Dialectical Logic
There are numerous books on dialectical logic; however, only few
of them are concerned with its specifically logical aspects.
This was a side effect of class struggle in the ideological
domain, when dialectics became a slogan of one party, and a curse
for the other. It has been forgotten that the origin of dialectics
can be traced up to the most ancient times, and that it was advocated
within philosophical idealism no less than by materialists. As any
logic, dialectics is universal and cannot reflect the interests of
specific social layers. As any logic, it can be used to support
quite different ideas, and it is only in practical activity that
one way of thought may overcome another.
For a few thousand years, the humanity developed within the
three socioeconomic formations based on expropriation of
the product's of one's activity by individuals or social groups
not involved in any production processes; this phase of human
development was necessary to break the primitive syncretism
of the earliest communal cultures, but its analytical nature
manifested itself in all-penetrating social discrimination,
and class antagonism. Classical logic was well suited to
reflect such a social organization, commonly known as
civilization. Now, when the last formation of this
development phase, capitalism, is approaching its end,
accents will shift in all kinds of philosophy to a more
dynamic approach allowing for drastic changes and revolutionary
development. Dialectical logic perfectly matches this demand.
Unfortunately, dialectical logic mainly developed outside the
English-speaking culture, and it may be difficult to translate
many of its categories so that their many-faceted meaning
would remain intact. Even in classical logic, a notion could
hardly be expressed with a single word or phrase; the more so
in dialectics. Up to now, dialectical logic is considered
by many people brought up in the classical spirit of stability
and determinacy as mere play of words, without any practical
importance. Dialectics is difficult to grasp by most scientists,
whose essentially analytical occupation forms their minds in
a rigid professional mould. It is only in crisis situations
that the limitations of the traditional modes of thought
become evident, demanding new logical principles to complement
the static (structural) approach of classical logic.
Dialectics - what's that?
While classical logic stressed the static, structural aspects
of reality, dialectics is all about change. No thing
can remain the same in dialectical logic, and there are
no clear shapes and rigid boundaries. The adepts of classical
logic would call it absolutely illogical - and it is certainly
not logical in the classical sense. However, despite all the
apparently arbitrary, and even chaotic look, dialectical logic
remains perfectly rational, being controlled by quite definite
principles. As the opposite of classical logic, it is as
crisp and formal, and its very arbitrariness is merely an
explicit form of the imminent arbitrariness of abstract
classical logicality. And, like classical logic, dialectics
can be made into scholastics, if no rapport to reality is
maintained.
The motion of thought, and the course of any other human
activity, must reflect the motion of the world, for the
activity to be successful. This means that dialectical
logic, like classical logic, is inseparable from ontology,
being the same philosophy viewed in a different aspect.
Origin of dialectical logic
Traditionally, Heractiles is said to be the farther of
dialectics in Europe. However, dialectical elements can
be found in practically any teaching of Ancient Greece,
and, of course, in Aristotle's lectures. It is much later
that dialectical and classical logic became split and
even opposed to each other. In the XIX century, the
inverse process of synthesizing the two approaches
on a common philosophical basis was initiated, but it
is still far from being completed.
As any logic at all, dialectical logic is not an arbitrary
construction, and its roots should be sought for in
the specific modes of human activity. While classical logic
ascends to binary discrimination and categorization,
dialectical logic is an abstraction of change in general.
It is complementary to classical logic in the same sense
as considering two distinct things is complemented by
considering their difference as a manifestation of their unity.
It was quite natural to express the ideas contrary to the
classical approach in the paradoxical form. Zeno's paradoxes
have long since become a standard example.
Logical forms
In classical logic, we consider notions, statements and inferences
as different levels of hierarchy. In dialectical logic, these forms
cannot be considered as distinct enough, and notions or arguments
can become statements, statements become notions etc., within the
same activity. Does it mean that there are no logical forms
in dialectics? Certainly not.
In any act of change, there are three aspects universally bound to
the very idea: first of all, there is something that changes
(thesis), something into which it is to change (antithesis),
and the way of transforming the former into the latter (synthesis).
These are the basic logical change in dialectical logic.
-
Thesis
Anything can change, and hence become a thesis. The possibility
of distinguishing the thesis as such implies its relative
stability, which open a broad way for applying classical logic
to describe it. Notions, statements and conclusions are
equally possible as the means of formulation (formalization).
-
Antithesis
As the opposite of the thesis, it is as well abstracted from
anything else, and as well describable in a classical manner.
The antithesis is a specific thing essentially different from
the thesis in some respect. The transformation of the thesis into
the antithesis necessarily looks like a leap, a jump from one
side of a crevasse to another, something unexplainable from the
classical standpoint.
-
Synthesis
The important point in any act of dialectical reasoning is
that both thesis and antithesis are the states, phases or
aspects of the same thing, which hence must be able to manifest
itself in the opposite ways recognizable as thesis and antithesis.
Otherwise, this is a quite ordinary thing, which can be
classically described as long as its relation to thesis and
antithesis is not considered.
Fundamental principles of dialectical logic
While the laws of classical logic have been formulated millennia
ago, the principles of dialectical logic had not received a
clear formulation until the beginning of XIX century, marked by
the works of Hegel and Marx. These formal rules are yet too
young to become commonly accepted, or even widely known.
