WAR ON EVIL
By Robert Wright
Evil has a reputation for resilience. And rightly so. Banishing it from
Middle Earth alone took three very long Lord of the Rings movies. But equally deserving
of this reputation is the concept of evil-in particular, a conception of evil
that was on display in those very movies: the idea that behind all the world's
bad deeds lies a single, dark, cosmic force. No matter how many theologians
reject this idea, no matter how incompatible it seems with modern science, it
keeps coming back.
You would have thought St. Augustine rid the world of it a millennium and a
half ago. He argued so powerfully against this notion of evil, and against the
whole Manichaean theology containing it, that it disappeared from serious
church discourse. Thereafter, evil was not a thing; it was just the absence of
good, as darkness is the absence of light. But then came the Protestants, and
some of them brought back the Manichaean view of a cosmic struggle between the
forces of good and evil.
The philosopher Peter Singer, in his recent book The President of Good &
Evil: The Ethics of George W. Bush, suggests that the president is an heir to
this strand of Protestant thought. Certainly Bush is an example of how hard it
is to kill notions of evil once and for all. On the eve of his presidency, in a
postmodern, post-Cold War age, "evildoers" had become a word reserved
for ironic use, with overtones of superhero kitsch. But after September 11,
Bush used that word earnestly, vowed to "rid the world of evil," and
later declared Iran, Iraq, and North Korea part of an "axis of evil."
So what's wrong with that? Why do I get uncomfortable when he talks about
evil? Because his idea of evil is dangerous and, in the current geopolitical
environment, seductive.
Some conservatives dismiss liberal qualms about Bush's talk of evil as
knee-jerk moral relativism. But rejecting his conception of evil doesn't mean
rejecting the idea of moral absolutes, of right and wrong, good and bad. Evil
in the Manichaean sense isn't just absolute badness. It's a grand unified
explanation of such badness, the linkage of diverse badness to a single source.
In the Lord of the Rings, the various plainly horrible enemy troops-ores,
ringwraiths, and so on-were evil in the Manichaean sense by virtue of their
unified command; all were under the sway of the dreaded Sauron.
For the forces of good-hobbits, elves, Bush-this unity of badness greatly
simplifies the question of strategy. If all of your enemies are Satan's
puppets, there's no point in drawing fine distinctions among them. No need to
figure out which ones are irredeemable and which can be bought off. They're all
bad to the bone, so just fight them at every pass, bear any burden, and so on.
But what if the world isn't that simple? What if some terrorists will settle
for nothing less than the United States' destruction, whereas others just want
a nationalist enclave in Chechnya or Mindanao? And what if treating all
terrorists the same-as all having equally illegitimate goals-makes them more
the same, more uniformly anti-American, more zealous? (Note that President
Ronald Reagan's "evil empire" formulation didn't court this danger;
the Soviet threat was already monolithic.)
Or what if Iran, Iraq, and North Korea are actually different kinds of
problems? And what if their rulers, however many bad things they've done, are
still human beings who respond rationally to clear incentives? If you're truly
open to this possibility, you might be cheered when a hideous dictator, under
threat of invasion, allows U.N. weapons inspectors to search his country. But
if you believe this dictator is not just bad but evil, you'll probably conclude
that you should invade his country anyway. You don't make deals with the devil.
|
|
And, of course, if you believe that all terrorists are truly evil, then
you'll be less inclined to fret about the civil liberties of suspected terrorists,
or about treating accused or convicted terrorists decently in prison. Evil,
after all, demands a scorched-earth policy. But what if such a policy, by
making lots of Muslims in the United States and abroad feel persecuted,
actually increases the number of terrorists?
Abandoning such counterproductive metaphysics doesn't mean slipping into
relativism, or even, necessarily, dispensing with the concept of evil. You can
attribute bad deeds to a single source-and hence believe in a kind of
evil-without adopting the brand of Manichaeism that seems to animate Bush. You
could believe that somewhere in human nature is a bad seed that underlies many
of the terrible things people do. If you're a Christian, you might think of
this seed as original sin. If you're not religious, you might see it in secular
terms-for example, as a core selfishness that can skew our moral perspective,
inclining us to tolerate, even welcome, the suffering of people who threaten
our interests.
This idea of evil as something at work in all of us makes for a perspective
very different than the one that seems to guide the president. It could lead
you to ask, If we're all born with this seed of badness, why does it bear more
fruit in some people than others? And this question could lead you to analyze
evildoers in their native environments, and thus distinguish between the causes
of terrorism in one place and in another.
This conception of evil could also lead to a bracing self-scrutiny. It could
make you vigilant for signs that your own moral calculus had been warped by
your personal, political, or ideological agenda. If, say, you had started a war
that killed more than 10,000 people, you might be pricked by the occasional
doubt about your judgment or motivation-rather than suffused in the assurance
that, as God's chosen servant, you are free from blame.
