But if Jaffa allows Aristotle to get in his way, he nonetheless is able to offer some important elements to serve in interpreting Lincoln. He quotes from the Dred Scott speech as to Lincoln's perception of the Declaration's first self-evident truth, holding it to have meant that all have a right to equality, although his reference to the Peoria speech probably correctly seen to fit Lincoln's notion that an alteration of the incorporating moral principle of the Union dissolves it, includes a Lincoln aversion to the insistence he sees in Douglas of the paramount principle of self-interest as both a critique of Locke for whom man was motivated by such, and a divorce of the philosophy of the Declaration from at least such notions in such as Locke. It is clearly the case that Lincoln was willing to compromise, but unlike Douglas' compromise of 1854, such agreement had to be founded on a toleration of an accepted evil, slavery, and not acknowledgment that such was not an evil. If Lincoln was being a realist, this should not be viewed as the later sort of compromise. He was after all operating in a legal environment in which even a bill to prohibit interstate transport of slaves would not only have been held unconstitutional by the Taney court, but was beyond the scope of federal authority to even consider. There is probably too much in the Jaffa article to try to contend with within the scope of this inquiry, but two premises emerge clearly from his argument. Lincoln was unquestionably anti-slavery and his political economy underscores his every word and act. The former sentiments had to be tempered by the Constitutional realities of the moment, by the fallacy of the arguments (of Randall, of Douglas, and others of any natural limits of slavery. The latter are underscored by Lincoln's perception that the Constitution was the highest authority, which Jaffa acknowledges but does not take far enough. The article quotes Lincoln's assertion that a fundamental principle of the Declaration (and Constitution) was in "enterprise and industry to all." Jaffa does contend that without the obliteration of slavery, industry could have been constrained to labor intensive production, but he seems only to infer that Lincoln's attack on slavery was in reality an assault on labor intensive activity generally at the expense of capital intensive industry. There are two currents which run through Jaffa which can be examined further within the context of other literature. Strozier's QUEST FOR UNION and Fehrenbacher's PRELUDE TO GREATNESS offer somewhat parallel theses of Lincoln's strategy during the 1850's, and there is a segment of the commentary on Lincoln which relates to the religious character of Lincoln's speech, a theme repeatedly referenced by Jaffa. The initial comments on Lincoln as a paramount symbol in our national pantheon are indicative of the role he has assumed in what may be called our civil religion. But in addition to that, there is an obvious thread of religiousity that permeates the life, actions, and words of the man himself. Cobb and Elder produced a review of such symbols in 1973 in American Politics Quarterly. The argued that symbols need not be functional in terms of tangible costs or benefits and that their impact by be substantive in either systemic or diversely individual fashion that "defines major elements of a political culture." They further suggest that the degree of specification of any symbol and its affective character will cause it to range on a continuum which measures its impact on social solidarity (or differentiation). The inculcation of values associated with symbols probably develops as early in life as the second and certainly the third stage of Pioget's model of cognitive development. As such, they may essentially be a pre-consciousness function (as discussed here earlier). This may help to explain how it can be that a symbol such as Lincoln whose own position was a highly attenuated one in an extremely divisive system, and who represents at some rather unspecific level some tenets which are yet quite divisive in our culture, could achieve and hold as prominent a status in our national civil religion. (That does not dismiss casually the possibility that the ideas represented are so thoroughly interwoven with our tradition and institutions that they transcend even such divisions). Thomas Fleming has posed the possibility that Lincoln's success during his lifetime in achieving the position from which his stature as a symbol is derived is at least partially attributable to his: "... habit of wrapping up his policy in the idiom of Holy Scripture, concealing within the Trojan Horse of his gasconade and moral superiority an agenda that would never have been approved if presented in any other form." (58) That quote taken from M.E. Bradford is one further element of absurdity in that article, as Harry Jaffa was quick to point out in his response the following month (59). Jaffa, while he sees such absurdities in every generation since the Civil War, traces Fleming's and Bradford's position to a 1931 diatribe against Lincoln by Edgar Lee Masters (LINCOLN, THE MAN). The "relentlessly Biblical rhetoric" which Lincoln used to distinguish himself from others of the period according to Fleming was used to achieve "the subjugation of the South [which] had to be smeared over with religion" (Masters). That, of course, may explain Lincoln's extraordinary political success in the South in 1860! Strozier's reference to such rhetoric is of decidedly more friendly character (60). Jaffa's response is to detail evidence which probably should have been obvious, but just as obviously was mandated: "Now any one acquainted in