasis on differences while
ignoring similarities, in addition to giving the mistaken appearance that all moral
conflicts are in some sense insoluble. In discussing moral conflicts in the United States
we tend to focus our attention on contemporary issues
abortion, euthanasia, affirmative action, and so forth
over which there is obviously wide and impassioned disagreement. However, we tend to
ignore the fact that the disputants in these moral debates hold a number of values in
common, that there are many moral issues on which almost all Americans agree (e.g.,
"It is wrong to molest six-year-old girls"), and that a number of past moral
conflicts have been solved (e.g., slavery, women's suffrage). Hence, by focusing our
attention only on disagreements, our perception has become skewed. Philosopher James
Rachels illustrates this point with an example from the sciences:
If we think of questions like this [i.e., abortion, euthanasia, affirmative
action, etc.], it is easy to believe that "proof" in ethics is impossible. The
same can be said of the sciences. There are many complicated matters that physicists
cannot agree on; and if we focused our attention entirely on them we might conclude
that there is no "proof" in physics. But of course, many simpler matters in
physics can be proven, and about those all competent physicists agree. Similarly,
in ethics there are many matters far simpler than abortion, about which all reasonable
people must agree.3
The Argument from the Virtue of Tolerance
Argument no. 2 for ethical relativism states: Since ethical relativism promotes
tolerance of certain cultural practices that members of Western civilization may think are
strange, ethical relativism is a good thing. However, although tolerance often is a
virtue, ethical relativists simply cannot justify their own position by appealing to it in
this way. First, the value of tolerance presupposes the existence of at least one real
objective (or absolute) value: tolerance. Bioethicist Tom Beauchamp makes this
observation:
If we interpret normative relativism as requiring tolerance of other views, the
whole theory is imperiled by inconsistency. The proposition that we ought to tolerate the
views of others, or that it is right not to interfere with others, is precluded by the
very strictures of the theory. Such a proposition bears all the marks of a non-relative
account of moral rightness, one based on, but not reducible to, the cross-cultural
findings of anthropologists...But if this moral principle [of tolerance] is recognized as
valid, it can of course be employed as an instrument for criticizing such cultural
practices as the denial of human rights to minorities and such beliefs as that of racial
superiority. A moral commitment to tolerance of other practices and beliefs thus leads
inexorably to the abandonment of normative relativism.4
Second, tolerance can only be a virtue if we think the other person, whose viewpoint
we're supposed to tolerate, is mistaken. That is to say, if we do not believe one
viewpoint is better than another, then to ask us to be tolerant of other viewpoints makes
no sense. For to tolerate another's viewpoint implies that this other person has a right
to his or her viewpoint despite the fact that others may think it is wrong. To be tolerant
of differing viewpoints involves just that differing viewpoints,
all of which cannot be equally correct at the same time. The man who supposes himself
tolerant while at the same time he believes nobody is either right or wrong about any
moral value is actually no more virtuous than the man who supposes his virginity is
chastity even though he was born with no sexual organs. Consequently, real tolerance
presupposes someone is right and someone is wrong, which implicitly denies moral
relativism.
It must be acknowledged, however, that there is a noble motive behind the relativists'
appeal to tolerance. They believe their view of tolerance will help us to better
understand other cultures and people without being hypercritical about their practices.
This in turn will keep us from using such criticism to justify the forced imposition of
our own cultural practices on them, such as putting blouses on the bare-breasted women of
the South Seas or forcing polygamous families to divide and become monogamous. I can
sympathize with this view of transcultural tolerance. As I stated earlier, however, a
cultural practice is different from a cultural value. It does not follow from different
practices that people have different values.
The local controversies surrounding the elimination of certain books from public school
curricula and libraries is an example of how people can agree on values and yet disagree
on practice. Those who favor more conservative guidelines, and who are often referred to
as advocating censorship, usually propose that certain materials are not suitable for
certain age groups. They argue that parents, not educational administrators, are best
suited to know what is good for their children. On the other hand, their opponents, who
are often referred to as advocating freedom of expression, usually propose that it should
be up to the teacher and the educational administrators to choose what is suitable
material, although they do believe that a line should be drawn somewhere. For example,
none of these defenders of freedom of expression defend the placing of hard-core
pornography in the hands of fourth graders.