In short, with this conception of evil, the world doesn't look like a Lord
of the Rings trailer, in which all the bad guys report to the same headquarters
and, for the sake of easy identification, are hideously ugly. It is a more
ambiguous world, a world in which evil lurks somewhere in everyone, and
enlightened policy is commensurately subtle.
Actually, there are traces of this view even in the Lord of the Rings films.
Hence the insidious ring, which can fill all who gaze on it with the desperate
desire to possess it, a desire that, if unchecked, leads to utter corruption.
The message would seem to be that, thanks to human frailty, anyone can play
host to evil-hobbits, elves, even, conceivably, the occasional American.
UNDERMINING FREE WILL
By Paul Davies
You don't have to read this article. But if you do, could you have chosen
otherwise? You probably feel that you were free to skip over it, but were you?
Belief in some measure of free will is common to all cultures and a large
part of what makes us human. It is also fundamental to our ethical and legal
systems. Yet today's scientists and philosophers are busily chipping away at
this social pillar-apparently without thinking about what might replace it.
What they question is a folk psychology that goes something like this:
Inside each of us is a self, a conscious agent who both observes the world and
makes decisions. In some cases (though perhaps not all), this agent has a
measure of choice and control over his or her actions. From this simple model
of human agency flow the familiar notions of responsibility, guilt, blame, and
credit. The law, for example, makes a clear distinction between a criminal act
carried out by a person under hypnosis or while sleepwalking, and a crime
committed in a state of normal awareness with full knowledge of the
consequences.
All this may seem like common sense, but philosophers and writers have
questioned it for centuriesand the attack is gathering speed. "All theory
is against the freedom of the will," wrote British critic Samuel Johnson.
In the 1940s, Oxford University philosophy Professor Gilbert Ryle coined the
derisory expression "the ghost in the machine" for the widespread
assumption that brains are occupied by immaterial selves that somehow control
the activities of our neurons. The contemporary American philosopher Daniel
Dennett now refers to the "fragile myth" of "spectral
puppeteers" inside our heads.
For skeptics of free will, human decisions are either determined by a
person's preexisting nature or, alternatively, are entirely arbitrary and
whimsical. Either way, genuine freedom of choice seems elusive. Physicists
often fire the opening salvo against free will. In the classical Newtonian
scheme, the universe is a gigantic clockwork mechanism, slavishly unfolding
according to deterministic laws. How then does a free agent act? There is
simply no room in this causally closed system for an immaterial mind to bend
the paths of atoms without coming into conflict with physical law. Nor does the
famed indeterminacy of quantum mechanics help minds to gain purchase on the
material world. Quantum uncertainty cannot create freedom. Genuine freedom
requires that our wills determine our actions reliably.
Physicists assert that free will is merely a feeling we have; the mind has
no genuine causal efficacy. Whence does this feeling arise? In his 2002 book,
The Illusion of Conscious Will, Harvard
University psychologist Daniel Wegner appeals to ingenious laboratory
experiments to show how subjects acquire the delusion of being in charge, even
when their conscious thoughts do not actually cause the actions they observe.
The rise of modern genetics has also undermined the belief that humans are
born with the freedom to shape their individual destinies. Scientists recognize
that genes shape our minds as well as our bodies. Evolutionary psychologists
seek to root personal qualities such as altruism and aggression in Darwinian mechanisms
of random mutation and natural selection. "We are survival machines-robot
vehicles blindly programmed to preserve the selfish molecules known as
genes," writes Oxford University biologist Richard Dawkins.
|
|
Those aspects of the mind that are not predetermined by genetics lie at the
mercy of "memetics." Memes are the mental equivalent of genes-ideas,
beliefs, and fashions that replicate and compete in the manner of genes.
British psychologist Susan Blackmore recently contended that our minds are
actually nothing but collections of memes that we catch from each other like
viruses, and that the familiar sense of "I" is some sort of fiction
that memes create for their own agenda.
These ideas are dangerous because there is more than a grain of truth in
them. There is an acute risk that they will be oversimplified and used to
justify an anything-goes attitude to criminal activity, ethnic conflict, even
genocide. Conversely, people convinced that the concept of individual choice is
a myth may passively conform to whatever fate an exploitative social or
political system may have decreed for them. If you thought eugenics was a
disastrous perversion of science, imagine a world where most people don't
believe in free will.