-
The principle of integrity
Dialectics cannot rely on the identity of a thing, since any thing
can become its opposite, under certain conditions. Still, there is
a more general principle that states that every thing is the unity
of its opposite aspects, and that it remains the same despite
all the transformations. On the other hand, its internal complexity
will make it exhibit its opposite sides to the rest of the world,
and any thing is bound to develop all its possible forms in full
until it can cease to exit. Sometimes, the presence of opposite
aspects in the same thing may take the form of internal struggle,
when two opposite tendencies shape the final appearance of the
thing, one of them dominating over another. This why, in the
Marxist literature, the principle of integrity was called
the law of the unity and struggle of the opposites.
From the classical viewpoint, the internal complexity of every
thing looks like contradiction in the definition, ascribing
opposite attributes to the same notion. In other words, the
first principle of dialectical logic says that every thesis
is contradictory. Applied to the classical logical forms,
it implies that no notion statement of conclusion can be fully
determinable, and hence every construction based on classical
logic is essentially incomplete. As negation of the
identity of any notion, the principle of integrity was sometimes
called the law of contradiction, compared with the law of
non-contradiction in classical logic. The idea of dialectical
contradiction is a core of dialectics as such.
Practically, the principle of integrity demands that every
change were based on the properties of the real things, rather
than abstract manipulations. To make anything out of something,
one has to use that something according to its inherent
tendencies (albeit hidden and non-trivial), and never rape
the world trying to make things what they cannot be (the
ideological position known as voluntarism).
-
The principle of negation
While the internal definiteness of a thing is determined by
the principle of integrity, the succession of the apparent
manifestations of the thing is determined by the principle
demanding that every next development phase should be a
negation of the original state. In other words, every thesis
can (and will) transform into its antithesis under appropriate
conditions.
The idea of dialectical negation is quite simple: to produce
the antithesis, we have to add something to the thesis that
was not in it originally, and, inversely, remove something
that should not be present in the result. Adding new features
can be considered as removing (negating) their absence.
However, in dialectical logic, the changes must be small
enough, to preserve the thing's integrity, and there is no
absolute change in every respect (which is more like the
complement operation in classical logic).
The principle of negation is important to prevent dogmatism.
It puts stress on a well-know, but often overlooked, fact that
every act is only appropriate in a definite context, and
there are no absolute laws, truths, or attitudes.
Dialectical negation is different from negation in classical
logic. While the latter lead to an entirely different idea,
the former leaves the thing the same, only making it
apparently (or functionally) different; it
merely shows how the internal opposites of the thing can
manifest themselves in the thing's relation to the world.
On the other hand, the negation of negation in classical
logic restores the original thing; in dialectical logic, negation
of negation is opposite not only to the antithesis negated, but
also to the original thesis, negated by the primary negation.
The negation of negation was often said to lead to the thing
or situation resembling the original that existed before
the primary negation. However, such a view is too simplified
to be correct. To return to some features of the original thesis,
one must negate the antithesis in the same respect,
which is not always possible; rather, the negation of negation
will result in yet another manifestation of the same thing, which will
be different from both thesis and antithesis, retaining
them both as its history, and resembling them both, in different
aspects. The negation of negation is a synthesis of the
thesis and antithesis. Any circularity does not belong to
the level of dialectics, merely outlining the zones of relative
stability, where classical logic could be applied.
-
The principle of measure
The fundamental principle that relates the internal complexity
of every thing to its apparent motion via a series of negations
says that every thing has its measure, a unique balance of
its internal definiteness (quality) and possible external
manifestations (quantity). The category of quality conveys
the idea of a thing as it is, as that very thing, and not another.
The philosophical category of quantity cannot be reduced to mere
numerical value; it also includes any structural aspects, systemic
behavior, or other external manifestations of internal complexity.
Everybody knows that most things can be slightly varied
without ceasing to be the same things. Such changes are called
quantitative. However, the principle of measure states that
quantitative changes can reach a threshold, beyond which the
quality of the thing would change, and it something quite
different from the original. This is the mechanism of dialectical
negation.
The other side of the same principle is that it is the quality
of any thing that determines when its quantitative changes
will put the end to the existence of the thing as such:
every thing is the cause of its own death.
It should be noted that, since dialectical negation does not
entirely annihilate the thing negated, but rather retains it
within the negation, qualitative changes do not produce
anything from nothing, merely transforming the already
existing things, but never annihilating them. Change in quality
is still change, which implies the retention of something
that undergoes the change. This something is reflected in the
category of measure.
While the principle of negation says that every thing has its limits,
the principle of measure states that the limits of every thing
are determined by itself. This is crucial for the methodology
of science, since allows, for every scientific model, to express
the limits of its applicability in terms of that very model.
One does not need to explain how important the idea of measure is in
the arts: it is enough to indicate that, for an artist, the feeling
of measure is the principal criterion of achieving the desired result.
The principle of measure is a cornerstone of any philosophy, since
it is concerned with the very ability to express the infinite and
universal in finite and partial philosophies.
[Logic]
[Hierarchies]
[Unism & Philosophy]
[Unism]
[Main sections]
[Page index]
[Keyword index]
[Search]
[Contact information]
[Guestbook]
|