the least with mid-Nineteenth century America, North and South, knows that the accents of the King James Bible were the common currency of political -- and indeed of familiar -- decisions. Lincoln's use of phrases drawn from the Bible was not the least unusual. What was unusual was the beauty and perfection of the language." (61) He offers a Southern speech base on the same Biblical passages as Lincoln's House Divided speech, but which is a thorough argument for not only slavery, but also racialism and white supremacy as a case in point. The speaker was Confederate Vice President Stephens in the aftermath of Ft. Sumpter. That speech goes even further, using the reference to argue that the Constitutional assumption of racial equality was in error. Lincoln himself, of course, repeatedly answered such assertions. That same 'problem' of Lincoln's political rhetoric appears to have also been a matter of concern for Don Fehrenbacher, but in that context it becomes quite a different kind of phenomenon, and while in his PRELUDE TO GREATNESS, Lincoln seems at times to descend to the level of consummate politico, there is at all times recognition that it is a principled politics that Lincoln is engaging in. Here, where Fleming saw Lincoln evading Douglas' questions in the debates, Fehrenbacher clearly establishes the opposite. In fact, Lincoln not only answers him but repeatedly poses questions to Douglas, over objection of his own supporters, that go unanswered, or as they are replied to, work to cripple Douglas and fragment the Democratic Party beyond 1858 (62). The foremost example of such strategic maneuvering by Lincoln results in the so-called Freeport Doctrine, a perhaps curious entitlement for what seems to be little more than the Taney court local energy mold for America. Hofstader alludes to Hearndon's portrayal of Lincoln as a political animal. His life was fully absorbed in his political being (63). He quotes Hearndon: "Politics was his life, newspapers his food, and his great ambition his motive power." (64) He goes on to describe Lincoln as no maverick, identifying him as "a firm orthodox Whig" (65) on every important issue, from the Bank, tariffs, the Mexican War and internal improvements, to the extension of slavery. The parallels cut deeply. The repeal of Missouri may have marked the demise of the Whigs, but it launched the GOP and reinvigorated Lincoln (66). And Lincoln took pains that he not be portrayed as a 'silk-stocking Whig' (67). He was clearly no Democrat, but could proceed from 'Jeffersonian' principle to support Hamilton's program, holding that the party of Jefferson had abandoned its principles in holding that one man's liberty was nothing when it conflicted with another's property (68). Especially Strozier (69) devotes some remarks to Lincoln's political rhetoric, including some commentary to his propensity to argue conspiracies. There is some inference that Lincoln was in such matters talking through his stove pipe hat. But 'conspiracy' is the stuff of politics and history. What, after all, is coalition-building? Stealth may or may not have anything to do with it. When those of common or mutual benefiting ends work together, they are 'conspiring.' Is Lincoln to be faulted for pointing out what everyone was aware of? There was a determined political effort largely centered around the Democratic Party to extend slavery, to restrict federal prerogatives, to accentuate state and local energy in economic matters, and the like. Lincoln represented quite an alternative position -- he might even be said to have conspired to promote it. Carey certainly did, in such causes as his Verspers circles. Lincoln was hardly as paranoid as Strozier seems to suggest (70). That same Confederate Vice President of earlier Fleming reference, while in the Senate and the Democratic Cabinets of the 1850's, undertook policy designed to limit American military capacity and decapitate movement toward a steamship industry in the United States -- efforts that clearly hurt the Union cause and made the Civil War bloodier, and which were not reversed until the war with such strategic defense initiatives as the Monitor projects. As Jaffa identified it, the assassins of Lincoln are, as they have been, busy people. A special emphasis should be placed on the fact that through all the debate as to interpretation of Lincoln, there is very little substantive reference or comment on 'Lincolnomics.' There is a controversy as to his position vis-à-vis Henry Clay of relevance to that. Fehrenbacher, for example, makes much of their connection while Strozier emphasizes Lincoln's opposition to his candidacy for the nomination in 1848. But any difference there had little to do with economics. With respect to 'Lincolnomics,' it is incredible that it seems to be of so little concern. It is here that the really important Lincoln emerges. Lincoln, the Great Emancipator, and Lincoln, the Preserver of the Union, are obviously important themes. Attempts to undermine such interpretations of Lincoln, whether in Woodward, Kelley, Fleming, or elsewhere, are totally inadequate. That fact, as much as anything else, may account for the continuation of these themes as central to popular conceptions of Mr. Lincoln, to return to the earlier caveat. What emerges as necessarily superior interpretation of Lincoln is analysis of him as both Emancipator and Preserver from his political economic perspective. He 'saved' the Union as much by his program of economic development as any other way. Similarly, emancipation was a blow against the labor intensive degradation of man. In this, he was very much cut in the mold of what is referred to as the American System of political