Commentary on Karl Jaspers Forum, Target Article 27, 6 June 2000
METAPHYSICAL MUSINGS
Practical Considerationsby Paul Jones2 July 2000 I has been solicited to comment on Adrian's article, which is a non-trivial undertaking, since the very genre of the text ("musings") does not imply any energetic reaction; it rather demands leisurely tasting the product paragraph by paragraph during coffee breaks - which, as it happens, is ideally suited for my present situation, when I cannot afford spending too much time on anything but survival work. However, I cannot completely agree with John Mikes, when he says that there is no "composition in the article, a lead-idea which is treated from the various aspects of the text". Well, it is eclectic and random, as implied by the title; however, it produces an integral impression indicating that there is a unifying idea, albeit never explicitly presented: Adrian's article has more in common with belles lettres than science or philosophy (somehow it reminds me Carrol's "Sylvie and Bruno") - but why should we consider science as the only way of comprehending anything? What kind of idea can that be? Well, one might try to express it with different means, either verbal or not, and this new product induced by the original text could become a presentation of another facet of the same thing, projecting a social trend onto individual experience. As I see it, Adrian's text turns around the fundamental hypothesis that the specifically analytical style of thought commonly associated with written (or, in general, formally structured) speech takes its origin in some pre-linguistic cultural phenomena, so that language formation could be considered as contrivance rather than spontaneous development. In particular, this viewpoint implies that any formalisation (including science) ascends to the pre-historic schemes, which must impose much similarity onto the formal systems designed in different cultures of different epochs. One might either agree with that view or not, but it has its own right for existence and is subject to investigation. Personally, I consider it as a preliminary approach to a more general idea, that of the primacy of people's activity over their mentality, which was earlier known as a corner stone of a philosophical teaching called historical materialism. Indeed, much of the conceptual problems Adrian encounters, and hence eclecticism, are due to the lack of clear understanding of what are those primary structures that made people to "contrive" language and ubiquitous conceptual frames, many examples of which Adrian's article contains. As soon as one admits that what people think is a reflection of what they do, everything becomes clear and logically consistent, both in the history of humanity and individual development of a person: any conceptual scheme is born from a specific activity, reproducing the scheme of that original activity in an activity of a different kind. Certainly, one should not treat the above principle in a primitive way, as a rigid junction between an act and its reflection in the actor. Everything people do becomes the heritage of the society, and it is only through the society that people can receive what they produce (and, in particular, perceive it). Quite often the products of human activity do not return to those who have produced them, and hence the influence of one's mode of life on one's mind is not straightforward. The important psychological implication of the principle of the priority of activity over mentality is that people can never accept anything unless they have been prepared to accept it by the very organisation of their life and work. No thought can come to anybody without a proper social background, including thoughts that seem to be far ahead of their time. The story of Diringer's Amerindian designing a written language provides a typical example: that person was ready to invent it, since his social environment has developed to the stage allowing for writing - otherwise he would have laughed at an idea like that, or simply killed the advocate of such a nonsense (recall Giordano Bruno's case). There is a reverse side of the medal: a genius can only arise from the ocean of mediocrity, and the annoying crowd of poor writers (artists, scientists, philosophers, workers...) is necessary to fertilise the soil for a great one, who merely collects the harvest grown by the others. A giant feeds on the everyday work of many dwarfs - the pattern mentioned by Adrian. Quite possibly, with an improved social organisation, this paradigm will loose its dominance. I have to wait for a better time to comment on the specific schemes described in Adrian's article. I certainly did not read all those 100,000 pages he alludes to (Mikes); however, being acquainted with at least 30% of them and having read a comparable heap of complementary literature, I have enough courage (or is it arrogance?) to judge. A list of a few weak points of Adrian's discourse presented below might stimulate further development in this area. First, there is too much attention to oral or written language, and underestimation of the gesture and other channels of communication. When Adrian says: "...without sound thinking one's praxis can hardly improve," I think of the genetically deaf-and-dumb people who manage, with the help of the society, to grow into conscious beings, and even master oral language and get their PhDs. Gesture language (like ASL) is no worse than oral language for close communication, and it allows development of writing in a similar way. The conditions of the Earth favoured sound communication, and eventually its ubiquity has become a prejudice. There are indications that a baby comes to one- and two-word language through a primitive gesture language, which, in its turn, merely reproduces some elements of the baby's activities shared with the grown-ups. Ethological observations and acquaintance with the usage of alternative lexicon in different languages make me think that first oral communication merely accompanied expressive gestures, gradually replacing them; the formation of the both was stimulated by people's participation in various joint activities. The dimensions of the space-time plays an important role in every human activity - no wonder it gets reflected in our language and thought. It is still difficult for most people to consider more dimensions than 3+1, and it is only recently that the concepts of many-dimensional configuration space of collective motion, the infinite-dimensional Hilbert space of quantum states, or a stratified manifold as an adequate representation for the motion of a strongly coupled system have become a common instrument in physical theory. Ordering, transforming simultaneous structures into one-dimensional sequences, and inversely, unfolding sequences in spatially organised pictures is indeed an important part of any human activity, correspondingly