The scientific assault on free will would be less alarming if some new legal
and ethical framework existed to take its place. But nobody really has a clue
what that new structure might look like. And, remember, the scientists may be
wrong to doubt free will. It would be rash to assume that physicists have said
the last word on causation, or that cognitive scientists fully understand brain
function and consciousness. But even if they are right, and free will really is
an illusion, it may still be a fiction worth maintaining. Physicists and
philosophers often deploy persuasive arguments in the rarified confines of
academe but ignore them for all practical purposes. For example, it is easy to
be persuaded that the flow of time is an illusion (in physics, time simply is,
it doesn't "pass"). But nobody would conduct their daily affairs
without continual reference to past, present, and future. Society would
disintegrate without adhering to the fiction that time passes. So it is with
the self and its freedom to participate in events. To paraphrase the writer
Isaac Bashevis Singer, we must believe in free will-we have no choice.
TRANSHUMANISM
By Francis Fukuyama
For the last several decades, a strange liberation movement has grown within
the developed world. Its crusaders aim much higher than civil rights
campaigners, feminists, or gayrights advocates. They want nothing less than to
liberate the human race from its biological constraints. As
"transhumanists" see it, humans must wrest their biological destiny
from evolution's blind process of random variation and adaptation and move to
the next stage as a species.
It is tempting to dismiss transhumanists as some sort of odd cult, nothing
more than science fiction taken too seriously: Witness their overthe-top Web
sites and recent press releases ("Cyborg Thinkers to Address Humanity's
Future," proclaims one). The plans of some transhumanists to freeze
themselves cryogenically in hopes of being revived in a future age seem only to
confirm the movement's place on the intellectual fringe.
But is the fundamental tenet of transhumanism-that we will someday use
biotechnology to make ourselves stronger, smarter, less prone to violence, and
longer-lived-really so outlandish? Transhumanism of a sort is implicit in much
of the research agenda of contemporary biomedicine. The new procedures and
technologies emerging from research laboratories and hospitals-whether
mood-altering drugs, substances to boost muscle mass or selectively erase
memory, prenatal genetic screening, or gene therapy-can as easily be used to
"enhance" the species as to ease or ameliorate illness.
Although the rapid advances in biotechnology often leave us vaguely
uncomfortable, the intellectual or moral threat they represent is not always
easy to identify. The human race, after all, is a pretty sorry mess, with our
stubborn diseases, physical limitations, and short lives. Throw in humanity's
jealousies, violence, and constant anxieties, and the transhumanist project
begins to look downright reasonable. If it were technologically possible, why
wouldn't we want to transcend our current species? The seeming reasonableness
of the project, particularly when considered in small increments, is part of
its danger. Society is unlikely to fall suddenly under the spell of the
transhumanist worldview. But it is very possible that we will nibble at
biotechnology's tempting offerings without realizing that they come at a
frightful moral cost.
The first victim of transhumanism might be equality. The U.S. Declaration of
Independence says that "all men are created equal," and the most
serious political fights in the history of the United States have been over who
qualifies as fully human. Women and blacks did not make the cut in 1776 when
Thomas Jefferson penned the declaration. Slowly and painfully, advanced
societies have realized that simply being human entitles a person to political
and legal equality. In effect, we have drawn a red line around the human being
and said that it is sacrosanct.
Underlying this idea of the equality of rights is the belief that we all
possess a human essence that dwarfs manifest differences in skin color, beauty,
and even intelligence. This essence, and the view that individuals therefore
have inherent value, is at the heart of political liberalism. But modifying
that essence is the core of the transhumanist project. If we start transforming
ourselves into something superior, what rights will these enhanced creatures
claim, and what rights will they possess when compared to those left behind? If
some move ahead, can anyone afford not to follow? These questions are troubling
enough within rich, developed societies. Add in the implications for citizens
of the world's poorest countries-for whom biotechnology's marvels likely will
be out of reachand the threat to the idea of equality becomes even more
menacing.
|
|
Transhumanism's advocates think they understand what constitutes a good
human being, and they are happy to leave behind the limited, mortal, natural
beings they see around them in favor of something better. But do they really
comprehend ultimate human goods? For all our obvious faults, we humans are
miraculously complex products of a long evolutionary process-products whose
whole is much more than the sum of our parts. Our good characteristics are
intimately connected to our bad ones: If we weren't violent and aggressive, we
wouldn't be able to defend ourselves; if we didn't have feelings of
exclusivity, we wouldn't be loyal to those close to us; if we never felt
jealousy, we would also never feel love. Even our mortality plays a critical
function in allowing our species as a whole to survive and adapt (and
transhumanists are just about the last group I'd like to see live forever).
Modifying any one of our key characteristics inevitably entails modifying a
complex, interlinked package of traits, and we will never be able to anticipate
the ultimate outcome.
Nobody knows what technological possibilities will emerge for human
self-modification. But we can already see the stirrings of Promethean desires
in how we prescribe drugs to alter the behavior and personalities of our
children. The environmental movement has taught us humility and respect for the
integrity of nonhuman nature. We need a similar humility concerning our human
nature. If we do not develop it soon, we may unwittingly invite the
transhumanists to deface humanity with their genetic bulldozers and
psychotropic shopping malls.