This, of course, makes the debate all the more interesting, since it means that both sides
agree on the following general principles: a line must be drawn, certain materials are
suitable for certain age groups, and education is important. Both advocate some kind of
"censorship." They just disagree on who should be the censors, what should be
censored, and on what basis the decision should be made. Therefore, they both hold to many
of the same values, but they disagree as to the application of these values, and the
acceptability of certain factual claims.
Although this distinction between practice and value helps us to be tolerant of unusual
cultural practices, we are still able to make valuable moral judgments about others and
ourselves. First, we are free to criticize those intolerable cultural practices that do
conflict with basic human values, such as in the cases of genocide in Nazi Germany and
apartheid in South Africa. Second, we are able to admit to real moral progress, such as in
the case of the abolition of slavery. And third, there can exist real moral reformers,
such as Martin Luther King, Jr., and the prophets of the Old Testament, who served as
prophetic voices to reprimand their cultures for having drifted far from a true moral
practice based on basic human values.
The above three points each of which follow from a belief
in objective transcultural values do not follow
from a belief in ethical relativism. That is to say, to remain consistent the ethical
relativist cannot criticize intolerable moral practices, believe in real moral progress,
or acknowledge the existence of real moral reformers. For these three forms of moral
judgment presuppose the existence of real objective transcultural values.
Although much more can be said about the justification and existence of certain values,5
the above is sufficient to demonstrate that ethical relativism is enormously problematic.
It shows that we can rationally discuss and argue with each other about right and wrong
without resorting to the claim that ethical judgments are merely subjective or relative
and that all such judgments have equal validity. For to claim the latter logically leads
one to the bizarre judgment that Mother Teresa is no more and no less virtuous than Adolf
Hitler. I believe this is sufficient to show ethical relativism to be bankrupt.
Moral relativism has been rejected by a near unanimous number of both secular and theistic
ethicists and philosophers.6 Yet it is still popular to espouse this view in
many of our secularized cultural institutions. It is thought to be more tolerant, more
open, and more intellectually respectable than the old-fashioned "absolutism."7
As we have seen, however, moral relativism is inconsistent with tolerance, closed off to
the possibility of moral truth, and an intellectual failure.
Francis J. Beckwith, Ph.D. is a Lecturer of Philosophy at the University of Nevada,
Las Vegas. His latest books are Politically Correct Death: Answering the Arguments for
Abortion Rights (Baker, 1993) and Are You Politically Correct? Debating America's
Cultural Standards (Prometheus, 1993).
NOTES
1 Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1987), 25.
2 James Rachels, "A Critique of Ethical Relativism," in Philosophy:
The Quest for Truth, ed. Louis P. Pojman (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1989), 322-23.
3 James Rachels, "Some Basic Points about Arguments," in The Right
Thing to Do: Basic Readings in Moral Philosophy, ed. James Rachels (New York: Random
House, 1989), 40.
4 Tom L. Beauchamp, Philosophical Ethics: An Introduction to Moral
Philosophy (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1982), 42.
5 For a philosophical defense of particular universal values, see C. S.
Lewis, The Abolition of Man (New York: Macmillan, 1947), 95-121; Lewis, Mere
Christianity (New York: Macmillan, 1984), chapters 1-5; Rachels, "A
Critique," 322-24; and J. P. Moreland, Scaling the Secular City (Grand Rapids:
Baker Book House, 1987), chapter 4.
6 E.g., see Rachels, "A Critique"; J. P. Moreland and Norman
L. Geisler, The Life and Death Debate: Moral Issues of Our Time (New York:
Greenwood Press, 1990), chapter 1.
7 I think this is more accurately referred to as moral objectivism, since not
all the values the absolutist holds are absolutely equal; some are better than others. See
Norman L. Geisler, Christian Ethics: Options and Issues (Grand Rapids: Baker Book
House, 1989).
This article is a significantly revised version of a portion of chapter 1 of Francis J.
Beckwith's Politically Correct Death: Answering the Arguments for Abortion Rights
(Grand Rapids: Baker Book House, 1993), 19-25. Reprinted by permission.
This article first appeared in the Fall 1993 issue of the Christian Research
Journal.
|