represented in language. This ubiquity has not yet been properly understood and appreciated. I suspect that it reflects a fundamental feature of any motion at all, however this is to be discussed elsewhere. I cannot agree that culture, language and art "seem to spring quite full blown into existence", according to archaeological data. On the contrary, all the data indicate that anything in culture is subject to change and development, from the most primitive to highly diversified forms. It is enough to look at the evolution of stone tools to get the impression. It would be incorrect to consider the fascinating cave paintings as the very first traces of art, thence concluding on its contrivance. Okladnikov's works on the evolution of primitive art in Siberia are convincing enough to prove art's development from the rhythmic organisation of the production process, and more recent observations on the process of dance figure formation from routine activities support that hypothesis too. One should also exercise caution associating various manifestations of iconic thinking and magical/religious rites with art. Naturalistic painting skills are not enough to make art, like the ability to press the trigger button of a modern automatic camera does mot make its owner a master of artistic photography. Art is made according to its specific laws, serving a definite social function. As a side remark, I do not believe that art could be a result of "after dinner daydreaming", as Adrian suggests. It is most doubtful that our predecessors had too much leisure - the primitive economy of that time could hardly allow it. It is after many centuries of development, with the dawn of civilisation, some people became engaged in the arts more than in any other activity; professional art appears even later. Archaic art was a part of the social production process, not a leisure occupation. The hypothesis if the origin of the written language from the arts deserves consideration. For me, it is not well formulated. Certainly, designing an icon requires some graphic capabilities, and it must be prepared by the development of art. We all know that calligraphy was exercised as an art by all the nations on a definite stage of their development (before the glory of the printing-press). However, the availability of the forms is not enough to start their using for the specific purpose of imaging speech, and there must have been other pre-requisites of that. It is more likely that first ideograms came in close syncretism with art, which then was hardly distinguishable from science, or philosophy, or magic rites. The traces of such a syncretism can be readily found in many later cultures. Thus, the ornamental function of the sacred texts in the decoration of a Moslem house was undetachable from their "protective" magic. Similarly, a carved roof ridge of a Russian village house was not only an element of decor, but also a rain water drain, and a talisman, and an indicator of the socio-ethnic position of the family... This leads to an important issue of the standard scheme of any development from syncretism through analysis to synthesis. Adrian does not distinguish synthesis (the unity of distinctions) from syncretism (no distinctions at all), which makes him suspect that "recent ventures in expanding our knowledge simply revert to the earliest foundations of our knowledge". There is no way back in the development of the human society, and what may seem a historical repetition appears to be a quite different phenomenon at a closer investigation, albeit borrowing certain forms from the past. In other words, we find something in the past that can serve our present purpose, and we fill it with a new content, suited to format the present ideas. There is no "esoteric" or "lost" supreme knowledge, and we should not overestimate our ancestors' abilities and achievements. It not that out intellect "was created and furnished by archaic man and we now in-habit it" - our intellect has made a long way from the archaic intellect, though one could still complain at its imperfection.
I only have to quote from Mikes: Yes, "something with very ancient roots is with us today". But there are two kinds of such a presence: either it is some rudiments of the primitive life indicating that the humans have not yet gone too far in their way from the animals to conscious beings (we are too much animals yet!) - or it is a reflection of the universal schemes of activity formed early in the human history and characterising consciousness as such. Between these past- and future-oriented heritage of the past, one might place the schemes originating form the specific conditions of our life on the Earth, which do penetrate all of our activity today, but are bound to get significantly modified in the future, when we leave the Earth to expand into the space. Below, I indicate a few inconsistencies found in the text. They do not much influence the general idea, but spoil the overall impression. It is most doubtful that, as Adrian puts it, "our mind readily recalls similar events and experiences but has problems with differences." On the contrary, a singularity is much easier to recall, while ordinary events similar to each other are extremely hard to recollect (many detective stories are based on this common psychological feature). The human mind is very sensitive to differences, and the main problem in art, science and philosophy is to find hidden similarities, which are not easy to observe. I was somewhat surprised at Adrian's interpretation of Aristotle's nous poietikos as "reference to available operations of an equilibrable system" - I doubt that Aristotle could ever have employed a language like that. The phrase "nous poietikos" can be plainly translated as "creative mind", or simply "creativity". The idea discussed by Aristotle is then that language is organised to reflect the organisation of human activity, the ways of making something. See above about historical materialism. Also, I would not mix Wittgenstein with Democritus. The assertion that "the world consists of atomic facts" is entirely different from "the world consists of atoms"; the former is sheer idealism, while the latter admits the existence of the world on itself. Finally, being Russian, I am well acquainted with Russian history - but I have never heard of Russians building walls like Chinese. All they had was wooden forts, like those known at many peoples since the most ancient times. To make their cities more protected, they invited Greek and Italian masters to built stone walls, and learned fortification from Europe. There are other issues that could be discussed in relation to Adrian's article, but one has to stop somewhere. Mikes' comment has expressed some of my thoughts too. Anyway, Adrian's article is rather stimulating and useful, and, personally, I liked its modest style.
[Unism] [Search] [Contact information] [Guestbook] |