economy of Franklin, Hamilton, Adams, Clay, Carey, Peshine Smith, and Raymond. It is in this regard that Lincoln transcends even the brightest interpretations in popular and scholarly evaluation. This is the essence of Lincoln and the substance of the apotheosis of Abraham Lincoln. A century after the North American Review referenced a renaissance of nationalism, the time is overdue for a further 'revision' of the popular and scholarly estimate of the central figure of that time, a revision which needs to focus on the essence of what renaissance and nationalism mean. It may be that "justice has been done to his patriotism, patience, and humanity" and that "only recently ,,, his intellectual capacity has been generally recognized and admitted .., " but there is to date still a great deficiency in our nation's interpretation and appreciation of Abraham Lincoln. While it has been suggested that Lincoln was a precursor of the 'modern' Presidency, and as such a sort of intermediary between Hamilton's 'energetic executive' and say, FDR, it should be emphasized that it is only the 'third' Roosevelt of the Arsenal of Democracy that comes close to cohering with Lincoln's political economy (though some aspects of the earlier FDRs do foreshadow that -- the TVA, for example, may, while most aspects of the New Deal do not). It does not suffice to say that it follows on the 'enlargement' of the office alone. Such an understanding of Lincoln does something else -- it raises some serious questions about the vision of the 'liberal' tradition in this country espoused by Louis Hartz. Too often this 'liberalism' is political jacobinism only and does not encompass the political economy necessary (as represented by Lincoln, et al). This deficiency to a great extent colors much of Hartz' analysis and renders much of his commentary wanting, whether he is talking about Lincoln, Hamilton, the Whigs or the Roosevelts. In Hartz, a jaded 'Americanism' replaces the American System, a point to which more will be addressed). How can it be that Hartz' Americanism finds Marx so alien when Lincoln's associates had far less trouble with him? That, of course, does not alter the failings of Marx so much as it exposes those of Hartz. Lincoln provides an important refinement on the 'born equal' argument (71) and the entire liberal absolutism perspective. Whatever Samuel Chase may have had in mind when he spoke of a 'third road' as a particular American prerogative in 1931 (72), the substantive essence of the Lincoln apotheosis suggests a great deal which Hartz' tradition passes over (though this is not to be confused with the 'third way' panned by Hayek or von Mises). At the very least, it is not enough to say, as Hartz does, that Lincoln 'democratizes' Hamilton's elitism (73). That not only fundamentally misreads Hamilton, but also constrains Lincoln. It leaves Hartz burdened by a poverty of economic perspective. That is not to argue economic determinism, but it does cast shadows across his analysis from Americanism to nationalism and the natural rights of man. It is undoubtedly the case that Lincoln's popular apotheosis in no way is attributable to anything close to these levels of consideration of his policy and philosophy, and yet, there may indeed be an absolute ethos embedded in Lincoln. It may also be the absolute moral ethos of the American people. And it may be in this conjunction that Lincoln has come to hold such a paramount position in our culture, in that he embodies the American Spirit, and does so in a manner which we recognize, though not in a reductionist fashion. But it is not one that is uniquely American either, and in this sense probably can best explain not only why our Revolution is exportable but also why what occurred at Lexington were indeed 'shots heard 'round the world.' In the Civil War as in the Revolution, the science of political economy and government was at issue and at stake. The extreme measures which Lincoln had to undertake were absolutely mandatory in that fight. The nation, as expressed in those ideas, was under assault, as it always had been. And if the measures seem extreme, they were dedicated to and based in the spirit that Franklin and Hamilton and Madison breathed into the Constitution -- an act of re-creation that marks man's existence in the image of the Creator who breathed that creative spirit into humanity. Karl Walling of the Air Force Academy has commented on this deliberate structuring in the presentation of his paper Republican Empire delivered at the Chicago Conference of the American Political Science Association on September 1, 1995. He depicts a Hamilton determined to structure the economy of scale 'empire' with the requisite 'public strength' instilled in the federal authority to hold it together in order to acheive 'individual security.' His case not only presents a Hamilton more similar to the one portrayed here, but one determined to establish the legal order toward securing that structuring. But he connects all this to the conception of civil religion which Hamilton developed out of Plutarch: "Hamilton was particularly impressed with the 'empire of the mind' of the Romans which Numa acquired through the political use of religion. However temporarily, Numa civilized the Romans by turning their thoughts from war to peace and indolence to industry. Namu's example gave Hamilton a lifelong respect for the political influences of religion, especially when passions of religious veneration can be associated with the constitutional rule of law. It also convinced him that no government could endure unless it possessed a similar kind of empire over the hearts and minds of its citizens." (74) Continue 1